CHAPTER I
THAT MEN BY VARIOUS WAYS ARRIVE AT THE SAME END.
CHAPTER II
OF SORROW
CHAPTER III
THAT OUR AFFECTIONS CARRY THEMSELVES BEYOND US
CHAPTER IV
THAT THE SOUL EXPENDS ITS PASSIONS UPON FALSE OBJECTS
CHAPTER V
WHETHER THE GOVERNOR HIMSELF GO OUT TO PARLEY
CHAPTER VI
THAT THE HOUR OF PARLEY DANGEROUS
CHAPTER VII
THAT THE INTENTION IS JUDGE OF OUR ACTIONS
CHAPTER VIII
OF IDLENESS
CHAPTER IX
OF LIARS
CHAPTER X
OF QUICK OR SLOW SPEECH
CHAPTER XI
OF PROGNOSTICATIONS
CHAPTER XII
OF CONSTANCY
CHAPTER XIII
THE CEREMONY OF THE INTERVIEW OF PRINCES
CHAPTER XIV
THAT MEN ARE JUSTLY PUNISHED FOR BEING OBSTINATE
CHAPTER XV
OF THE PUNISHMENT OF COWARDICE
CHAPTER XVI
A PROCEEDING OF SOME AMBASSADORS
CHAPTER XVII
OF FEAR
CHAPTER XVIII
NOT TO JUDGE OF OUR HAPPINESS TILL AFTER DEATH.
CHAPTER XIX
THAT TO STUDY PHILOSOPY IS TO LEARN TO DIE
CHAPTER XX
OF THE FORCE OF IMAGINATION
CHAPTER XXI
THAT THE PROFIT OF ONE MAN IS THE DAMAGE OF ANOTHER
CHAPTER XXII
OF CUSTOM; WE SHOULD NOT EASILY CHANGE A LAW RECEIVED
CHAPTER XXIII
VARIOUS EVENTS FROM THE SAME COUNSEL
CHAPTER XXIV
OF PEDANTRY
CHAPTER XXV
OF THE EDUCATION OF CHILDREN
CHAPTER XXVI
FOLLY TO MEASURE TRUTH AND ERROR BY OUR OWN CAPACITY
CHAPTER XXVII
OF FRIENDSHIP
CHAPTER XXVIII
NINE AND TWENTY SONNETS OF ESTIENNE DE LA BOITIE
CHAPTER XXIX
OF MODERATION
CHAPTER XXX
OF CANNIBALS
CHAPTER XXXI
THAT A MAN IS SOBERLY TO JUDGE OF THE DIVINE ORDINANCES
CHAPTER XXXII
WE ARE TO AVOID PLEASURES, EVEN AT THE EXPENSE OF LIFE
CHAPTER XXXIII
FORTUNE IS OFTEN OBSERVED TO ACT BY THE RULE OF REASON
CHAPTER XXXIV
OF ONE DEFECT IN OUR GOVERNMENT
CHAPTER XXXV
OF THE CUSTOM OF WEARING CLOTHES
CHAPTER XXXVI
OF CATO THE YOUNGER
CHAPTER XXXVII
THAT WE LAUGH AND CRY FOR THE SAME THING
CHAPTER XXXVIII
OF SOLITUDE
CHAPTER XXXIX
A CONSIDERATION UPON CICERO
CHAPTER XL
RELISH FOR GOOD AND EVIL DEPENDS UPON OUR OPINION
CHAPTER XLI
NOT TO COMMUNICATE A MAN'S HONOUR
CHAPTER XLII
OF THE INEQUALITY AMOUNGST US.
CHAPTER XLIII
OF SUMPTUARY LAWS
CHAPTER XLIV
OF SLEEP
CHAPTER XLV
OF THE BATTLE OF DREUX
CHAPTER XLVI
OF NAMES
CHAPTER XLVII
OF THE UNCERTAINTY OF OUR JUDGMENT
CHAPTER XLVIII
OF WAR HORSES, OR DESTRIERS
CHAPTER XLIX
OF ANCIENT CUSTOMS
CHAPTER L
OF DEMOCRITUS AND HERACLITUS
CHAPTER LI
OF THE VANITY OF WORDS
CHAPTER LII
OF THE PARSIMONY OF THE ANCIENTS
CHAPTER LIII
OF A SAYING OF CAESAR
CHAPTER LIV
OF VAIN SUBTLETIES
CHAPTER LV
OF SMELLS
CHAPTER LVI
OF PRAYERS
CHAPTER LVII
OF AGE
BOOK THE FIRST
CHAPTER I—THAT MEN BY VARIOUS WAYS ARRIVE AT THE SAME END.
The most usual way of appeasing the indignation of such as we have
any way offended, when we see them in possession of the power of
revenge, and find that we absolutely lie at their mercy, is by
submission, to move them to commiseration and pity; and yet bravery,
constancy, and resolution, however quite contrary means, have sometimes
served to produce the same effect.—[Florio's version begins thus: "The
most vsuall waie to appease those minds wee have offended, when revenge
lies in their hands, and that we stand at their mercie, is by submission
to move them to commiseration and pity: Nevertheless, courage,
constancie, and resolution (means altogether opposite) have sometimes
wrought the same effect."—] [The spelling is Florio's D.W.]
Edward, Prince of Wales [Edward, the Black Prince. D.W.] (the same
who so long governed our Guienne, a personage whose condition and
fortune have in them a great deal of the most notable and most
considerable parts of grandeur), having been highly incensed by the
Limousins, and taking their city by assault, was not, either by the
cries of the people, or the prayers and tears of the women and children,
abandoned to slaughter and prostrate at his feet for mercy, to be stayed
from prosecuting his revenge; till, penetrating further into the town,
he at last took notice of three French gentlemen,—[These were Jean de
Villemure, Hugh de la Roche, and Roger de Beaufort.—Froissart, i. c.
289. {The city was Limoges. D.W.}]—who with incredible bravery alone
sustained the power of his victorious army. Then it was that
consideration and respect unto so remarkable a valour first stopped the
torrent of his fury, and that his clemency, beginning with these three
cavaliers, was afterwards extended to all the remaining inhabitants of
the city.
Scanderbeg, Prince of Epirus, pursuing one of his soldiers with
purpose to kill him, the soldier, having in vain tried by all the ways
of humility and supplication to appease him, resolved, as his last
refuge, to face about and await him sword in hand: which behaviour of
his gave a sudden stop to his captain's fury, who, for seeing him assume
so notable a resolution, received him into grace; an example, however,
that might suffer another interpretation with such as have not read of
the prodigious force and valour of that prince.
The Emperor Conrad III. having besieged Guelph, Duke of Bavaria,—[In
1140, in Weinsberg, Upper Bavaria.]—would not be prevailed upon, what
mean and unmanly satisfactions soever were tendered to him, to
condescend to milder conditions than that the ladies and gentlewomen
only who were in the town with the duke might go out without violation
of their honour, on foot, and with so much only as they could carry
about them. Whereupon they, out of magnanimity of heart, presently
contrived to carry out, upon their shoulders, their husbands and
children, and the duke himself; a sight at which the emperor was so
pleased, that, ravished with the generosity of the action, he wept for
joy, and immediately extinguishing in his heart the mortal and capital
hatred he had conceived against this duke, he from that time forward
treated him and his with all humanity. The one and the other of these
two ways would with great facility work upon my nature; for I have a
marvellous propensity to mercy and mildness, and to such a degree that I
fancy of the two I should sooner surrender my anger to compassion than
to esteem. And yet pity is reputed a vice amongst the Stoics, who will
that we succour the afflicted, but not that we should be so affected
with their sufferings as to suffer with them. I conceived these examples
not ill suited to the question in hand, and the rather because therein
we observe these great souls assaulted and tried by these two several
ways, to resist the one without relenting, and to be shook and subjected
by the other. It may be true that to suffer a man's heart to be totally
subdued by compassion may be imputed to facility, effeminacy, and
over-tenderness; whence it comes to pass that the weaker natures, as of
women, children, and the common sort of people, are the most subject to
it but after having resisted and disdained the power of groans and
tears, to yield to the sole reverence of the sacred image of Valour,
this can be no other than the effect of a strong and inflexible soul
enamoured of and honouring masculine and obstinate courage.
Nevertheless, astonishment and admiration may, in less generous minds,
beget a like effect: witness the people of Thebes, who, having put two
of their generals upon trial for their lives for having continued in
arms beyond the precise term of their commission, very hardly pardoned
Pelopidas, who, bowing under the weight of so dangerous an accusation,
made no manner of defence for himself, nor produced other arguments than
prayers and supplications; whereas, on the contrary, Epaminondas,
falling to recount magniloquently the exploits he had performed in their
service, and, after a haughty and arrogant manner reproaching them with
ingratitude and injustice, they had not the heart to proceed any further
in his trial, but broke up the court and departed, the whole assembly
highly commending the high courage of this personage.—[Plutarch, How far
a Man may praise Himself, c. 5.]
Dionysius the elder, after having, by a tedious siege and through
exceeding great difficulties, taken the city of Reggio, and in it the
governor Phyton, a very gallant man, who had made so obstinate a
defence, was resolved to make him a tragical example of his revenge: in
order whereunto he first told him, "That he had the day before caused
his son and all his kindred to be drowned." To which Phyton returned no
other answer but this: "That they were then by one day happier than he."
After which, causing him to be stripped, and delivering him into the
hands of the tormentors, he was by them not only dragged through the
streets of the town, and most ignominiously and cruelly whipped, but
moreover vilified with most bitter and contumelious language: yet still
he maintained his courage entire all the way, with a strong voice and
undaunted countenance proclaiming the honourable and glorious cause of
his death; namely, for that he would not deliver up his country into the
hands of a tyrant; at the same time denouncing against him a speedy
chastisement from the offended gods. At which Dionysius, reading in his
soldiers' looks, that instead of being incensed at the haughty language
of this conquered enemy, to the contempt of their captain and his
triumph, they were not only struck with admiration of so rare a virtue,
but moreover inclined to mutiny, and were even ready to rescue the
prisoner out of the hangman's hands, he caused the torturing to cease,
and afterwards privately caused him to be thrown into the sea.—[Diod.
Sic., xiv. 29.]
Man (in good earnest) is a marvellous vain, fickle, and unstable
subject, and on whom it is very hard to form any certain and uniform
judgment. For Pompey could pardon the whole city of the Mamertines,
though furiously incensed against it, upon the single account of the
virtue and magnanimity of one citizen, Zeno,—[Plutarch calls him Stheno,
and also Sthemnus and Sthenis]—who took the fault of the public wholly
upon himself; neither entreated other favour, but alone to undergo the
punishment for all: and yet Sylla's host, having in the city of Perugia
—[Plutarch says Preneste, a town of Latium.]—manifested the same virtue,
obtained nothing by it, either for himself or his fellow-citizens.
And, directly contrary to my first examples, the bravest of all men,
and who was reputed so gracious to all those he overcame, Alexander,
having, after many great difficulties, forced the city of Gaza, and,
entering, found Betis, who commanded there, and of whose valour in the
time of this siege he had most marvellous manifest proof, alone,
forsaken by all his soldiers, his armour hacked and hewed to pieces,
covered all over with blood and wounds, and yet still fighting in the
crowd of a number of Macedonians, who were laying on him on all sides,
he said to him, nettled at so dear-bought a victory (for, in addition to
the other damage, he had two wounds newly received in his own person),
"Thou shalt not die, Betis, as thou dost intend; be sure thou shall
suffer all the torments that can be inflicted on a captive." To which
menace the other returning no other answer, but only a fierce and
disdainful look; "What," says Alexander, observing his haughty and
obstinate silence, "is he too stiff to bend a knee! Is he too proud to
utter one suppliant word! Truly, I will conquer this silence; and if I
cannot force a word from his mouth, I will, at least, extract a groan
from his heart." And thereupon converting his anger into fury, presently
commanded his heels to be bored through, causing him, alive, to be
dragged, mangled, and dismembered at a cart's tail.—[Quintus Curtius,
iv. 6. This act of cruelty has been doubted, notwithstanding the
statement of Curtius.]—Was it that the height of courage was so natural
and familiar to this conqueror, that because he could not admire, he
respected it the less? Or was it that he conceived valour to be a virtue
so peculiar to himself, that his pride could not, without envy, endure
it in another? Or was it that the natural impetuosity of his fury was
incapable of opposition? Certainly, had it been capable of moderation,
it is to be believed that in the sack and desolation of Thebes, to see
so many valiant men, lost and totally destitute of any further defence,
cruelly massacred before his eyes, would have appeased it: where there
were above six thousand put to the sword, of whom not one was seen to
fly, or heard to cry out for quarter; but, on the contrary, every one
running here and there to seek out and to provoke the victorious enemy
to help them to an honourable end. Not one was seen who, however
weakened with wounds, did not in his last gasp yet endeavour to revenge
himself, and with all the arms of a brave despair, to sweeten his own
death in the death of an enemy. Yet did their valour create no pity, and
the length of one day was not enough to satiate the thirst of the
conqueror's revenge, but the slaughter continued to the last drop of
blood that was capable of being shed, and stopped not till it met with
none but unarmed persons, old men, women, and children, of them to carry
away to the number of thirty thousand slaves.
CHAPTER II—OF SORROW
No man living is more free from this passion than I, who yet neither
like it in myself nor admire it in others, and yet generally the world,
as a settled thing, is pleased to grace it with a particular esteem,
clothing therewith wisdom, virtue, and conscience. Foolish and sordid
guise! —["No man is more free from this passion than I, for I neither
love nor regard it: albeit the world hath undertaken, as it were upon
covenant, to grace it with a particular favour. Therewith they adorne
age, vertue, and conscience. Oh foolish and base ornament!" Florio,
1613, p. 3] —The Italians have more fitly baptized by this name—[La
tristezza]— malignity; for 'tis a quality always hurtful, always idle
and vain; and as being cowardly, mean, and base, it is by the Stoics
expressly and particularly forbidden to their sages.
But the story—[Herodotus, iii. 14.]—says that Psammenitus, King of
Egypt, being defeated and taken prisoner by Cambyses, King of Persia,
seeing his own daughter pass by him as prisoner, and in a wretched
habit, with a bucket to draw water, though his friends about him were so
concerned as to break out into tears and lamentations, yet he himself
remained unmoved, without uttering a word, his eyes fixed upon the
ground; and seeing, moreover, his son immediately after led to
execution, still maintained the same countenance; till spying at last
one of his domestic and familiar friends dragged away amongst the
captives, he fell to tearing his hair and beating his breast, with all
the other extravagances of extreme sorrow.
A story that may very fitly be coupled with another of the same kind,
of recent date, of a prince of our own nation, who being at Trent, and
having news there brought him of the death of his elder brother, a
brother on whom depended the whole support and honour of his house, and
soon after of that of a younger brother, the second hope of his family,
and having withstood these two assaults with an exemplary resolution;
one of his servants happening a few days after to die, he suffered his
constancy to be overcome by this last accident; and, parting with his
courage, so abandoned himself to sorrow and mourning, that some thence
were forward to conclude that he was only touched to the quick by this
last stroke of fortune; but, in truth, it was, that being before brimful
of grief, the least addition overflowed the bounds of all patience.
Which, I think, might also be said of the former example, did not the
story proceed to tell us that Cambyses asking Psammenitus, "Why, not
being moved at the calamity of his son and daughter, he should with so
great impatience bear the misfortune of his friend?" "It is," answered
he, "because only this last affliction was to be manifested by tears,
the two first far exceeding all manner of expression."
And, peradventure, something like this might be working in the fancy
of the ancient painter,—[Cicero, De Orator., c. 22 ; Pliny, xxxv. 10.]—
who having, in the sacrifice of Iphigenia, to represent the sorrow of
the assistants proportionably to the several degrees of interest every
one had in the death of this fair innocent virgin, and having, in the
other figures, laid out the utmost power of his art, when he came to
that of her father, he drew him with a veil over his face, meaning
thereby that no kind of countenance was capable of expressing such a
degree of sorrow. Which is also the reason why the poets feign the
miserable mother, Niobe, having first lost seven sons, and then
afterwards as many daughters (overwhelmed with her losses), to have been
at last transformed into a rock—
"Diriguisse malis,"
["Petrified with her misfortunes."—Ovid, Met., vi. 304.]
thereby to express that melancholic, dumb, and deaf stupefaction,
which benumbs all our faculties, when oppressed with accidents greater
than we are able to bear. And, indeed, the violence and impression of an
excessive grief must of necessity astonish the soul, and wholly deprive
her of her ordinary functions: as it happens to every one of us, who,
upon any sudden alarm of very ill news, find ourselves surprised,
stupefied, and in a manner deprived of all power of motion, so that the
soul, beginning to vent itself in tears and lamentations, seems to free
and disengage itself from the sudden oppression, and to have obtained
some room to work itself out at greater liberty.
"Et via vix tandem voci laxata dolore est."
["And at length and with difficulty is a passage opened by grief for
utterance."—AEneid, xi. 151.]
In the war that Ferdinand made upon the widow of King John of
Hungary, about Buda, a man-at-arms was particularly taken notice of by
every one for his singular gallant behaviour in a certain encounter;
and, unknown, highly commended, and lamented, being left dead upon the
place: but by none so much as by Raisciac, a German lord, who was
infinitely enamoured of so rare a valour. The body being brought off,
and the count, with the common curiosity coming to view it, the armour
was no sooner taken off but he immediately knew him to be his own son, a
thing that added a second blow to the compassion of all the beholders;
only he, without uttering a word, or turning away his eyes from the
woeful object, stood fixedly contemplating the body of his son, till the
vehemency of sorrow having overcome his vital spirits, made him sink
down stone-dead to the ground.
"Chi puo dir com' egli arde, a in picciol fuoco,"
["He who can say how he burns with love, has little fire"
—Petrarca, Sonetto 137.]
say the Innamoratos, when they would represent an 'insupportable
passion.
"Misero quod omneis
Eripit sensus mihi: nam simul te,
Lesbia, aspexi, nihil est super mi,
Quod loquar amens.
Lingua sed torpet: tenuis sub artus
Flamma dimanat; sonitu suopte
Tintinant aures; gemina teguntur
Lumina nocte."
["Love deprives me of all my faculties: Lesbia, when once in thy
presence, I have not left the power to tell my distracting passion:
my tongue becomes torpid; a subtle flame creeps through my veins; my
ears tingle in deafness; my eyes are veiled with darkness."
Catullus, Epig. li. 5]
Neither is it in the height and greatest fury of the fit that we are
in a condition to pour out our complaints or our amorous persuasions,
the soul being at that time over-burdened, and labouring with profound
thoughts; and the body dejected and languishing with desire; and thence
it is that sometimes proceed those accidental impotencies that so
unseasonably surprise the lover, and that frigidity which by the force
of an immoderate ardour seizes him even in the very lap of fruition.
—[The edition of 1588 has here, "An accident not unknown to myself."]—
For all passions that suffer themselves to be relished and digested are
but moderate:
"Curae leves loquuntur, ingentes stupent."
["Light griefs can speak: deep sorrows are dumb."
—Seneca, Hippolytus, act ii. scene 3.]
A surprise of unexpected joy does likewise often produce the same
effect:
"Ut me conspexit venientem, et Troja circum
Arma amens vidit, magnis exterrita monstris,
Diriguit visu in medio, calor ossa reliquit,
Labitur, et longo vix tandem tempore fatur."
["When she beheld me advancing, and saw, with stupefaction, the
Trojan arms around me, terrified with so great a prodigy, she
fainted away at the very sight: vital warmth forsook her limbs: she
sinks down, and, after a long interval, with difficulty speaks."—
AEneid, iii. 306.]
Besides the examples of the Roman lady, who died for joy to see her
son safe returned from the defeat of Cannae; and of Sophocles and of
Dionysius the Tyrant,—[Pliny, vii. 53. Diodorus Siculus, however (xv. c.
20), tells us that Dionysius "was so overjoyed at the news that he made
a great sacrifice upon it to the gods, prepared sumptuous feasts, to
which he invited all his friends, and therein drank so excessively that
it threw him into a very bad distemper."]—who died of joy; and of
Thalna, who died in Corsica, reading news of the honours the Roman
Senate had decreed in his favour, we have, moreover, one in our time, of
Pope Leo X., who upon news of the taking of Milan, a thing he had so
ardently desired, was rapt with so sudden an excess of joy that he
immediately fell into a fever and died.—[Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia,
vol. xiv.]—And for a more notable testimony of the imbecility of human
nature, it is recorded by the ancients—[Pliny, 'ut supra']—that Diodorus
the dialectician died upon the spot, out of an extreme passion of shame,
for not having been able in his own school, and in the presence of a
great auditory, to disengage himself from a nice argument that was
propounded to him. I, for my part, am very little subject to these
violent passions; I am naturally of a stubborn apprehension, which also,
by reasoning, I every day harden and fortify.
CHAPTER III—THAT OUR AFFECTIONS CARRY THEMSELVES BEYOND US.
Such as accuse mankind of the folly of gaping after future things,
and advise us to make our benefit of those which are present, and to set
up our rest upon them, as having no grasp upon that which is to come,
even less than that which we have upon what is past, have hit upon the
most universal of human errors, if that may be called an error to which
nature herself has disposed us, in order to the continuation of her own
work, prepossessing us, amongst several others, with this deceiving
imagination, as being more jealous of our action than afraid of our
knowledge.
We are never present with, but always beyond ourselves: fear, desire,
hope, still push us on towards the future, depriving us, in the
meantime, of the sense and consideration of that which is to amuse us
with the thought of what shall be, even when we shall be no
more.—[Rousseau, Emile, livre ii.]
"Calamitosus est animus futuri auxius."
["The mind anxious about the future is unhappy."
—Seneca, Epist., 98.]
We find this great precept often repeated in Plato, "Do thine own
work, and know thyself." Of which two parts, both the one and the other
generally, comprehend our whole duty, and do each of them in like manner
involve the other; for who will do his own work aright will find that
his first lesson is to know what he is, and that which is proper to
himself; and who rightly understands himself will never mistake another
man's work for his own, but will love and improve himself above all
other things, will refuse superfluous employments, and reject all
unprofitable thoughts and propositions. As folly, on the one side,
though it should enjoy all it desire, would notwithstanding never be
content, so, on the other, wisdom, acquiescing in the present, is never
dissatisfied with itself. —[Cicero, Tusc. Quae., 57, v. 18.]—Epicurus
dispenses his sages from all foresight and care of the future.
Amongst those laws that relate to the dead, I look upon that to be
very sound by which the actions of princes are to be examined after
their decease.—[Diodorus Siculus, i. 6.]— They are equals with, if not
masters of the laws, and, therefore, what justice could not inflict upon
their persons, 'tis but reason should be executed upon their reputations
and the estates of their successors—things that we often value above
life itself. 'Tis a custom of singular advantage to those countries
where it is in use, and by all good princes to be desired, who have
reason to take it ill, that the memories of the wicked should be used
with the same reverence and respect with their own. We owe subjection
and obedience to all our kings, whether good or bad, alike, for that has
respect unto their office; but as to esteem and affection, these are
only due to their virtue. Let us grant to political government to endure
them with patience, however unworthy; to conceal their vices; and to
assist them with our recommendation in their indifferent actions, whilst
their authority stands in need of our support. But, the relation of
prince and subject being once at an end, there is no reason we should
deny the expression of our real opinions to our own liberty and common
justice, and especially to interdict to good subjects the glory of
having reverently and faithfully served a prince, whose imperfections
were to them so well known; this were to deprive posterity of a useful
example. And such as, out of respect to some private obligation,
unjustly espouse and vindicate the memory of a faulty prince, do private
right at the expense of public justice. Livy does very truly say,—[xxxv.
48.]— "That the language of men bred up in courts is always full of vain
ostentation and false testimony, every one indifferently magnifying his
own master, and stretching his commendation to the utmost extent of
virtue and sovereign grandeur." Some may condemn the freedom of those
two soldiers who so roundly answered Nero to his beard; the one being
asked by him why he bore him ill-will? "I loved thee," answered he,
"whilst thou wert worthy of it, but since thou art become a parricide,
an incendiary, a player, and a coachman, I hate thee as thou dost
deserve." And the other, why he should attempt to kill him? "Because,"
said he, "I could think of no other remedy against thy perpetual
mischiefs." —[Tacitus, Annal., xv. 67.]—But the public and universal
testimonies that were given of him after his death (and so will be to
all posterity, both of him and all other wicked princes like him), of
his tyrannies and abominable deportment, who, of a sound judgment, can
reprove them?
I am scandalised, that in so sacred a government as that of the
Lacedaemonians there should be mixed so hypocritical a ceremony at the
interment of their kings; where all their confederates and neighbours,
and all sorts and degrees of men and women, as well as their slaves, cut
and slashed their foreheads in token of sorrow, repeating in their cries
and lamentations that that king (let him have been as wicked as the
devil) was the best that ever they had;—[Herodotus, vi. 68.]—by this
means attributing to his quality the praise that only belongs to merit,
and that of right is due to supreme desert, though lodged in the lowest
and most inferior subject.
Aristotle, who will still have a hand in everything, makes a 'quaere'
upon the saying of Solon, that none can be said to be happy until he is
dead: "whether, then, he who has lived and died according to his heart's
desire, if he have left an ill repute behind him, and that his posterity
be miserable, can be said to be happy?" Whilst we have life and motion,
we convey ourselves by fancy and preoccupation, whither and to what we
please; but once out of being, we have no more any manner of
communication with that which is, and it had therefore been better said
by Solon that man is never happy, because never so, till he is no more.
"Quisquam
Vix radicitus e vita se tollit, et eicit;
Sed facit esse sui quiddam super inscius ipse,
Nec removet satis a projecto corpore sese, et
Vindicat."
["Scarcely one man can, even in dying, wholly detach himself from
the idea of life; in his ignorance he must needs imagine that there
is in him something that survives him, and cannot sufficiently
separate or emancipate himself from his remains"
—Lucretius, iii. 890.]
Bertrand de Guesclin, dying at the siege of the Castle of Rancon,
near unto Puy, in Auvergne, the besieged were afterwards, upon
surrender, enjoined to lay down the keys of the place upon the corpse of
the dead general. Bartolommeo d'Alviano, the Venetian General, happening
to die in the service of the Republic in Brescia, and his corpse being
to be carried through the territory of Verona, an enemy's country, most
of the army were inclined to demand safe-conduct from the Veronese; but
Theodoro Trivulzio opposed the motion, rather choosing to make his way
by force of arms, and to run the hazard of a battle, saying it was by no
means fit that he who in his life was never afraid of his enemies should
seem to apprehend them when he was dead. In truth, in affairs of the
same nature, by the Greek laws, he who made suit to an enemy for a body
to give it burial renounced his victory, and had no more right to erect
a trophy, and he to whom such suit was made was reputed victor. By this
means it was that Nicias lost the advantage he had visibly obtained over
the Corinthians, and that Agesilaus, on the contrary, assured that which
he had before very doubtfully gained over the Boeotians.—[Plutarch, Life
of Nicias, c. ii.; Life of Agesilaus, c. vi.]
These things might appear strange, had it not been a general practice
in all ages not only to extend the concern of ourselves beyond this
life, but, moreover, to fancy that the favour of Heaven does not only
very often accompany us to the grave, but has also, even after life, a
concern for our ashes. Of which there are so many ancient examples (to
say nothing of those of our own observation), that it is not necessary I
should longer insist upon it. Edward I., King of England, having in the
long wars betwixt him and Robert, King of Scotland, had experience of
how great importance his own immediate presence was to the success of
his affairs, having ever been victorious in whatever he undertook in his
own person, when he came to die, bound his son in a solemn oath that, so
soon as he should be dead he should boil his body till the flesh parted
from the bones, and bury the flesh, reserving the bones to carry
continually with him in his army, so often as he should be obliged to go
against the Scots, as if destiny had inevitably attached victory, even
to his remains. John Zisca, the same who, to vindication of Wicliffe's
heresies, troubled the Bohemian state, left order that they should flay
him after his death, and of his skin make a drum to carry in the war
against his enemies, fancying it would contribute to the continuation of
the successes he had always obtained in the wars against them. In like
manner certain of the Indians, in their battles with the Spaniards,
carried with them the bones of one of their captains, in consideration
of the victories they had formerly obtained under his conduct. And other
people of the same New World carry about with them, in their wars, the
relics of valiant men who have died in battle, to incite their courage
and advance their fortune. Of which examples the first reserve nothing
for the tomb but the reputation they have acquired by their former
achievements, but these attribute to them a certain present and active
power.
The proceeding of Captain Bayard is of a better composition, who
finding himself wounded to death with an harquebuss shot, and being
importuned to retire out of the fight, made answer that he would not
begin at the last gasp to turn his back to the enemy, and accordingly
still fought on, till feeling himself too faint and no longer able to
sit on his horse, he commanded his steward to set him down at the foot
of a tree, but so that he might die with his face towards the enemy,
which he did.
I must yet add another example, equally remarkable for the present
consideration with any of the former. The Emperor Maximilian,
great-grandfather to the now King Philip,—[Philip II. of Spain.]—was a
prince endowed throughout with great and extraordinary qualities, and
amongst the rest with a singular beauty of person, but had withal a
humour very contrary to that of other princes, who for the despatch of
their most important affairs convert their close-stool into a chair of
State, which was, that he would never permit any of his bedchamber, how
familiar soever, to see him in that posture, and would steal aside to
make water as religiously as a virgin, shy to discover to his physician
or any other whomsoever those parts that we are accustomed to conceal. I
myself, who have so impudent a way of talking, am, nevertheless,
naturally so modest this way, that unless at the importunity of
necessity or pleasure, I scarcely ever communicate to the sight of any
either those parts or actions that custom orders us to conceal, wherein
I suffer more constraint than I conceive is very well becoming a man,
especially of my profession. But he nourished this modest humour to such
a degree of superstition as to give express orders in his last will that
they should put him on drawers so soon as he should be dead; to which,
methinks, he would have done well to have added that he should be
blindfolded, too, that put them on. The charge that Cyrus left with his
children, that neither they, nor any other, should either see or touch
his body after the soul was departed from it,—[Xenophon, Cyropedia,
viii. 7.]—I attribute to some superstitious devotion of his; for both
his historian and himself, amongst their great qualities, marked the
whole course of their lives with a singular respect and reverence to
religion.
I was by no means pleased with a story, told me by a man of very
great quality of a relation of mine, and one who had given a very good
account of himself both in peace and war, that, coming to die in a very
old age, of excessive pain of the stone, he spent the last hours of his
life in an extraordinary solicitude about ordering the honour and
ceremony of his funeral, pressing all the men of condition who came to
see him to engage their word to attend him to his grave: importuning
this very prince, who came to visit him at his last gasp, with a most
earnest supplication that he would order his family to be there, and
presenting before him several reasons and examples to prove that it was
a respect due to a man of his condition; and seemed to die content,
having obtained this promise, and appointed the method and order of his
funeral parade. I have seldom heard of so persistent a vanity.
Another, though contrary curiosity (of which singularity, also, I do
not want domestic example), seems to be somewhat akin to this, that a
man shall cudgel his brains at the last moments of his life to contrive
his obsequies to so particular and unusual a parsimony as of one servant
with a lantern, I see this humour commended, and the appointment of
Marcus. Emilius Lepidus, who forbade his heirs to bestow upon his hearse
even the common ceremonies in use upon such occasions. Is it yet
temperance and frugality to avoid expense and pleasure of which the use
and knowledge are imperceptible to us? See, here, an easy and cheap
reformation. If instruction were at all necessary in this case, I should
be of opinion that in this, as in all other actions of life, each person
should regulate the matter according to his fortune; and the philosopher
Lycon prudently ordered his friends to dispose of his body where they
should think most fit, and as to his funeral, to order it neither too
superfluous nor too mean. For my part, I should wholly refer the
ordering of this ceremony to custom, and shall, when the time comes,
accordingly leave it to their discretion to whose lot it shall fall to
do me that last office. "Totus hic locus est contemnendus in nobis, non
negligendus in nostris;"—["The place of our sepulture is to be contemned
by us, but not to be neglected by our friends."—Cicero, Tusc. i. 45.]—
and it was a holy saying of a saint, "Curatio funeris, conditio
sepultura: pompa exequiarum, magis sunt vivorum solatia, quam subsidia
mortuorum."—["The care of death, the place of sepulture, the pomps of
obsequies, are rather consolations to the living than succours to the
dead." August. De Civit. Dei, i. 12.]—Which made Socrates answer Crito,
who, at death, asked him how he would be buried: "How you will," said
he. "If I were to concern myself beyond the present about this affair, I
should be most tempted, as the greatest satisfaction of this kind, to
imitate those who in their lifetime entertain themselves with the
ceremony and honours of their own obsequies beforehand, and are pleased
with beholding their own dead countenance in marble. Happy are they who
can gratify their senses by insensibility, and live by their death!"
I am ready to conceive an implacable hatred against all popular
domination, though I think it the most natural and equitable of all, so
oft as I call to mind the inhuman injustice of the people of Athens,
who, without remission, or once vouchsafing to hear what they had to say
for themselves, put to death their brave captains newly returned
triumphant from a naval victory they had obtained over the
Lacedaemonians near the Arginusian Isles, the most bloody and obstinate
engagement that ever the Greeks fought at sea; because (after the
victory) they followed up the blow and pursued the advantages presented
to them by the rule of war, rather than stay to gather up and bury their
dead. And the execution is yet rendered more odious by the behaviour of
Diomedon, who, being one of the condemned, and a man of most eminent
virtue, political and military, after having heard the sentence,
advancing to speak, no audience till then having been allowed, instead
of laying before them his own cause, or the impiety of so cruel a
sentence, only expressed a solicitude for his judges' preservation,
beseeching the gods to convert this sentence to their good, and praying
that, for neglecting to fulfil the vows which he and his companions had
made (with which he also acquainted them) in acknowledgment of so
glorious a success, they might not draw down the indignation of the gods
upon them; and so without more words went courageously to his death.
Fortune, a few years after, punished them in the same kind; for
Chabrias, captain-general of their naval forces, having got the better
of Pollis, Admiral of Sparta, at the Isle of Naxos, totally lost the
fruits of his victory, one of very great importance to their affairs, in
order not to incur the danger of this example, and so that he should not
lose a few bodies of his dead friends that were floating in the sea,
gave opportunity to a world of living enemies to sail away in safety,
who afterwards made them pay dear for this unseasonable superstition:—
"Quaeris, quo jaceas, post obitum, loco?
Quo non nata jacent."
["Dost ask where thou shalt lie after death?
Where things not born lie, that never being had."]
Seneca, Tyoa. Choro ii. 30.
This other restores the sense of repose to a body without a soul:
"Neque sepulcrum, quo recipiatur, habeat: portum corporis, ubi,
remissa human, vita, corpus requiescat a malis."
["Nor let him have a sepulchre wherein he may be received, a haven
for his body, where, life being gone, that body may rest from its
woes."—Ennius, ap. Cicero, Tusc. i. 44.]
As nature demonstrates to us that several dead things retain yet an
occult relation to life; wine changes its flavour and complexion in
cellars, according to the changes and seasons of the vine from whence it
came; and the flesh of—venison alters its condition in the
powdering-tub, and its taste according to the laws of the living flesh
of its kind, as it is said.
CHAPTER IV—THAT THE SOUL EXPENDS ITS PASSIONS UPON FALSE OBJECTS,
WHERE THE TRUE ARE WANTING
A gentleman of my country, marvellously tormented with the gout,
being importuned by his physicians totally to abstain from all manner of
salt meats, was wont pleasantly to reply, that in the extremity of his
fits he must needs have something to quarrel with, and that railing at
and cursing, one while the Bologna sausages, and another the dried
tongues and the hams, was some mitigation to his pain. But, in good
earnest, as the arm when it is advanced to strike, if it miss the blow,
and goes by the wind, it pains us; and as also, that, to make a pleasant
prospect, the sight should not be lost and dilated in vague air, but
have some bound and object to limit and circumscribe it at a reasonable
distance.
"Ventus ut amittit vires, nisi robore densa
Occurrant sylvae, spatio diffusus inani."
["As the wind loses its force diffused in void space, unless it in
its strength encounters the thick wood."—Lucan, iii. 362.]
So it seems that the soul, being transported and discomposed, turns
its violence upon itself, if not supplied with something to oppose it,
and therefore always requires an object at which to aim, and whereon to
act. Plutarch says of those who are delighted with little dogs and
monkeys, that the amorous part that is in us, for want of a legitimate
object, rather than lie idle, does after that manner forge and create
one false and frivolous. And we see that the soul, in its passions,
inclines rather to deceive itself, by creating a false and fantastical a
subject, even contrary to its own belief, than not to have something to
work upon. After this manner brute beasts direct their fury to fall upon
the stone or weapon that has hurt them, and with their teeth a even
execute revenge upon themselves for the injury they have received from
another:
"Pannonis haud aliter, post ictum saevior ursa,
Cui jaculum parva Lybis amentavit habena,
Se rotat in vulnus, telumque irata receptum
Impetit, et secum fugientem circuit hastam."
["So the she-bear, fiercer after the blow from the Lybian's thong-
hurled dart, turns round upon the wound, and attacking the received
spear, twists it, as she flies."—Lucan, vi. 220.]
What causes of the misadventures that befall us do we not invent?
what is it that we do not lay the fault to, right or wrong, that we may
have something to quarrel with? It is not those beautiful tresses you
tear, nor is it the white bosom that in your anger you so unmercifully
beat, that with an unlucky bullet have slain your beloved brother;
quarrel with something else. Livy, speaking of the Roman army in Spain,
says that for the loss of the two brothers, their great captains:
"Flere omnes repente, et offensare capita."
["All at once wept and tore their hair."-Livy, xxv. 37.]
'Tis a common practice. And the philosopher Bion said pleasantly of
the king, who by handsful pulled his hair off his head for sorrow, "Does
this man think that baldness is a remedy for grief?"—[Cicero, Tusc.
Quest., iii. 26.]—Who has not seen peevish gamesters chew and swallow
the cards, and swallow the dice, in revenge for the loss of their money?
Xerxes whipped the sea, and wrote a challenge to Mount Athos; Cyrus
employed a whole army several days at work, to revenge himself of the
river Gyndas, for the fright it had put him into in passing over it; and
Caligula demolished a very beautiful palace for the pleasure his mother
had once enjoyed there.
—[Pleasure—unless 'plaisir' were originally 'deplaisir'—must be
understood here ironically, for the house was one in which she had
been imprisoned.—Seneca, De Ira. iii. 22]—
I remember there was a story current, when I was a boy, that one of
our neighbouring kings—[Probably Alfonso XI. of Castile]—having received
a blow from the hand of God, swore he would be revenged, and in order to
it, made proclamation that for ten years to come no one should pray to
Him, or so much as mention Him throughout his dominions, or, so far as
his authority went, believe in Him; by which they meant to paint not so
much the folly as the vainglory of the nation of which this tale was
told. They are vices that always go together, but in truth such actions
as these have in them still more of presumption than want of wit.
Augustus Caesar, having been tossed with a tempest at sea, fell to
defying Neptune, and in the pomp of the Circensian games, to be
revenged, deposed his statue from the place it had amongst the other
deities. Wherein he was still less excusable than the former, and less
than he was afterwards when, having lost a battle under Quintilius Varus
in Germany, in rage and despair he went running his head against the
wall, crying out, "O Varus! give me back my legions!" for these exceed
all folly, forasmuch as impiety is joined therewith, invading God
Himself, or at least Fortune, as if she had ears that were subject to
our batteries; like the Thracians, who when it thunders or lightens,
fall to shooting against heaven with Titanian vengeance, as if by
flights of arrows they intended to bring God to reason. Though the
ancient poet in Plutarch tells us—
"Point ne se faut couroucer aux affaires,
Il ne leur chault de toutes nos choleres."
["We must not trouble the gods with our affairs; they take no heed
of our angers and disputes."—Plutarch.]
But we can never enough decry the disorderly sallies of our minds.
CHAPTER V—WHETHER THE GOVERNOR OF A PLACE BESIEGED OUGHT HIMSELF TO
GO OUT TO PARLEY
Quintus Marcius, the Roman legate in the war against Perseus, King of
Macedon, to gain time wherein to reinforce his army, set on foot some
overtures of accommodation, with which the king being lulled asleep,
concluded a truce for some days, by this means giving his enemy
opportunity and leisure to recruit his forces, which was afterwards the
occasion of the king's final ruin. Yet the elder senators, mindful of
their forefathers' manners, condemned this proceeding as degenerating
from their ancient practice, which, they said, was to fight by valour,
and not by artifice, surprises, and night-encounters; neither by
pretended flight nor unexpected rallies to overcome their enemies; never
making war till having first proclaimed it, and very often assigned both
the hour and place of battle. Out of this generous principle it was that
they delivered up to Pyrrhus his treacherous physician, and to the
Etrurians their disloyal schoolmaster. This was, indeed, a procedure
truly Roman, and nothing allied to the Grecian subtlety, nor to the
Punic cunning, where it was reputed a victory of less glory to overcome
by force than by fraud. Deceit may serve for a need, but he only
confesses himself overcome who knows he is neither subdued by policy nor
misadventure, but by dint of valour, man to man, in a fair and just war.
It very well appears, by the discourse of these good old senators, that
this fine sentence was not yet received amongst them.
"Dolus, an virtus, quis in hoste requirat?"
["What matters whether by valour or by strategem we overcome the
enemy?"—Aeneid, ii. 390]
The Achaians, says Polybius, abhorred all manner of double-dealing in
war, not reputing it a victory unless where the courage of the enemy was
fairly subdued:
"Eam vir sanctus et sapiens sciet veram esse victoriam, quae, salva
fide et integra dignitate, parabitur."—["An honest and prudent man will
acknowledge that only to be a true victory which shall be obtained
saving his own good faith and dignity."—Florus, i. 12.]—Says another:
"Vosne velit, an me, regnare hera, quidve ferat,
fors virtute experiamur."
["Whether you or I shall rule, or what shall happen, let us
determine by valour."—Cicero, De Offic., i. 12]
In the kingdom of Ternate, amongst those nations which we so broadly
call barbarians, they have a custom never to commence war, till it be
first proclaimed; adding withal an ample declaration of what means they
have to do it with, with what and how many men, what ammunitions, and
what, both offensive and defensive, arms; but also, that being done, if
their enemies do not yield and come to an agreement, they conceive it
lawful to employ without reproach in their wars any means which may help
them to conquer.
The ancient Florentines were so far from seeking to obtain any
advantage over their enemies by surprise, that they always gave them a
month's warning before they drew their army into the field, by the
continual tolling of a bell they called Martinella.—[After St. Martin.]
For what concerns ourselves, who are not so scrupulous in this
affair, and who attribute the honour of the war to him who has the
profit of it, and who after Lysander say, "Where the lion's skin is too
short, we must eke it out with a bit from that of a fox"; the most usual
occasions of surprise are derived from this practice, and we hold that
there are no moments wherein a chief ought to be more circumspect, and
to have his eye so much at watch, as those of parleys and treaties of
accommodation; and it is, therefore, become a general rule amongst the
martial men of these latter times, that a governor of a place never
ought, in a time of siege, to go out to parley. It was for this that in
our fathers' days the Seigneurs de Montmord and de l'Assigni, defending
Mousson against the Count of Nassau, were so highly censured. But yet,
as to this, it would be excusable in that governor who, going out,
should, notwithstanding, do it in such manner that the safety and
advantage should be on his side; as Count Guido di Rangone did at Reggio
(if we are to believe Du Bellay, for Guicciardini says it was he
himself) when the Seigneur de l'Escut approached to parley, who stepped
so little away from his fort, that a disorder happening in the interim
of parley, not only Monsieur de l'Escut and his party who were advanced
with him, found themselves by much the weaker, insomuch that Alessandro
Trivulcio was there slain, but he himself follow the Count, and, relying
upon his honour, to secure himself from the danger of the shot within
the walls of the town.
Eumenes, being shut up in the city of Nora by Antigonus, and by him
importuned to come out to speak with him, as he sent him word it was fit
he should to a greater man than himself, and one who had now an
advantage over him, returned this noble answer. "Tell him," said he,
"that I shall never think any man greater than myself whilst I have my
sword in my hand," and would not consent to come out to him till first,
according to his own demand, Antigonus had delivered him his own nephew
Ptolomeus in hostage.
And yet some have done very well in going out in person to parley, on
the word of the assailant: witness Henry de Vaux, a cavalier of
Champagne, who being besieged by the English in the Castle of Commercy,
and Bartholomew de Brunes, who commanded at the Leaguer, having so
sapped the greatest part of the castle without, that nothing remained
but setting fire to the props to bury the besieged under the ruins, he
requested the said Henry to come out to speak with him for his own good,
which he did with three more in company; and, his ruin being made
apparent to him, he conceived himself singularly obliged to his enemy,
to whose discretion he and his garrison surrendered themselves; and fire
being presently applied to the mine, the props no sooner began to fail,
but the castle was immediately blown up from its foundations, no one
stone being left upon another.
I could, and do, with great facility, rely upon the faith of another;
but I should very unwillingly do it in such a case, as it should thereby
be judged that it was rather an effect of my despair and want of courage
than voluntarily and out of confidence and security in the faith of him
with whom I had to do.
CHAPTER VI—THAT THE HOUR OF PARLEY DANGEROUS
I saw, notwithstanding, lately at Mussidan, a place not far from my
house, that those who were driven out thence by our army, and others of
their party, highly complained of treachery, for that during a treaty of
accommodation, and in the very interim that their deputies were
treating, they were surprised and cut to pieces: a thing that,
peradventure, in another age, might have had some colour of foul play;
but, as I have just said, the practice of arms in these days is quite
another thing, and there is now no confidence in an enemy excusable till
the treaty is finally sealed; and even then the conqueror has enough to
do to keep his word: so hazardous a thing it is to entrust the
observation of the faith a man has engaged to a town that surrenders
upon easy and favourable conditions, to the licence of a victorious
army, and to give the soldier free entrance into it in the heat of
blood.
Lucius AEmilius Regillus, the Roman praetor, having lost his time in
attempting to take the city of Phocaea by force, by reason of the
singular valour wherewith the inhabitants defended themselves,
conditioned, at last, to receive them as friends to the people of Rome,
and to enter the town, as into a confederate city, without any manner of
hostility, of which he gave them all assurance; but having, for the
greater pomp, brought his whole army in with him, it was no more in his
power, with all the endeavour he could use, to restrain his people: so
that, avarice and revenge trampling under foot both his authority and
all military discipline, he there saw a considerable part of the city
sacked and ruined before his face.
Cleomenes was wont to say, "that what mischief soever a man could do
his enemy in time of war was above justice, and nothing accountable to
it in the sight of gods and men." And so, having concluded a truce with
those of Argos for seven days, the third night after he fell upon them
when they were all buried in sleep, and put them to the sword, alleging
that there had no nights been mentioned in the truce; but the gods
punished this subtle perfidy.
In a time of parley also; and while the citizens were relying upon
their safety warrant, the city of Casilinum was taken by surprise, and
that even in the age of the justest captains and the most perfect Roman
military discipline; for it is not said that it is not lawful for us, in
time and place, to make advantage of our enemies' want of understanding,
as well as their want of courage.
And, doubtless, war has naturally many privileges that appear
reasonable even to the prejudice of reason. And therefore here the rule
fails, "Neminem id agere ut ex alte rius praedetur inscitia."—["No one
should preys upon another's folly."—Cicero, De Offic., iii. 17.]—But I
am astonished at the great liberty allowed by Xenophon in such cases,
and that both by precept and by the example of several exploits of his
complete emperor; an author of very great authority, I confess, in those
affairs, as being in his own person both a great captain and a
philosopher of the first form of Socrates' disciples; and yet I cannot
consent to such a measure of licence as he dispenses in all things and
places.
Monsieur d'Aubigny, besieging Capua, and after having directed a
furious battery against it, Signor Fabricio Colonna, governor of the
town, having from a bastion begun to parley, and his soldiers in the
meantime being a little more remiss in their guard, our people entered
the place at unawares, and put them all to the sword. And of later
memory, at Yvoy, Signor Juliano Romero having played that part of a
novice to go out to parley with the Constable, at his return found his
place taken. But, that we might not scape scot-free, the Marquess of
Pescara having laid siege to Genoa, where Duke Ottaviano Fregosa
commanded under our protection, and the articles betwixt them being so
far advanced that it was looked upon as a done thing, and upon the point
to be concluded, the Spaniards in the meantime having slipped in, made
use of this treachery as an absolute victory. And since, at Ligny, in
Barrois, where the Count de Brienne commanded, the emperor having in his
own person beleaguered that place, and Bertheville, the said Count's
lieutenant, going out to parley, whilst he was capitulating the town was
taken.
"Fu il vincer sempremai laudabil cosa,
Vincasi o per fortuna, o per ingegno,"
["Victory is ever worthy of praise, whether obtained by valour or
wisdom."—Ariosto, xv. I.]
But the philosopher Chrysippus was of another opinion, wherein I also
concur; for he was used to say that those who run a race ought to employ
all the force they have in what they are about, and to run as fast as
they can; but that it is by no means fair in them to lay any hand upon
their adversary to stop him, nor to set a leg before him to throw him
down. And yet more generous was the answer of that great Alexander to
Polypercon who was persuading him to take the advantage of the night's
obscurity to fall upon Darius. "By no means," said be; "it is not for
such a man as I am to steal a victory, 'Malo me fortunae poeniteat, quam
victoria pudeat.'"—["I had rather complain of ill-fortune than be
ashamed of victory." Quint. Curt, iv. 13]—
"Atque idem fugientem baud est dignatus Oroden
Sternere, nec jacta caecum dare cuspide vulnus
Obvius, adversoque occurrit, seque viro vir
Contulit, haud furto melior, sed fortibus armis."
["He deigned not to throw down Orodes as he fled, or with the darted
spear to give him a wound unseen; but overtaking him, he confronted
him face to face, and encountered man to man: superior, not in
stratagem, but in valiant arms."—AEneid, x. 732.]
CHAPTER VII——THAT THE INTENTION IS JUDGE OF OUR ACTIONS
'Tis a saying, "That death discharges us of all our obligations." I
know some who have taken it in another sense. Henry VII., King of
England, articled with Don Philip, son to Maximilian the emperor, or (to
place him more honourably) father to the Emperor Charles V., that the
said Philip should deliver up the Duke of Suffolk of the White Rose, his
enemy, who was fled into the Low Countries, into his hands; which Philip
accordingly did, but upon condition, nevertheless, that Henry should
attempt nothing against the life of the said Duke; but coming to die,
the king in his last will commanded his son to put him to death
immediately after his decease. And lately, in the tragedy that the Duke
of Alva presented to us in the persons of the Counts Horn and Egmont at
Brussels, —[Decapitated 4th June 1568]—there were very remarkable
passages, and one amongst the rest, that Count Egmont (upon the security
of whose word and faith Count Horn had come and surrendered himself to
the Duke of Alva) earnestly entreated that he might first mount the
scaffold, to the end that death might disengage him from the obligation
he had passed to the other. In which case, methinks, death did not
acquit the former of his promise, and that the second was discharged
from it without dying. We cannot be bound beyond what we are able to
perform, by reason that effect and performance are not at all in our
power, and that, indeed, we are masters of nothing but the will, in
which, by necessity, all the rules and whole duty of mankind are founded
and established: therefore Count Egmont, conceiving his soul and will
indebted to his promise, although he had not the power to make it good,
had doubtless been absolved of his duty, even though he had outlived the
other; but the King of England wilfully and premeditately breaking his
faith, was no more to be excused for deferring the execution of his
infidelity till after his death than the mason in Herodotus, who having
inviolably, during the time of his life, kept the secret of the treasure
of the King of Egypt, his master, at his death discovered it to his
children.—[Herod., ii. 121.]
I have taken notice of several in my time, who, convicted by their
consciences of unjustly detaining the goods of another, have endeavoured
to make amends by their will, and after their decease; but they had as
good do nothing, as either in taking so much time in so pressing an
affair, or in going about to remedy a wrong with so little
dissatisfaction or injury to themselves. They owe, over and above,
something of their own; and by how much their payment is more strict and
incommodious to themselves, by so much is their restitution more just
meritorious. Penitency requires penalty; but they yet do worse than
these, who reserve the animosity against their neighbour to the last
gasp, having concealed it during their life; wherein they manifest
little regard of their own honour, irritating the party offended in
their memory; and less to their the power, even out of to make their
malice die with them, but extending the life of their hatred even beyond
their own. Unjust judges, who defer judgment to a time wherein they can
have no knowledge of the cause! For my part, I shall take care, if I
can, that my death discover nothing that my life has not first and
openly declared.
CHAPTER VIII——OF IDLENESS
As we see some grounds that have long lain idle and untilled, when
grown rich and fertile by rest, to abound with and spend their virtue in
the product of innumerable sorts of weeds and wild herbs that are
unprofitable, and that to make them perform their true office, we are to
cultivate and prepare them for such seeds as are proper for our service;
and as we see women that, without knowledge of man, do sometimes of
themselves bring forth inanimate and formless lumps of flesh, but that
to cause a natural and perfect generation they are to be husbanded with
another kind of seed: even so it is with minds, which if not applied to
some certain study that may fix and restrain them, run into a thousand
extravagances, eternally roving here and there in the vague expanse of
the imagination—
"Sicut aqua tremulum labris ubi lumen ahenis,
Sole repercussum, aut radiantis imagine lunae,
Omnia pervolitat late loca; jamque sub auras
Erigitur, summique ferit laquearia tecti."
["As when in brazen vats of water the trembling beams of light,
reflected from the sun, or from the image of the radiant moon,
swiftly float over every place around, and now are darted up on
high, and strike the ceilings of the upmost roof."—
AEneid, viii. 22.]
—in which wild agitation there is no folly, nor idle fancy they do
not light upon:—
"Velut aegri somnia, vanae
Finguntur species."
["As a sick man's dreams, creating vain phantasms."—
Hor., De Arte Poetica, 7.]
The soul that has no established aim loses itself, for, as it is
said—
"Quisquis ubique habitat, Maxime, nusquam habitat."
["He who lives everywhere, lives nowhere."—Martial, vii. 73.]
When I lately retired to my own house, with a resolution, as much as
possibly I could, to avoid all manner of concern in affairs, and to
spend in privacy and repose the little remainder of time I have to live,
I fancied I could not more oblige my mind than to suffer it at full
leisure to entertain and divert itself, which I now hoped it might
henceforth do, as being by time become more settled and mature; but I
find—
"Variam semper dant otia mentem,"
["Leisure ever creates varied thought."—Lucan, iv. 704]
that, quite contrary, it is like a horse that has broke from his
rider, who voluntarily runs into a much more violent career than any
horseman would put him to, and creates me so many chimaeras and
fantastic monsters, one upon another, without order or design, that, the
better at leisure to contemplate their strangeness and absurdity, I have
begun to commit them to writing, hoping in time to make it ashamed of
itself.
CHAPTER IX——OF LIARS
There is not a man living whom it would so little become to speak
from memory as myself, for I have scarcely any at all, and do not think
that the world has another so marvellously treacherous as mine. My other
faculties are all sufficiently ordinary and mean; but in this I think
myself very rare and singular, and deserving to be thought famous.
Besides the natural inconvenience I suffer by it (for, certes, the
necessary use of memory considered, Plato had reason when he called it a
great and powerful goddess), in my country, when they would say a man
has no sense, they say, such an one has no memory; and when I complain
of the defect of mine, they do not believe me, and reprove me, as though
I accused myself for a fool: not discerning the difference betwixt
memory and understanding, which is to make matters still worse for me.
But they do me wrong; for experience, rather, daily shows us, on the
contrary, that a strong memory is commonly coupled with infirm judgment.
They do, me, moreover (who am so perfect in nothing as in friendship), a
great wrong in this, that they make the same words which accuse my
infirmity, represent me for an ungrateful person; they bring my
affections into question upon the account of my memory, and from a
natural imperfection, make out a defect of conscience. "He has forgot,"
says one, "this request, or that promise; he no more remembers his
friends; he has forgot to say or do, or conceal such and such a thing,
for my sake." And, truly, I am apt enough to forget many things, but to
neglect anything my friend has given me in charge, I never do it. And it
should be enough, methinks, that I feel the misery and inconvenience of
it, without branding me with malice, a vice so contrary to my humour.
However, I derive these comforts from my infirmity: first, that it is
an evil from which principally I have found reason to correct a worse,
that would easily enough have grown upon me, namely, ambition; the
defect being intolerable in those who take upon them public affairs.
That, like examples in the progress of nature demonstrate to us, she has
fortified me in my other faculties proportionably as she has left me
unfurnished in this; I should otherwise have been apt implicitly to have
reposed my mind and judgment upon the bare report of other men, without
ever setting them to work upon their own force, had the inventions and
opinions of others been ever been present with me by the benefit of
memory. That by this means I am not so talkative, for the magazine of
the memory is ever better furnished with matter than that of the
invention. Had mine been faithful to me, I had ere this deafened all my
friends with my babble, the subjects themselves arousing and stirring up
the little faculty I have of handling and employing them, heating and
distending my discourse, which were a pity: as I have observed in
several of my intimate friends, who, as their memories supply them with
an entire and full view of things, begin their narrative so far back,
and crowd it with so many impertinent circumstances, that though the
story be good in itself, they make a shift to spoil it; and if
otherwise, you are either to curse the strength of their memory or the
weakness of their judgment: and it is a hard thing to close up a
discourse, and to cut it short, when you have once started; there is
nothing wherein the force of a horse is so much seen as in a round and
sudden stop. I see even those who are pertinent enough, who would, but
cannot stop short in their career; for whilst they are seeking out a
handsome period to conclude with, they go on at random, straggling about
upon impertinent trivialities, as men staggering upon weak legs. But,
above all, old men who retain the memory of things past, and forget how
often they have told them, are dangerous company; and I have known
stories from the mouth of a man of very great quality, otherwise very
pleasant in themselves, become very wearisome by being repeated a
hundred times over and over again to the same people.
Secondly, that, by this means, I the less remember the injuries I
have received; insomuch that, as the ancient said,—[Cicero, Pro Ligar.
c. 12.]—I should have a register of injuries, or a prompter, as Darius,
who, that he might not forget the offence he had received from those of
Athens, so oft as he sat down to dinner, ordered one of his pages three
times to repeat in his ear, "Sir, remember the Athenians";—[Herod., v.
105.]—and then, again, the places which I revisit, and the books I read
over again, still smile upon me with a fresh novelty.
It is not without good reason said "that he who has not a good memory
should never take upon him the trade of lying." I know very well that
the grammarians—[Nigidius, Aulus Gellius, xi. ii; Nonius, v. 80.]—
distinguish betwixt an untruth and a lie, and say that to tell an
untruth is to tell a thing that is false, but that we ourselves believe
to be true; and that the definition of the word to lie in Latin, from
which our French is taken, is to tell a thing which we know in our
conscience to be untrue; and it is of this last sort of liars only that
I now speak. Now, these do either wholly contrive and invent the
untruths they utter, or so alter and disguise a true story that it ends
in a lie. When they disguise and often alter the same story, according
to their own fancy, 'tis very hard for them, at one time or another, to
escape being trapped, by reason that the real truth of the thing, having
first taken possession of the memory, and being there lodged impressed
by the medium of knowledge and science, it will be difficult that it
should not represent itself to the imagination, and shoulder out
falsehood, which cannot there have so sure and settled footing as the
other; and the circumstances of the first true knowledge evermore
running in their minds, will be apt to make them forget those that are
illegitimate, and only, forged by their own fancy. In what they, wholly
invent, forasmuch as there is no contrary impression to jostle their
invention there seems to be less danger of tripping; and yet even this
by reason it is a vain body and without any hold, is very apt to escape
the memory, if it be not well assured. Of which I had very pleasant
experience, at the expense of such as profess only to form and
accommodate their speech to the affair they have in hand, or to humour
of the great folks to whom they are speaking; for the circumstances to
which these men stick not to enslave their faith and conscience being
subject to several changes, their language must vary accordingly: whence
it happens that of the same thing they tell one man that it is this, and
another that it is that, giving it several colours; which men, if they
once come to confer notes, and find out the cheat, what becomes of this
fine art? To which may be added, that they must of necessity very often
ridiculously trap themselves; for what memory can be sufficient to
retain so many different shapes as they have forged upon one and the
same subject? I have known many in my time very ambitious of the repute
of this fine wit; but they do not see that if they have the reputation
of it, the effect can no longer be.
In plain truth, lying is an accursed vice. We are not men, nor have
other tie upon one another, but by our word. If we did but discover the
horror and gravity of it, we should pursue it with fire and sword, and
more justly than other crimes. I see that parents commonly, and with
indiscretion enough, correct their children for little innocent faults,
and torment them for wanton tricks, that have neither impression nor
consequence; whereas, in my opinion, lying only, and, which is of
something a lower form, obstinacy, are the faults which are to be
severely whipped out of them, both in their infancy and in their
progress, otherwise they grow up and increase with them; and after a
tongue has once got the knack of lying, 'tis not to be imagined how
impossible it is to reclaim it whence it comes to pass that we see some,
who are otherwise very honest men, so subject and enslaved to this vice.
I have an honest lad to my tailor, whom I never knew guilty of one
truth, no, not when it had been to his advantage. If falsehood had, like
truth, but one face only, we should be upon better terms; for we should
then take for certain the contrary to what the liar says: but the
reverse of truth has a hundred thousand forms, and a field indefinite,
without bound or limit. The Pythagoreans make good to be certain and
finite, and evil, infinite and uncertain. There are a thousand ways to
miss the white, there is only one to hit it. For my own part, I have
this vice in so great horror, that I am not sure I could prevail with my
conscience to secure myself from the most manifest and extreme danger by
an impudent and solemn lie. An ancient father says "that a dog we know
is better company than a man whose language we do not understand."
"Ut externus alieno pene non sit hominis vice."
["As a foreigner cannot be said to supply us the place of a man."
—Pliny, Nat. Hist. vii. I]
And how much less sociable is false speaking than silence?
King Francis I. vaunted that he had by this means nonplussed
Francesco Taverna, ambassador of Francesco Sforza, Duke of Milan, a man
very famous for his science in talking in those days. This gentleman had
been sent to excuse his master to his Majesty about a thing of very
great consequence, which was this: the King, still to maintain some
intelligence with Italy, out of which he had lately been driven, and
particularly with the duchy of Milan, had thought it convenient to have
a gentleman on his behalf to be with that Duke: an ambassador in effect,
but in outward appearance a private person who pretended to reside there
upon his own particular affairs; for the Duke, much more depending upon
the Emperor, especially at a time when he was in a treaty of marriage
with his niece, daughter to the King of Denmark, who is now dowager of
Lorraine, could not manifest any practice and conference with us without
his great interest. For this commission one Merveille, a Milanese
gentleman, and an equerry to the King, being thought very fit, was
accordingly despatched thither with private credentials, and
instructions as ambassador, and with other letters of recommendation to
the Duke about his own private concerns, the better to mask and colour
the business; and was so long in that court, that the Emperor at last
had some inkling of his real employment there; which was the occasion of
what followed after, as we suppose; which was, that under pretence of
some murder, his trial was in two days despatched, and his head in the
night struck off in prison. Messire Francesco being come, and prepared
with a long counterfeit history of the affair (for the King had applied
himself to all the princes of Christendom, as well as to the Duke
himself, to demand satisfaction), had his audience at the morning
council; where, after he had for the support of his cause laid open
several plausible justifications of the fact, that his master had never
looked upon this Merveille for other than a private gentleman and his
own subject, who was there only in order to his own business, neither
had he ever lived under any other aspect; absolutely disowning that he
had ever heard he was one of the King's household or that his Majesty so
much as knew him, so far was he from taking him for an ambassador: the
King, in his turn, pressing him with several objections and demands, and
challenging him on all sides, tripped him up at last by asking, why,
then, the execution was performed by night, and as it were by stealth?
At which the poor confounded ambassador, the more handsomely to
disengage himself, made answer, that the Duke would have been very loth,
out of respect to his Majesty, that such an execution should have been
performed by day. Any one may guess if he was not well rated when he
came home, for having so grossly tripped in the presence of a prince of
so delicate a nostril as King Francis.
Pope Julius II. having sent an ambassador to the King of England to
animate him against King Francis, the ambassador having had his
audience, and the King, before he would give an answer, insisting upon
the difficulties he should find in setting on foot so great a
preparation as would be necessary to attack so potent a King, and urging
some reasons to that effect, the ambassador very unseasonably replied
that he had also himself considered the same difficulties, and had
represented them to the Pope. From which saying of his, so directly
opposite to the thing propounded and the business he came about, which
was immediately to incite him to war, the King of England first derived
the argument (which he afterward found to be true), that this
ambassador, in his own mind, was on the side of the French; of which
having advertised his master, his estate at his return home was
confiscated, and he himself very narrowly escaped the losing of his
head.—[Erasmi Op. (1703), iv. col. 684.]
CHAPTER X——OF QUICK OR SLOW SPEECH
"Onc ne furent a touts toutes graces donnees."
["All graces were never yet given to any one man."—A verse
in one of La Brebis' Sonnets.]
So we see in the gift of eloquence, wherein some have such a facility
and promptness, and that which we call a present wit so easy, that they
are ever ready upon all occasions, and never to be surprised; and others
more heavy and slow, never venture to utter anything but what they have
long premeditated, and taken great care and pains to fit and prepare.
Now, as we teach young ladies those sports and exercises which are
most proper to set out the grace and beauty of those parts wherein their
chiefest ornament and perfection lie, so it should be in these two
advantages of eloquence, to which the lawyers and preachers of our age
seem principally to pretend. If I were worthy to advise, the slow
speaker, methinks, should be more proper for the pulpit, and the other
for the bar: and that because the employment of the first does naturally
allow him all the leisure he can desire to prepare himself, and besides,
his career is performed in an even and unintermitted line, without stop
or interruption; whereas the pleader's business and interest compels him
to enter the lists upon all occasions, and the unexpected objections and
replies of his adverse party jostle him out of his course, and put him,
upon the instant, to pump for new and extempore answers and defences.
Yet, at the interview betwixt Pope Clement and King Francis at
Marseilles, it happened, quite contrary, that Monsieur Poyet, a man bred
up all his life at the bar, and in the highest repute for eloquence,
having the charge of making the harangue to the Pope committed to him,
and having so long meditated on it beforehand, as, so they said, to have
brought it ready made along with him from Paris; the very day it was to
have been pronounced, the Pope, fearing something might be said that
might give offence to the other princes' ambassadors who were there
attending on him, sent to acquaint the King with the argument which he
conceived most suiting to the time and place, but, by chance, quite
another thing to that Monsieur de Poyet had taken so much pains about:
so that the fine speech he had prepared was of no use, and he was upon
the instant to contrive another; which finding himself unable to do,
Cardinal du Bellay was constrained to perform that office. The pleader's
part is, doubtless, much harder than that of the preacher; and yet, in
my opinion, we see more passable lawyers than preachers, at all events
in France. It should seem that the nature of wit is to have its
operation prompt and sudden, and that of judgment to have it more
deliberate and more slow. But he who remains totally silent, for want of
leisure to prepare himself to speak well, and he also whom leisure does
noways benefit to better speaking, are equally unhappy.
'Tis said of Severus Cassius that he spoke best extempore, that he
stood more obliged to fortune than to his own diligence; that it was an
advantage to him to be interrupted in speaking, and that his adversaries
were afraid to nettle him, lest his anger should redouble his eloquence.
I know, experimentally, the disposition of nature so impatient of
tedious and elaborate premeditation, that if it do not go frankly and
gaily to work, it can perform nothing to purpose. We say of some
compositions that they stink of oil and of the lamp, by reason of a
certain rough harshness that laborious handling imprints upon those
where it has been employed. But besides this, the solicitude of doing
well, and a certain striving and contending of a mind too far strained
and overbent upon its undertaking, breaks and hinders itself like water,
that by force of its own pressing violence and abundance, cannot find a
ready issue through the neck of a bottle or a narrow sluice. In this
condition of nature, of which I am now speaking, there is this also,
that it would not be disordered and stimulated with such passions as the
fury of Cassius (for such a motion would be too violent and rude); it
would not be jostled, but solicited; it would be roused and heated by
unexpected, sudden, and accidental occasions. If it be left to itself,
it flags and languishes; agitation only gives it grace and vigour. I am
always worst in my own possession, and when wholly at my own
disposition: accident has more title to anything that comes from me than
I; occasion, company, and even the very rising and falling of my own
voice, extract more from my fancy than I can find, when I sound and
employ it by myself. By which means, the things I say are better than
those I write, if either were to be preferred, where neither is worth
anything. This, also, befalls me, that I do not find myself where I seek
myself, and I light upon things more by chance than by any inquisition
of my own judgment. I perhaps sometimes hit upon something when I write,
that seems quaint and sprightly to me, though it will appear dull and
heavy to another.—But let us leave these fine compliments; every one
talks thus of himself according to his talent. But when I come to speak,
I am already so lost that I know not what I was about to say, and in
such cases a stranger often finds it out before me. If I should make
erasure so often as this inconvenience befalls me, I should make clean
work; occasion will, at some other time, lay it as visible to me as the
light, and make me wonder what I should stick at.
CHAPTER XI——OF PROGNOSTICATIONS
For what concerns oracles, it is certain that a good while before the
coming of Jesus Christ they had begun to lose their credit; for we see
that Cicero troubled to find out the cause of their decay, and he has
these words:
"Cur isto modo jam oracula Delphis non eduntur,
non modo nostro aetate, sed jam diu; ut nihil
possit esse contemptius?"
["What is the reason that the oracles at Delphi are no longer
uttered: not merely in this age of ours, but for a long time past,
insomuch that nothing is more in contempt?"
—Cicero, De Divin., ii. 57.]
But as to the other prognostics, calculated from the anatomy of
beasts at sacrifices (to which purpose Plato does, in part, attribute
the natural constitution of the intestines of the beasts themselves),
the scraping of poultry, the flight of birds—
"Aves quasdam . . . rerum augurandarum
causa natas esse putamus."
["We think some sorts of birds are purposely created to serve
the purposes of augury."—Cicero, De Natura Deor., ii. 64.]
claps of thunder, the overflowing of rivers—
"Multa cernunt Aruspices, multa Augures provident,
multa oraculis declarantur, multa vaticinationibus,
multa somniis, multa portentis."
["The Aruspices discern many things, the Augurs foresee many things,
many things are announced by oracles, many by vaticinations, many by
dreams, many by portents."—Cicero, De Natura Deor., ii. 65.]
—and others of the like nature, upon which antiquity founded most of
their public and private enterprises, our religion has totally abolished
them. And although there yet remain amongst us some practices of
divination from the stars, from spirits, from the shapes and complexions
of men, from dreams and the like (a notable example of the wild
curiosity of our nature to grasp at and anticipate future things, as if
we had not enough to do to digest the present)—
"Cur hanc tibi, rector Olympi,
Sollicitis visum mortalibus addere curam,
Noscant venturas ut dira per omina clades?...
Sit subitum, quodcumque paras; sit coeca futuri
Mens hominum fati, liceat sperare timenti."
["Why, ruler of Olympus, hast thou to anxious mortals thought fit to
add this care, that they should know by, omens future slaughter?...
Let whatever thou art preparing be sudden. Let the mind of men be
blind to fate in store; let it be permitted to the timid to hope."
—Lucan, ii. 14]
"Ne utile quidem est scire quid futurum sit;
miserum est enim, nihil proficientem angi,"
["It is useless to know what shall come to pass; it is a miserable
thing to be tormented to no purpose."
—Cicero, De Natura Deor., iii. 6.]
yet are they of much less authority now than heretofore. Which makes
so much more remarkable the example of Francesco, Marquis of Saluzzo,
who being lieutenant to King Francis I. in his ultramontane army,
infinitely favoured and esteemed in our court, and obliged to the king's
bounty for the marquisate itself, which had been forfeited by his
brother; and as to the rest, having no manner of provocation given him
to do it, and even his own affection opposing any such disloyalty,
suffered himself to be so terrified, as it was confidently reported,
with the fine prognostics that were spread abroad everywhere in favour
of the Emperor Charles V., and to our disadvantage (especially in Italy,
where these foolish prophecies were so far believed, that at Rome great
sums of money were ventured out upon return of greater, when the
prognostics came to pass, so certain they made themselves of our ruin),
that, having often bewailed, to those of his acquaintance who were most
intimate with him, the mischiefs that he saw would inevitably fall upon
the Crown of France and the friends he had in that court, he revolted
and turned to the other side; to his own misfortune, nevertheless, what
constellation soever governed at that time. But he carried himself in
this affair like a man agitated by divers passions; for having both
towns and forces in his hands, the enemy's army under Antonio de Leyva
close by him, and we not at all suspecting his design, it had been in
his power to have done more than he did; for we lost no men by this
infidelity of his, nor any town, but Fossano only, and that after a long
siege and a brave defence.—(1536)
"Prudens futuri temporis exitum
Caliginosa nocte premit Deus,
Ridetque, si mortalis ultra
Fas trepidat."
["A wise God covers with thick night the path of the future, and
laughs at the man who alarms himself without reason."
—Hor., Od., iii. 29.]
"Ille potens sui
Laetusque deget, cui licet in diem
Dixisse vixi! cras vel atra
Nube polum pater occupato,
Vel sole puro."
["He lives happy and master of himself who can say as each day
passes on, 'I HAVE LIVED:' whether to-morrow our Father shall give
us a clouded sky or a clear day."—Hor., Od., iii. 29]
"Laetus in praesens animus; quod ultra est,
Oderit curare."
["A mind happy, cheerful in the present state, will take good care
not to think of what is beyond it."—Ibid., ii. 25]
And those who take this sentence in a contrary sense interpret it
amiss:
"Ista sic reciprocantur, ut et si divinatio sit,
dii sint; et si dii lint, sit divinatio."
["These things are so far reciprocal that if there be divination,
there must be deities; and if deities, divination."—Cicero, De
Divin., i. 6.]
Much more wisely Pacuvius—
"Nam istis, qui linguam avium intelligunt,
Plusque ex alieno jecore sapiunt, quam ex suo,
Magis audiendum, quam auscultandum, censeo."
["As to those who understand the language of birds, and who rather
consult the livers of animals other than their own, I had rather
hear them than attend to them."
—Cicero, De Divin., i. 57, ex Pacuvio]
The so celebrated art of divination amongst the Tuscans took its
beginning thus: A labourer striking deep with his cutter into the earth,
saw the demigod Tages ascend, with an infantine aspect, but endued with
a mature and senile wisdom. Upon the rumour of which, all the people ran
to see the sight, by whom his words and science, containing the
principles and means to attain to this art, were recorded, and kept for
many ages.—[Cicero, De Devina, ii. 23]—A birth suitable to its progress;
I, for my part, should sooner regulate my affairs by the chance of a die
than by such idle and vain dreams. And, indeed, in all republics, a good
share of the government has ever been referred to chance. Plato, in the
civil regimen that he models according to his own fancy, leaves to it
the decision of several things of very great importance, and will,
amongst other things, that marriages should be appointed by lot;
attributing so great importance to this accidental choice as to ordain
that the children begotten in such wedlock be brought up in the country,
and those begotten in any other be thrust out as spurious and base; yet
so, that if any of those exiles, notwithstanding, should, peradventure,
in growing up give any good hope of himself, he might be recalled, as,
also, that such as had been retained, should be exiled, in case they
gave little expectation of themselves in their early growth.
I see some who are mightily given to study and comment upon their
almanacs, and produce them to us as an authority when anything has
fallen out pat; and, for that matter, it is hardly possible but that
these alleged authorities sometimes stumble upon a truth amongst an
infinite number of lies.
"Quis est enim, qui totum diem jaculans
non aliquando collineet?"
["For who shoots all day at butts that does not sometimes hit the
white?"—Cicero, De Divin., ii. 59.]
I think never the better of them for some such accidental hit. There
would be more certainty in it if there were a rule and a truth of always
lying. Besides, nobody records their flimflams and false prognostics,
forasmuch as they are infinite and common; but if they chop upon one
truth, that carries a mighty report, as being rare, incredible, and
prodigious. So Diogenes, surnamed the Atheist, answered him in
Samothrace, who, showing him in the temple the several offerings and
stories in painting of those who had escaped shipwreck, said to him,
"Look, you who think the gods have no care of human things, what do you
say to so many persons preserved from death by their especial favour?"
"Why, I say," answered he, "that their pictures are not here who were
cast away, who are by much the greater number."—[Cicero, De Natura
Deor., i. 37.]
Cicero observes that of all the philosophers who have acknowledged a
deity, Xenophanes the Colophonian only has endeavoured to eradicate all
manner of divination—[Cicero, De Divin., i. 3.]—; which makes it the
less a wonder if we have now and then seen some of our princes,
sometimes to their own cost, rely too much upon these vanities. I had
given anything with my own eyes to see those two great marvels, the book
of Joachim the Calabrian abbot, which foretold all the future Popes,
their names and qualities; and that of the Emperor Leo, which prophesied
all the emperors and patriarchs of Greece. This I have been an
eyewitness of, that in public confusions, men astonished at their
fortune, have abandoned their own reason, superstitiously to seek out in
the stars the ancient causes and menaces of the present mishaps, and in
my time have been so strangely successful in it, as to make me believe
that this being an amusement of sharp and volatile wits, those who have
been versed in this knack of unfolding and untying riddles, are capable,
in any sort of writing, to find out what they desire. But above all,
that which gives them the greatest room to play in, is the obscure,
ambiguous, and fantastic gibberish of the prophetic canting, where their
authors deliver nothing of clear sense, but shroud all in riddle, to the
end that posterity may interpret and apply it according to its own
fancy.
Socrates demon might, perhaps, be no other but a certain impulsion of
the will, which obtruded itself upon him without the advice or consent
of his judgment; and in a soul so enlightened as his was, and so
prepared by a continual exercise of wisdom-and virtue, 'tis to be
supposed those inclinations of his, though sudden and undigested, were
very important and worthy to be followed. Every one finds in himself
some image of such agitations, of a prompt, vehement, and fortuitous
opinion; and I may well allow them some authority, who attribute so
little to our prudence, and who also myself have had some, weak in
reason, but violent in persuasion and dissuasion, which were most
frequent with Socrates,—[Plato, in his account of Theages the
Pythagorean]—by which I have suffered myself to be carried away so
fortunately, and so much to my own advantage, that they might have been
judged to have had something in them of a divine inspiration.
CHAPTER XII——OF CONSTANCY
The law of resolution and constancy does not imply that we ought not,
as much as in us lies, to decline and secure ourselves from the
mischiefs and inconveniences that threaten us; nor, consequently, that
we shall not fear lest they should surprise us: on the contrary, all
decent and honest ways and means of securing ourselves from harms, are
not only permitted, but, moreover, commendable, and the business of
constancy chiefly is, bravely to stand to, and stoutly to suffer those
inconveniences which are not possibly to be avoided. So that there is no
supple motion of body, nor any movement in the handling of arms, how
irregular or ungraceful soever, that we need condemn, if they serve to
protect us from the blow that is made against us.
Several very warlike nations have made use of a retreating and flying
way of fight as a thing of singular advantage, and, by so doing, have
made their backs more dangerous to their enemies than their faces. Of
which kind of fighting the Turks still retain something in their
practice of arms; and Socrates, in Plato, laughs at Laches, who had
defined fortitude to be a standing firm in the ranks against the enemy.
"What!" says he, "would it, then, be a reputed cowardice to overcome
them by giving ground?" urging, at the same time, the authority of
Homer, who commends in AEneas the science of flight. And whereas Laches,
considering better of it, admits the practice as to the Scythians, and,
in general, all cavalry whatever, he again attacks him with the example
of the Lacedaemonian foot—a nation of all other the most obstinate in
maintaining their ground—who, in the battle of Plataea, not being able
to break into the Persian phalanx, bethought themselves to disperse and
retire, that by the enemy supposing they fled, they might break and
disunite that vast body of men in the pursuit, and by that stratagem
obtained the victory.
As for the Scythians, 'tis said of them, that when Darius went his
expedition to subdue them, he sent, by a herald, highly to reproach
their king, that he always retired before him and declined a battle; to
which Idanthyrses,—[Herod., iv. 127.]—for that was his name, returned
answer, that it was not for fear of him, or of any man living, that he
did so, but that it was the way of marching in practice with his nation,
who had neither tilled fields, cities, nor houses to defend, or to fear
the enemy should make any advantage of but that if he had such a stomach
to fight, let him but come to view their ancient places of sepulture,
and there he should have his fill.
Nevertheless, as to cannon-shot, when a body of men are drawn up in
the face of a train of artillery, as the occasion of war often requires,
it is unhandsome to quit their post to avoid the danger, forasmuch as by
reason of its violence and swiftness we account it inevitable; and many
a one, by ducking, stepping aside, and such other motions of fear, has
been, at all events, sufficiently laughed at by his companions. And yet,
in the expedition that the Emperor Charles V. made against us into
Provence, the Marquis de Guast going to reconnoitre the city of Arles,
and advancing out of the cover of a windmill, under favour of which he
had made his approach, was perceived by the Seigneurs de Bonneval and
the Seneschal of Agenois, who were walking upon the 'theatre aux
ayenes'; who having shown him to the Sieur de Villiers, commissary of
the artillery, he pointed a culverin so admirably well, and levelled it
so exactly right against him, that had not the Marquis, seeing fire
given to it, slipped aside, it was certainly concluded the shot had
taken him full in the body. And, in like manner, some years before,
Lorenzo de' Medici, Duke of Urbino, and father to the
queen-mother—[Catherine de' Medici, mother of Henry III.]—laying siege
to Mondolfo, a place in the territories of the Vicariat in Italy, seeing
the cannoneer give fire to a piece that pointed directly against him, it
was well for him that he ducked, for otherwise the shot, that only razed
the top of his head, had doubtless hit him full in the breast. To say
truth, I do not think that these evasions are performed upon the account
of judgment; for how can any man living judge of high or low aim on so
sudden an occasion? And it is much more easy to believe that fortune
favoured their apprehension, and that it might be as well at another
time to make them face the danger, as to seek to avoid it. For my own
part, I confess I cannot forbear starting when the rattle of a
harquebuse thunders in my ears on a sudden, and in a place where I am
not to expect it, which I have also observed in others, braver fellows
than I.
Neither do the Stoics pretend that the soul of their philosopher need
be proof against the first visions and fantasies that surprise him; but,
as to a natural subjection, consent that he should tremble at the
terrible noise of thunder, or the sudden clatter of some falling ruin,
and be affrighted even to paleness and convulsion; and so in other
passions, provided his judgment remain sound and entire, and that the
seat of his reason suffer no concussion nor alteration, and that he
yield no consent to his fright and discomposure. To him who is not a
philosopher, a fright is the same thing in the first part of it, but
quite another thing in the second; for the impression of passions does
not remain superficially in him, but penetrates farther, even to the
very seat of reason, infecting and corrupting it, so that he judges
according to his fear, and conforms his behaviour to it. In this verse
you may see the true state of the wise Stoic learnedly and plainly
expressed:—
"Mens immota manet; lachrymae volvuntur inanes."
["Though tears flow, the mind remains unmoved."
—Virgil, AEneid, iv. 449]
The Peripatetic sage does not exempt himself totally from
perturbations of mind, but he moderates them.
CHAPTER XIII——THE CEREMONY OF THE INTERVIEW OF PRINCES
There is no subject so frivolous that does not merit a place in this
rhapsody. According to our common rule of civility, it would be a
notable affront to an equal, and much more to a superior, to fail being
at home when he has given you notice he will come to visit you. Nay,
Queen Margaret of Navarre further adds, that it would be a rudeness in a
gentleman to go out, as we so often do, to meet any that is coming to
see him, let him be of what high condition soever; and that it is more
respectful and more civil to stay at home to receive him, if only upon
the account of missing him by the way, and that it is enough to receive
him at the door, and to wait upon him. For my part, who as much as I can
endeavour to reduce the ceremonies of my house, I very often forget both
the one and the other of these vain offices. If, peradventure, some one
may take offence at this, I can't help it; it is much better to offend
him once than myself every day, for it would be a perpetual slavery. To
what end do we avoid the servile attendance of courts, if we bring the
same trouble home to our own private houses? It is also a common rule in
all assemblies, that those of less quality are to be first upon the
place, by reason that it is more due to the better sort to make others
wait and expect them.
Nevertheless, at the interview betwixt Pope Clement and King Francis
at Marseilles,—[in 1533.]—the King, after he had taken order for the
necessary preparations for his reception and entertainment, withdrew out
of the town, and gave the Pope two or three days' respite for his entry,
and to repose and refresh himself, before he came to him. And in like
manner, at the assignation of the Pope and the Emperor,—[Charles V. in
1532.] at Bologna, the Emperor gave the Pope opportunity to come thither
first, and came himself after; for which the reason given was this, that
at all the interviews of such princes, the greater ought to be first at
the appointed place, especially before the other in whose territories
the interview is appointed to be, intimating thereby a kind of deference
to the other, it appearing proper for the less to seek out and to apply
themselves to the greater, and not the greater to them.
Not every country only, but every city and every society has its
particular forms of civility. There was care enough to this taken in my
education, and I have lived in good company enough to know the
formalities of our own nation, and am able to give lessons in it. I love
to follow them, but not to be so servilely tied to their observation
that my whole life should be enslaved to ceremonies, of which there are
some so troublesome that, provided a man omits them out of discretion,
and not for want of breeding, it will be every whit as handsome. I have
seen some people rude, by being overcivil and troublesome in their
courtesy.
Still, these excesses excepted, the knowledge of courtesy and good
manners is a very necessary study. It is, like grace and beauty, that
which begets liking and an inclination to love one another at the first
sight, and in the very beginning of acquaintance; and, consequently,
that which first opens the door and intromits us to instruct ourselves
by the example of others, and to give examples ourselves, if we have any
worth taking notice of and communicating.
CHAPTER XIV——THAT MEN ARE JUSTLY PUNISHED FOR BEING OBSTINATE IN THE
DEFENCE OF A FORT THAT IS NOT IN REASON TO BE DEFENDED
Valour has its bounds as well as other virtues, which, once
transgressed, the next step is into the territories of vice; so that by
having too large a proportion of this heroic virtue, unless a man be
very perfect in its limits, which upon the confines are very hard to
discern, he may very easily unawares run into temerity, obstinacy, and
folly. From this consideration it is that we have derived the custom, in
times of war, to punish, even with death, those who are obstinate to
defend a place that by the rules of war is not tenable; otherwise men
would be so confident upon the hope of impunity, that not a henroost but
would resist and seek to stop an army.
The Constable Monsieur de Montmorenci, having at the siege of Pavia
been ordered to pass the Ticino, and to take up his quarters in the
Faubourg St. Antonio, being hindered by a tower at the end of the
bridge, which was so obstinate as to endure a battery, hanged every man
he found within it for their labour. And again, accompanying the Dauphin
in his expedition beyond the Alps, and taking the Castle of Villano by
assault, and all within it being put to the sword by the fury of the
soldiers, the governor and his ensign only excepted, he caused them both
to be trussed up for the same reason; as also did the Captain Martin du
Bellay, then governor of Turin, with the governor of San Buono, in the
same country, all his people having been cut to pieces at the taking of
the place.
But forasmuch as the strength or weakness of a fortress is always
measured by the estimate and counterpoise of the forces that attack it
—for a man might reasonably enough despise two culverins, that would be
a madman to abide a battery of thirty pieces of cannon—where also the
greatness of the prince who is master of the field, his reputation, and
the respect that is due unto him, are also put into the balance, there
is danger that the balance be pressed too much in that direction. And it
may happen that a man is possessed with so great an opinion of himself
and his power, that thinking it unreasonable any place should dare to
shut its gates against him, he puts all to the sword where he meets with
any opposition, whilst his fortune continues; as is plain in the fierce
and arrogant forms of summoning towns and denouncing war, savouring so
much of barbarian pride and insolence, in use amongst the Oriental
princes, and which their successors to this day do yet retain and
practise. And in that part of the world where the Portuguese subdued the
Indians, they found some states where it was a universal and inviolable
law amongst them that every enemy overcome by the king in person, or by
his lieutenant, was out of composition.
So above all both of ransom and mercy a man should take heed, if he
can, of falling into the hands of a judge who is an enemy and
victorious.
CHAPTER XV——OF THE PUNISHMENT OF COWARDICE
I once heard of a prince, and a great captain, having a narration
given him as he sat at table of the proceeding against Monsieur de
Vervins, who was sentenced to death for having surrendered Boulogne to
the English, —[To Henry VIII. in 1544]—openly maintaining that a soldier
could not justly be put to death for want of courage. And, in truth,
'tis reason that a man should make a great difference betwixt faults
that merely proceed from infirmity, and those that are visibly the
effects of treachery and malice: for, in the last, we act against the
rules of reason that nature has imprinted in us; whereas, in the former,
it seems as if we might produce the same nature, who left us in such a
state of imperfection and weakness of courage, for our justification.
Insomuch that many have thought we are not fairly questionable for
anything but what we commit against our conscience; and it is partly
upon this rule that those ground their opinion who disapprove of capital
or sanguinary punishments inflicted upon heretics and misbelievers; and
theirs also who advocate or a judge is not accountable for having from
mere ignorance failed in his administration.
But as to cowardice, it is certain that the most usual way of
chastising it is by ignominy and and it is supposed that this practice
brought into use by the legislator Charondas; and that, before his time,
the laws of Greece punished those with death who fled from a battle;
whereas he ordained only that they be for three days exposed in the
public dressed in woman's attire, hoping yet for some service from them,
having awakened their courage by this open shame:
"Suffundere malis homims sanguinem, quam effundere."
["Rather bring the blood into a man's cheek than let it out of his
body." Tertullian in his Apologetics.]
It appears also that the Roman laws did anciently punish those with
death who had run away; for Ammianus Marcellinus says that the Emperor
Julian commanded ten of his soldiers, who had turned their backs in an
encounter against the Parthians, to be first degraded, and afterward put
to death, according, says he, to the ancient laws,—[Ammianus
Marcellinus, xxiv. 4; xxv. i.]—and yet elsewhere for the like offence he
only condemned others to remain amongst the prisoners under the baggage
ensign. The severe punishment the people of Rome inflicted upon those
who fled from the battle of Cannae, and those who ran away with Aeneius
Fulvius at his defeat, did not extend to death. And yet, methinks, 'tis
to be feared, lest disgrace should make such delinquents desperate, and
not only faint friends, but enemies.
Of late memory,—[In 1523]—the Seigneur de Frauget, lieutenant to the
Mareschal de Chatillon's company, having by the Mareschal de Chabannes
been put in government of Fuentarabia in the place of Monsieur de Lude,
and having surrendered it to the Spaniard, he was for that condemned to
be degraded from all nobility, and both himself and his posterity
declared ignoble, taxable, and for ever incapable of bearing arms, which
severe sentence was afterwards accordingly executed at Lyons.—[In 1536]
—And, since that, all the gentlemen who were in Guise when the Count of
Nassau entered into it, underwent the same punishment, as several others
have done since for the like offence. Notwithstanding, in case of such a
manifest ignorance or cowardice as exceeds all ordinary example, 'tis
but reason to take it for a sufficient proof of treachery and malice,
and for such to be punished.
CHAPTER XVI——A PROCEEDING OF SOME AMBASSADORS
I observe in my travels this custom, ever to learn something from the
information of those with whom I confer (which is the best school of all
others), and to put my company upon those subjects they are the best
able to speak of:—
"Basti al nocchiero ragionar de' venti,
Al bifolco dei tori; et le sue piaghe
Conti'l guerrier; conti'l pastor gli armenti."
["Let the sailor content himself with talking of the winds; the
cowherd of his oxen; the soldier of his wounds; the shepherd of his
flocks."—An Italian translation of Propertius, ii. i, 43]
For it often falls out that, on the contrary, every one will rather
choose to be prating of another man's province than his own, thinking it
so much new reputation acquired; witness the jeer Archidamus put upon
Pertander, "that he had quitted the glory of being an excellent
physician to gain the repute of a very bad poet.—[Plutarch, Apoth. of
the Lacedaemonians, 'in voce' Archidamus.]—And do but observe how large
and ample Caesar is to make us understand his inventions of building
bridges and contriving engines of war,—[De Bello Gall., iv. 17.]—and how
succinct and reserved in comparison, where he speaks of the offices of
his profession, his own valour, and military conduct. His exploits
sufficiently prove him a great captain, and that he knew well enough;
but he would be thought an excellent engineer to boot; a quality
something different, and not necessary to be expected in him. The elder
Dionysius was a very great captain, as it befitted his fortune he should
be; but he took very great pains to get a particular reputation by
poetry, and yet he was never cut out for a poet. A man of the legal
profession being not long since brought to see a study furnished with
all sorts of books, both of his own and all other faculties, took no
occasion at all to entertain himself with any of them, but fell very
rudely and magisterially to descant upon a barricade placed on the
winding stair before the study door, a thing that a hundred captains and
common soldiers see every day without taking any notice or offence.
"Optat ephippia bos piger, optat arare caballus."
["The lazy ox desires a saddle and bridle; the horse wants to
plough."—Hor., Ep., i. 14,43.]
By this course a man shall never improve himself, nor arrive at any
perfection in anything. He must, therefore, make it his business always
to put the architect, the painter, the statuary, every mechanic artisan,
upon discourse of their own capacities.
And, to this purpose, in reading histories, which is everybody's
subject, I use to consider what kind of men are the authors: if they be
persons that profess nothing but mere letters, I, in and from them,
principally observe and learn style and language; if physicians, I the
rather incline to credit what they report of the temperature of the air,
of the health and complexions of princes, of wounds and diseases; if
lawyers, we are from them to take notice of the controversies of rights
and wrongs, the establishment of laws and civil government, and the
like; if divines, the affairs of the Church, ecclesiastical censures,
marriages, and dispensations; if courtiers, manners and ceremonies; if
soldiers, the things that properly belong to their trade, and,
principally, the accounts of the actions and enterprises wherein they
were personally engaged; if ambassadors, we are to observe negotiations,
intelligences, and practices, and the manner how they are to be carried
on.
And this is the reason why (which perhaps I should have lightly
passed over in another) I dwelt upon and maturely considered one passage
in the history written by Monsieur de Langey, a man of very great
judgment in things of that nature: after having given a narrative of the
fine oration Charles V. had made in the Consistory at Rome, and in the
presence of the Bishop of Macon and Monsieur du Velly, our ambassadors
there, wherein he had mixed several injurious expressions to the
dishonour of our nation; and amongst the rest, "that if his captains and
soldiers were not men of another kind of fidelity, resolution, and
sufficiency in the knowledge of arms than those of the King, he would
immediately go with a rope about his neck and sue to him for mercy" (and
it should seem the Emperor had really this, or a very little better
opinion of our military men, for he afterwards, twice or thrice in his
life, said the very same thing); as also, that he challenged the King to
fight him in his shirt with rapier and poignard in a boat. The said
Sieur de Langey, pursuing his history, adds that the forenamed
ambassadors, sending a despatch to the King of these things, concealed
the greatest part, and particularly the last two passages. At which I
could not but wonder that it should be in the power of an ambassador to
dispense with anything which he ought to signify to his master,
especially of so great importance as this, coming from the mouth of such
a person, and spoken in so great an assembly; and I should rather
conceive it had been the servant's duty faithfully to have represented
to him the whole thing as it passed, to the end that the liberty of
selecting, disposing, judging, and concluding might have remained in
him: for either to conceal or to disguise the truth for fear he should
take it otherwise than he ought to do, and lest it should prompt him to
some extravagant resolution, and, in the meantime, to leave him ignorant
of his affairs, should seem, methinks, rather to belong to him who is to
give the law than to him who is only to receive it; to him who is in
supreme command, and not to him who ought to look upon himself as
inferior, not only in authority, but also in prudence and good counsel.
I, for my part, would not be so served in my little concerns.
We so willingly slip the collar of command upon any pretence
whatever, and are so ready to usurp upon dominion, every one does so
naturally aspire to liberty and power, that no utility whatever derived
from the wit or valour of those he employs ought to be so dear to a
superior as a downright and sincere obedience. To obey more upon the
account of understanding than of subjection, is to corrupt the office of
command —[Taken from Aulus Gellius, i. 13.]—; insomuch that P. Crassus,
the same whom the Romans reputed five times happy, at the time when he
was consul in Asia, having sent to a Greek engineer to cause the greater
of two masts of ships that he had taken notice of at Athens to be
brought to him, to be employed about some engine of battery he had a
design to make; the other, presuming upon his own science and
sufficiency in those affairs, thought fit to do otherwise than directed,
and to bring the less, which, according to the rules of art, was really
more proper for the use to which it was designed; but Crassus, though he
gave ear to his reasons with great patience, would not, however, take
them, how sound or convincing soever, for current pay, but caused him to
be well whipped for his pains, valuing the interest of discipline much
more than that of the work in hand.
Notwithstanding, we may on the other side consider that so precise
and implicit an obedience as this is only due to positive and limited
commands. The employment of ambassadors is never so confined, many
things in their management of affairs being wholly referred to the
absolute sovereignty of their own conduct; they do not simply execute,
but also, to their own discretion and wisdom, form and model their
master's pleasure. I have, in my time, known men of command checked for
having rather obeyed the express words of the king's letters, than the
necessity of the affairs they had in hand. Men of understanding do yet,
to this day, condemn the custom of the kings of Persia to give their
lieutenants and agents so little rein, that, upon the least arising
difficulties, they must fain have recourse to their further commands;
this delay, in so vast an extent of dominion, having often very much
prejudiced their affairs; and Crassus, writing to a man whose profession
it was best to understand those things, and pre-acquainting him to what
use this mast was designed, did he not seem to consult his advice, and
in a manner invite him to interpose his better judgment?
CHAPTER XVII——OF FEAR
"Obstupui, steteruntque comae et vox faucibus haesit."
["I was amazed, my hair stood on end, and my voice stuck in my
throat." Virgil, AEneid, ii. 774.]
I am not so good a naturalist (as they call it) as to discern by what
secret springs fear has its motion in us; but, be this as it may, 'tis a
strange passion, and such a one that the physicians say there is no
other whatever that sooner dethrones our judgment from its proper seat;
which is so true, that I myself have seen very many become frantic
through fear; and, even in those of the best settled temper it is most
certain that it begets a terrible astonishment and confusion during the
fit. I omit the vulgar sort, to whom it one while represents their
great-grandsires risen out of their graves in their shrouds, another
while werewolves, nightmares, and chimaeras; but even amongst soldiers,
a sort of men over whom, of all others, it ought to have the least
power, how often has it converted flocks of sheep into armed squadrons,
reeds and bullrushes into pikes and lances, friends into enemies, and
the French white cross into the red cross of Spain! When Monsieur de
Bourbon took Rome,—[In 1527]—an ensign who was upon guard at Borgo San
Pietro was seized with such a fright upon the first alarm, that he threw
himself out at a breach with his colours upon his shoulder, and ran
directly upon the enemy, thinking he had retreated toward the inward
defences of the city, and with much ado, seeing Monsieur de Bourbon's
people, who thought it had been a sally upon them, draw up to receive
him, at last came to himself, and saw his error; and then facing about,
he retreated full speed through the same breach by which he had gone
out, but not till he had first blindly advanced above three hundred
paces into the open field. It did not, however, fall out so well with
Captain Giulio's ensign, at the time when St. Paul was taken from us by
the Comte de Bures and Monsieur de Reu, for he, being so astonished with
fear as to throw himself, colours and all, out of a porthole, was
immediately, cut to pieces by the enemy; and in the same siege, it was a
very memorable fear that so seized, contracted, and froze up the heart
of a gentleman, that he sank down, stone-dead, in the breach, without
any manner of wound or hurt at all. The like madness does sometimes push
on a whole multitude; for in one of the encounters that Germanicus had
with the Germans, two great parties were so amazed with fear that they
ran two opposite ways, the one to the same place from which the other
had fled.—[Tacit, Annal., i. 63.]—Sometimes it adds wings to the heels,
as in the two first: sometimes it nails them to the ground, and fetters
them from moving; as we read of the Emperor Theophilus, who, in a battle
he lost against the Agarenes, was so astonished and stupefied that he
had no power to fly—
"Adeo pavor etiam auxilia formidat"
["So much does fear dread even the means of safety."—Quint.
Curt., ii. II.]
—till such time as Manuel, one of the principal commanders of his
army, having jogged and shaked him so as to rouse him out of his trance,
said to him, "Sir, if you will not follow me, I will kill you; for it is
better you should lose your life than, by being taken, lose your
empire." —[Zonaras, lib. iii.]—But fear does then manifest its utmost
power when it throws us upon a valiant despair, having before deprived
us of all sense both of duty and honour. In the first pitched battle the
Romans lost against Hannibal, under the Consul Sempronius, a body of ten
thousand foot, that had taken fright, seeing no other escape for their
cowardice, went and threw themselves headlong upon the great battalion
of the enemies, which with marvellous force and fury they charged
through and through, and routed with a very great slaughter of the
Carthaginians, thus purchasing an ignominious flight at the same price
they might have gained a glorious victory.—[Livy, xxi. 56.]
The thing in the world I am most afraid of is fear, that passion
alone, in the trouble of it, exceeding all other accidents. What
affliction could be greater or more just than that of Pompey's friends,
who, in his ship, were spectators of that horrible murder? Yet so it
was, that the fear of the Egyptian vessels they saw coming to board
them, possessed them with so great alarm that it is observed they
thought of nothing but calling upon the mariners to make haste, and by
force of oars to escape away, till being arrived at Tyre, and delivered
from fear, they had leisure to turn their thoughts to the loss of their
captain, and to give vent to those tears and lamentations that the other
more potent passion had till then suspended.
"Tum pavor sapientiam omnem mihiex animo expectorat."
["Then fear drove out all intelligence from my mind."—Ennius, ap.
Cicero, Tusc., iv. 8.]
Such as have been well rubbed in some skirmish, may yet, all wounded
and bloody as they are, be brought on again the next day to charge; but
such as have once conceived a good sound fear of the enemy, will never
be made so much as to look him in the face. Such as are in immediate
fear of a losing their estates, of banishment, or of slavery, live in
perpetual anguish, and lose all appetite and repose; whereas such as are
actually poor, slaves, or exiles, ofttimes live as merrily as other
folk. And the many people who, impatient of the perpetual alarms of
fear, have hanged or drowned themselves, or dashed themselves to pieces,
give us sufficiently to understand that fear is more importunate and
insupportable than death itself.
The Greeks acknowledged another kind of fear, differing from any we
have spoken of yet, that surprises us without any visible cause, by an
impulse from heaven, so that whole nations and whole armies have been
struck with it. Such a one was that which brought so wonderful a
desolation upon Carthage, where nothing was to be heard but affrighted
voices and outcries; where the inhabitants were seen to sally out of
their houses as to an alarm, and there to charge, wound, and kill one
another, as if they had been enemies come to surprise their city. All
things were in disorder and fury till, with prayers and sacrifices, they
had appeased their gods—[Diod. Sic., xv. 7]; and this is that they call
panic terrors.—[Ibid. ; Plutarch on Isis and Osiris, c. 8.]
CHAPTER XVIII——THAT MEN ARE NOT TO JUDGE OF OUR HAPPINESS TILL AFTER
DEATH.
[Charron has borrowed with unusual liberality from this and the
succeeding chapter. See Nodier, Questions, p. 206.]
"Scilicet ultima semper
Exspectanda dies homini est; dicique beatus
Ante obitum nemo supremaque funera debet."
["We should all look forward to our last day: no one can be called
happy till he is dead and buried."—Ovid, Met, iii. 135]
The very children know the story of King Croesus to this purpose, who
being taken prisoner by Cyrus, and by him condemned to die, as he was
going to execution cried out, "O Solon, Solon!" which being presently
reported to Cyrus, and he sending to inquire of him what it meant,
Croesus gave him to understand that he now found the teaching Solon had
formerly given him true to his cost; which was, "That men, however
fortune may smile upon them, could never be said to be happy till they
had been seen to pass over the last day of their lives," by reason of
the uncertainty and mutability of human things, which, upon very light
and trivial occasions, are subject to be totally changed into a quite
contrary condition. And so it was that Agesilaus made answer to one who
was saying what a happy young man the King of Persia was, to come so
young to so mighty a kingdom: "'Tis true," said he, "but neither was
Priam unhappy at his years."—[Plutarch, Apothegms of the
Lacedaemonians.]—In a short time, kings of Macedon, successors to that
mighty Alexander, became joiners and scriveners at Rome; a tyrant of
Sicily, a pedant at Corinth; a conqueror of one-half of the world and
general of so many armies, a miserable suppliant to the rascally
officers of a king of Egypt: so much did the prolongation of five or six
months of life cost the great Pompey; and, in our fathers' days,
Ludovico Sforza, the tenth Duke of Milan, whom all Italy had so long
truckled under, was seen to die a wretched prisoner at Loches, but not
till he had lived ten years in captivity,—[He was imprisoned by Louis
XI. in an iron cage]— which was the worst part of his fortune. The
fairest of all queens, —[Mary, Queen of Scots.]—widow to the greatest
king in Europe, did she not come to die by the hand of an executioner?
Unworthy and barbarous cruelty! And a thousand more examples there are
of the same kind; for it seems that as storms and tempests have a malice
against the proud and overtowering heights of our lofty buildings, there
are also spirits above that are envious of the greatnesses here below:
"Usque adeo res humanas vis abdita quaedam
Obterit, et pulchros fasces, saevasque secures
Proculcare, ac ludibrio sibi habere videtur."
["So true it is that some occult power upsets human affairs, the
glittering fasces and the cruel axes spurns under foot, and seems to
make sport of them."—Lucretius, v. 1231.]
And it should seem, also, that Fortune sometimes lies in wait to
surprise the last hour of our lives, to show the power she has, in a
moment, to overthrow what she was so many years in building, making us
cry out with Laberius:
"Nimirum hac die
Una plus vixi mihi, quam vivendum fuit."
["I have lived longer by this one day than I should have
done."—Macrobius, ii. 7.]
And, in this sense, this good advice of Solon may reasonably be
taken; but he, being a philosopher (with which sort of men the favours
and disgraces of Fortune stand for nothing, either to the making a man
happy or unhappy, and with whom grandeurs and powers are accidents of a
quality almost indifferent) I am apt to think that he had some further
aim, and that his meaning was, that the very felicity of life itself,
which depends upon the tranquillity and contentment of a well-descended
spirit, and the resolution and assurance of a well-ordered soul, ought
never to be attributed to any man till he has first been seen to play
the last, and, doubtless, the hardest act of his part. There may be
disguise and dissimulation in all the rest: where these fine
philosophical discourses are only put on, and where accident, not
touching us to the quick, gives us leisure to maintain the same gravity
of aspect; but, in this last scene of death, there is no more
counterfeiting: we must speak out plain, and discover what there is of
good and clean in the bottom of the pot,
"Nam vera; voces turn demum pectore ab imo
Ejiciuntur; et eripitur persona, manet res."
["Then at last truth issues from the heart; the visor's gone,
the man remains."—Lucretius, iii. 57.]
Wherefore, at this last, all the other actions of our life ought to
be tried and sifted: 'tis the master-day, 'tis the day that is judge of
all the rest, "'tis the day," says one of the ancients,—[Seneca, Ep.,
102]— "that must be judge of all my foregoing years." To death do I
refer the assay of the fruit of all my studies: we shall then see
whether my discourses came only from my mouth or from my heart. I have
seen many by their death give a good or an ill repute to their whole
life. Scipio, the father-in-law of Pompey, in dying, well removed the
ill opinion that till then every one had conceived of him. Epaminondas
being asked which of the three he had in greatest esteem, Chabrias,
Iphicrates, or himself. "You must first see us die," said he, "before
that question can be resolved."—[Plutarch, Apoth.]—And, in truth, he
would infinitely wrong that man who would weigh him without the honour
and grandeur of his end.
God has ordered all things as it has best pleased Him; but I have, in
my time, seen three of the most execrable persons that ever I knew in
all manner of abominable living, and the most infamous to boot, who all
died a very regular death, and in all circumstances composed, even to
perfection. There are brave and fortunate deaths: I have seen death cut
the thread of the progress of a prodigious advancement, and in the
height and flower of its increase, of a certain person,—[Montaigne
doubtless refers to his friend Etienne de la Boetie, at whose death in
1563 he was present.]—with so glorious an end that, in my opinion, his
ambitious and generous designs had nothing in them so high and great as
their interruption. He arrived, without completing his course, at the
place to which his ambition aimed, with greater glory than he could
either have hoped or desired, anticipating by his fall the name and
power to which he aspired in perfecting his career. In the judgment I
make of another man's life, I always observe how he carried himself at
his death; and the principal concern I have for my own is that I may die
well—that is, patiently and tranquilly.
CHAPTER XIX——THAT TO STUDY PHILOSOPY IS TO LEARN TO DIE
Cicero says—[Tusc., i. 31.]—"that to study philosophy is nothing but
to prepare one's self to die." The reason of which is, because study and
contemplation do in some sort withdraw from us our soul, and employ it
separately from the body, which is a kind of apprenticeship and a
resemblance of death; or, else, because all the wisdom and reasoning in
the world do in the end conclude in this point, to teach us not to fear
to die. And to say the truth, either our reason mocks us, or it ought to
have no other aim but our contentment only, nor to endeavour anything
but, in sum, to make us live well, and, as the Holy Scripture says, at
our ease. All the opinions of the world agree in this, that pleasure is
our end, though we make use of divers means to attain it: they would,
otherwise, be rejected at the first motion; for who would give ear to
him that should propose affliction and misery for his end? The
controversies and disputes of the philosophical sects upon this point
are merely verbal:
"Transcurramus solertissimas nugas"
["Let us skip over those subtle trifles."—Seneca, Ep., 117.]
—there is more in them of opposition and obstinacy than is consistent
with so sacred a profession; but whatsoever personage a man takes upon
himself to perform, he ever mixes his own part with it.
Let the philosophers say what they will, the thing at which we all
aim, even in virtue is pleasure. It amuses me to rattle in ears this
word, which they so nauseate to and if it signify some supreme pleasure
and contentment, it is more due to the assistance of virtue than to any
other assistance whatever. This pleasure, for being more gay, more
sinewy, more robust and more manly, is only the more seriously
voluptuous, and we ought give it the name of pleasure, as that which is
more favourable, gentle, and natural, and not that from which we have
denominated it. The other and meaner pleasure, if it could deserve this
fair name, it ought to be by way of competition, and not of privilege. I
find it less exempt from traverses and inconveniences than virtue
itself; and, besides that the enjoyment is more momentary, fluid, and
frail, it has its watchings, fasts, and labours, its sweat and its
blood; and, moreover, has particular to itself so many several sorts of
sharp and wounding passions, and so dull a satiety attending it, as
equal it to the severest penance. And we mistake if we think that these
incommodities serve it for a spur and a seasoning to its sweetness (as
in nature one contrary is quickened by another), or say, when we come to
virtue, that like consequences and difficulties overwhelm and render it
austere and inaccessible; whereas, much more aptly than in
voluptuousness, they ennoble, sharpen, and heighten the perfect and
divine pleasure they procure us. He renders himself unworthy of it who
will counterpoise its cost with its fruit, and neither understands the
blessing nor how to use it. Those who preach to us that the quest of it
is craggy, difficult, and painful, but its fruition pleasant, what do
they mean by that but to tell us that it is always unpleasing? For what
human means will ever attain its enjoyment? The most perfect have been
fain to content themselves to aspire unto it, and to approach it only,
without ever possessing it. But they are deceived, seeing that of all
the pleasures we know, the very pursuit is pleasant. The attempt ever
relishes of the quality of the thing to which it is directed, for it is
a good part of, and consubstantial with, the effect. The felicity and
beatitude that glitters in Virtue, shines throughout all her
appurtenances and avenues, even to the first entry and utmost limits.
Now, of all the benefits that virtue confers upon us, the contempt of
death is one of the greatest, as the means that accommodates human life
with a soft and easy tranquillity, and gives us a pure and pleasant
taste of living, without which all other pleasure would be extinct.
Which is the reason why all the rules centre and concur in this one
article. And although they all in like manner, with common accord, teach
us also to despise pain, poverty, and the other accidents to which human
life is subject, it is not, nevertheless, with the same solicitude, as
well by reason these accidents are not of so great necessity, the
greater part of mankind passing over their whole lives without ever
knowing what poverty is, and some without sorrow or sickness, as
Xenophilus the musician, who lived a hundred and six years in a perfect
and continual health; as also because, at the worst, death can, whenever
we please, cut short and put an end to all other inconveniences. But as
to death, it is inevitable:—
"Omnes eodem cogimur; omnium
Versatur urna serius ocius
Sors exitura, et nos in aeternum
Exilium impositura cymbae."
["We are all bound one voyage; the lot of all, sooner or later, is
to come out of the urn. All must to eternal exile sail away."
—Hor., Od., ii. 3, 25.]
and, consequently, if it frights us, 'tis a perpetual torment, for
which there is no sort of consolation. There is no way by which it may
not reach us. We may continually turn our heads this way and that, as in
a suspected country:
"Quae, quasi saxum Tantalo, semper impendet."
["Ever, like Tantalus stone, hangs over us."
—Cicero, De Finib., i. 18.]
Our courts of justice often send back condemned criminals to be
executed upon the place where the crime was committed; but, carry them
to fine houses by the way, prepare for them the best entertainment you
can—
"Non Siculae dapes
Dulcem elaborabunt saporem:
Non avium cyatheaceae cantus
Somnum reducent."
["Sicilian dainties will not tickle their palates, nor the melody of
birds and harps bring back sleep."—Hor., Od., iii. 1, 18.]
Do you think they can relish it? and that the fatal end of their
journey being continually before their eyes, would not alter and deprave
their palate from tasting these regalios?
"Audit iter, numeratque dies, spatioque viarum
Metitur vitam; torquetur peste futura."
["He considers the route, computes the time of travelling, measuring
his life by the length of the journey; and torments himself by
thinking of the blow to come."—Claudianus, in Ruf., ii. 137.]
The end of our race is death; 'tis the necessary object of our aim,
which, if it fright us, how is it possible to advance a step without a
fit of ague? The remedy the vulgar use is not to think on't; but from
what brutish stupidity can they derive so gross a blindness? They must
bridle the ass by the tail:
"Qui capite ipse suo instituit vestigia retro,"
["Who in his folly seeks to advance backwards"—Lucretius, iv. 474]
'tis no wonder if he be often trapped in the pitfall. They affright
people with the very mention of death, and many cross themselves, as it
were the name of the devil. And because the making a man's will is in
reference to dying, not a man will be persuaded to take a pen in hand to
that purpose, till the physician has passed sentence upon and totally
given him over, and then betwixt and terror, God knows in how fit a
condition of understanding he is to do it.
The Romans, by reason that this poor syllable death sounded so
harshly to their ears and seemed so ominous, found out a way to soften
and spin it out by a periphrasis, and instead of pronouncing such a one
is dead, said, "Such a one has lived," or "Such a one has ceased to
live" —[Plutarch, Life of Cicero, c. 22:]—for, provided there was any
mention of life in the case, though past, it carried yet some sound of
consolation. And from them it is that we have borrowed our expression,
"The late Monsieur such and such a one."—["feu Monsieur un tel."]
Peradventure, as the saying is, the term we have lived is worth our
money. I was born betwixt eleven and twelve o'clock in the forenoon the
last day of February 1533, according to our computation, beginning the
year the 1st of January,—[This was in virtue of an ordinance of Charles
IX. in 1563. Previously the year commenced at Easter, so that the 1st
January 1563 became the first day of the year 1563.]—and it is now but
just fifteen days since I was complete nine-and-thirty years old; I make
account to live, at least, as many more. In the meantime, to trouble a
man's self with the thought of a thing so far off were folly. But what?
Young and old die upon the same terms; no one departs out of life
otherwise than if he had but just before entered into it; neither is any
man so old and decrepit, who, having heard of Methuselah, does not think
he has yet twenty good years to come. Fool that thou art! who has
assured unto thee the term of life? Thou dependest upon physicians'
tales: rather consult effects and experience. According to the common
course of things, 'tis long since that thou hast lived by extraordinary
favour; thou hast already outlived the ordinary term of life. And that
it is so, reckon up thy acquaintance, how many more have died before
they arrived at thy age than have attained unto it; and of those who
have ennobled their lives by their renown, take but an account, and I
dare lay a wager thou wilt find more who have died before than after
five-and-thirty years of age. It is full both of reason and piety, too,
to take example by the humanity of Jesus Christ Himself; now, He ended
His life at three-and-thirty years. The greatest man, that was no more
than a man, Alexander, died also at the same age. How many several ways
has death to surprise us?
"Quid quisque, vitet, nunquam homini satis
Cautum est in horas."
["Be as cautious as he may, man can never foresee the danger that
may at any hour befal him."—Hor. O. ii. 13, 13.]
To omit fevers and pleurisies, who would ever have imagined that a
duke of Brittany,—[Jean II. died 1305.]—should be pressed to death in a
crowd as that duke was at the entry of Pope Clement, my neighbour, into
Lyons?—[Montaigne speaks of him as if he had been a contemporary
neighbour, perhaps because he was the Archbishop of Bordeaux. Bertrand
le Got was Pope under the title of Clement V., 1305-14.]—Hast thou not
seen one of our kings—[Henry II., killed in a tournament, July 10,
1559]—killed at a tilting, and did not one of his ancestors die by
jostle of a hog?—[Philip, eldest son of Louis le Gros.]—AEschylus,
threatened with the fall of a house, was to much purpose circumspect to
avoid that danger, seeing that he was knocked on the head by a tortoise
falling out of an eagle's talons in the air. Another was choked with a
grape-stone;—[Val. Max., ix. 12, ext. 2.]—an emperor killed with the
scratch of a comb in combing his head. AEmilius Lepidus with a stumble
at his own threshold,—[Pliny, Nat. Hist., vii. 33.]— and Aufidius with a
jostle against the door as he entered the council-chamber. And betwixt
the very thighs of women, Cornelius Gallus the proctor; Tigillinus,
captain of the watch at Rome; Ludovico, son of Guido di Gonzaga, Marquis
of Mantua; and (of worse example) Speusippus, a Platonic philosopher,
and one of our Popes. The poor judge Bebius gave adjournment in a case
for eight days; but he himself, meanwhile, was condemned by death, and
his own stay of life expired. Whilst Caius Julius, the physician, was
anointing the eyes of a patient, death closed his own; and, if I may
bring in an example of my own blood, a brother of mine, Captain St.
Martin, a young man, three-and-twenty years old, who had already given
sufficient testimony of his valour, playing a match at tennis, received
a blow of a ball a little above his right ear, which, as it gave no
manner of sign of wound or contusion, he took no notice of it, nor so
much as sat down to repose himself, but, nevertheless, died within five
or six hours after of an apoplexy occasioned by that blow.
These so frequent and common examples passing every day before our
eyes, how is it possible a man should disengage himself from the thought
of death, or avoid fancying that it has us every moment by the throat?
What matter is it, you will say, which way it comes to pass, provided a
man does not terrify himself with the expectation? For my part, I am of
this mind, and if a man could by any means avoid it, though by creeping
under a calf's skin, I am one that should not be ashamed of the shift;
all I aim at is, to pass my time at my ease, and the recreations that
will most contribute to it, I take hold of, as little glorious and
exemplary as you will:
"Praetulerim . . . delirus inersque videri,
Dum mea delectent mala me, vel denique fallant,
Quam sapere, et ringi."
["I had rather seem mad and a sluggard, so that my defects are
agreeable to myself, or that I am not painfully conscious of them,
than be wise, and chaptious."—Hor., Ep., ii. 2, 126.]
But 'tis folly to think of doing anything that way. They go, they
come, they gallop and dance, and not a word of death. All this is very
fine; but withal, when it comes either to themselves, their wives, their
children, or friends, surprising them at unawares and unprepared, then,
what torment, what outcries, what madness and despair! Did you ever see
anything so subdued, so changed, and so confounded? A man must,
therefore, make more early provision for it; and this brutish
negligence, could it possibly lodge in the brain of any man of sense
(which I think utterly impossible), sells us its merchandise too dear.
Were it an enemy that could be avoided, I would then advise to borrow
arms even of cowardice itself; but seeing it is not, and that it will
catch you as well flying and playing the poltroon, as standing to't like
an honest man:—
"Nempe et fugacem persequitur virum,
Nec parcit imbellis juventae
Poplitibus timidoque tergo."
["He pursues the flying poltroon, nor spares the hamstrings of the
unwarlike youth who turns his back"—Hor., Ep., iii. 2, 14.]
And seeing that no temper of arms is of proof to secure us:—
"Ille licet ferro cautus, se condat et aere,
Mors tamen inclusum protrahet inde caput"
["Let him hide beneath iron or brass in his fear, death will pull
his head out of his armour."—Propertious iii. 18]
—let us learn bravely to stand our ground, and fight him. And to
begin to deprive him of the greatest advantage he has over us, let us
take a way quite contrary to the common course. Let us disarm him of his
novelty and strangeness, let us converse and be familiar with him, and
have nothing so frequent in our thoughts as death. Upon all occasions
represent him to our imagination in his every shape; at the stumbling of
a horse, at the falling of a tile, at the least prick with a pin, let us
presently consider, and say to ourselves, "Well, and what if it had been
death itself?" and, thereupon, let us encourage and fortify ourselves.
Let us evermore, amidst our jollity and feasting, set the remembrance of
our frail condition before our eyes, never suffering ourselves to be so
far transported with our delights, but that we have some intervals of
reflecting upon, and considering how many several ways this jollity of
ours tends to death, and with how many dangers it threatens it. The
Egyptians were wont to do after this manner, who in the height of their
feasting and mirth, caused a dried skeleton of a man to be brought into
the room to serve for a memento to their guests:
"Omnem crede diem tibi diluxisse supremum
Grata superveniet, quae non sperabitur, hora."
["Think each day when past is thy last; the next day, as unexpected,
will be the more welcome."—Hor., Ep., i. 4, 13.]
Where death waits for us is uncertain; let us look for him
everywhere. The premeditation of death is the premeditation of liberty;
he who has learned to die has unlearned to serve. There is nothing evil
in life for him who rightly comprehends that the privation of life is no
evil: to know, how to die delivers us from all subjection and
constraint. Paulus Emilius answered him whom the miserable King of
Macedon, his prisoner, sent to entreat him that he would not lead him in
his triumph, "Let him make that request to himself."—[ Plutarch, Life of
Paulus Aemilius, c. 17; Cicero, Tusc., v. 40.]
In truth, in all things, if nature do not help a little, it is very
hard for art and industry to perform anything to purpose. I am in my own
nature not melancholic, but meditative; and there is nothing I have more
continually entertained myself withal than imaginations of death, even
in the most wanton time of my age:
"Jucundum quum aetas florida ver ageret."
["When my florid age rejoiced in pleasant spring."
—Catullus, lxviii.]
In the company of ladies, and at games, some have perhaps thought me
possessed with some jealousy, or the uncertainty of some hope, whilst I
was entertaining myself with the remembrance of some one, surprised, a
few days before, with a burning fever of which he died, returning from
an entertainment like this, with his head full of idle fancies of love
and jollity, as mine was then, and that, for aught I knew, the
same-destiny was attending me.
"Jam fuerit, nec post unquam revocare licebit."
["Presently the present will have gone, never to be recalled."
Lucretius, iii. 928.]
Yet did not this thought wrinkle my forehead any more than any other.
It is impossible but we must feel a sting in such imaginations as these,
at first; but with often turning and returning them in one's mind, they,
at last, become so familiar as to be no trouble at all: otherwise, I,
for my part, should be in a perpetual fright and frenzy; for never man
was so distrustful of his life, never man so uncertain as to its
duration. Neither health, which I have hitherto ever enjoyed very strong
and vigorous, and very seldom interrupted, does prolong, nor sickness
contract my hopes. Every minute, methinks, I am escaping, and it
eternally runs in my mind, that what may be done to-morrow, may be done
to-day. Hazards and dangers do, in truth, little or nothing hasten our
end; and if we consider how many thousands more remain and hang over our
heads, besides the accident that immediately threatens us, we shall find
that the sound and the sick, those that are abroad at sea, and those
that sit by the fire, those who are engaged in battle, and those who sit
idle at home, are the one as near it as the other.
"Nemo altero fragilior est; nemo in crastinum sui certior."
["No man is more fragile than another: no man more certain than
another of to-morrow."—Seneca, Ep., 91.]
For anything I have to do before I die, the longest leisure would
appear too short, were it but an hour's business I had to do.
A friend of mine the other day turning over my tablets, found therein
a memorandum of something I would have done after my decease, whereupon
I told him, as it was really true, that though I was no more than a
league's distance only from my own house, and merry and well, yet when
that thing came into my head, I made haste to write it down there,
because I was not certain to live till I came home. As a man that am
eternally brooding over my own thoughts, and confine them to my own
particular concerns, I am at all hours as well prepared as I am ever
like to be, and death, whenever he shall come, can bring nothing along
with him I did not expect long before. We should always, as near as we
can, be booted and spurred, and ready to go, and, above all things, take
care, at that time, to have no business with any one but one's self:—
"Quid brevi fortes jaculamur avo
Multa?"
["Why for so short a life tease ourselves with so many projects?"
—Hor., Od., ii. 16, 17.]
for we shall there find work enough to do, without any need of
addition. One man complains, more than of death, that he is thereby
prevented of a glorious victory; another, that he must die before he has
married his daughter, or educated his children; a third seems only
troubled that he must lose the society of his wife; a fourth, the
conversation of his son, as the principal comfort and concern of his
being. For my part, I am, thanks be to God, at this instant in such a
condition, that I am ready to dislodge, whenever it shall please Him,
without regret for anything whatsoever. I disengage myself throughout
from all worldly relations; my leave is soon taken of all but myself.
Never did any one prepare to bid adieu to the world more absolutely and
unreservedly, and to shake hands with all manner of interest in it, than
I expect to do. The deadest deaths are the best:
"'Miser, O miser,' aiunt, 'omnia ademit
Una dies infesta mihi tot praemia vitae.'"
["'Wretch that I am,' they cry, 'one fatal day has deprived me of
all joys of life.'"—Lucretius, iii. 911.]
And the builder,
"Manuet," says he, "opera interrupta, minaeque
Murorum ingentes."
["The works remain incomplete, the tall pinnacles of the walls
unmade."—AEneid, iv. 88.]
A man must design nothing that will require so much time to the
finishing, or, at least, with no such passionate desire to see it
brought to perfection. We are born to action:
"Quum moriar, medium solvar et inter opus."
["When I shall die, let it be doing that I had designed."
—Ovid, Amor., ii. 10, 36.]
I would always have a man to be doing, and, as much as in him lies,
to extend and spin out the offices of life; and then let death take me
planting my cabbages, indifferent to him, and still less of my gardens
not being finished. I saw one die, who, at his last gasp, complained of
nothing so much as that destiny was about to cut the thread of a
chronicle he was then compiling, when he was gone no farther than the
fifteenth or sixteenth of our kings:
"Illud in his rebus non addunt: nec tibi earum
jam desiderium rerum super insidet una."
["They do not add, that dying, we have no longer a desire to possess
things."—Lucretius, iii. 913.]
We are to discharge ourselves from these vulgar and hurtful humours.
To this purpose it was that men first appointed the places of sepulture
adjoining the churches, and in the most frequented places of the city,
to accustom, says Lycurgus, the common people, women, and children, that
they should not be startled at the sight of a corpse, and to the end,
that the continual spectacle of bones, graves, and funeral obsequies
should put us in mind of our frail condition:
"Quin etiam exhilarare viris convivia caede
Mos olim, et miscere epulis spectacula dira
Certantum ferro, saepe et super ipsa cadentum
Pocula, respersis non parco sanguine mensis."
["It was formerly the custom to enliven banquets with slaughter, and
to combine with the repast the dire spectacle of men contending with
the sword, the dying in many cases falling upon the cups, and
covering the tables with blood."—Silius Italicus, xi. 51.]
And as the Egyptians after their feasts were wont to present the
company with a great image of death, by one that cried out to them,
"Drink and be merry, for such shalt thou be when thou art dead"; so it
is my custom to have death not only in my imagination, but continually
in my mouth. Neither is there anything of which I am so inquisitive, and
delight to inform myself, as the manner of men's deaths, their words,
looks, and bearing; nor any places in history I am so intent upon; and
it is manifest enough, by my crowding in examples of this kind, that I
have a particular fancy for that subject. If I were a writer of books, I
would compile a register, with a comment, of the various deaths of men:
he who should teach men to die would at the same time teach them to
live. Dicarchus made one, to which he gave that title; but it was
designed for another and less profitable end.
Peradventure, some one may object, that the pain and terror of dying
so infinitely exceed all manner of imagination, that the best fencer
will be quite out of his play when it comes to the push. Let them say
what they will: to premeditate is doubtless a very great advantage; and
besides, is it nothing to go so far, at least, without disturbance or
alteration? Moreover, Nature herself assists and encourages us: if the
death be sudden and violent, we have not leisure to fear; if otherwise,
I perceive that as I engage further in my disease, I naturally enter
into a certain loathing and disdain of life. I find I have much more ado
to digest this resolution of dying, when I am well in health, than when
languishing of a fever; and by how much I have less to do with the
commodities of life, by reason that I begin to lose the use and pleasure
of them, by so much I look upon death with less terror. Which makes me
hope, that the further I remove from the first, and the nearer I
approach to the latter, I shall the more easily exchange the one for the
other. And, as I have experienced in other occurrences, that, as Caesar
says, things often appear greater to us at distance than near at hand, I
have found, that being well, I have had maladies in much greater horror
than when really afflicted with them. The vigour wherein I now am, the
cheerfulness and delight wherein I now live, make the contrary estate
appear in so great a disproportion to my present condition, that, by
imagination, I magnify those inconveniences by one-half, and apprehend
them to be much more troublesome, than I find them really to be, when
they lie the most heavy upon me; I hope to find death the same.
Let us but observe in the ordinary changes and declinations we daily
suffer, how nature deprives us of the light and sense of our bodily
decay. What remains to an old man of the vigour of his youth and better
days?
"Heu! senibus vitae portio quanta manet."
["Alas, to old men what portion of life remains!"—-Maximian, vel
Pseudo-Gallus, i. 16.]
Caesar, to an old weather-beaten soldier of his guards, who came to
ask him leave that he might kill himself, taking notice of his withered
body and decrepit motion, pleasantly answered, "Thou fanciest, then,
that thou art yet alive."—[Seneca, Ep., 77.]—Should a man fall into this
condition on the sudden, I do not think humanity capable of enduring
such a change: but nature, leading us by the hand, an easy and, as it
were, an insensible pace, step by step conducts us to that miserable
state, and by that means makes it familiar to us, so that we are
insensible of the stroke when our youth dies in us, though it be really
a harder death than the final dissolution of a languishing body, than
the death of old age; forasmuch as the fall is not so great from an
uneasy being to none at all, as it is from a sprightly and flourishing
being to one that is troublesome and painful. The body, bent and bowed,
has less force to support a burden; and it is the same with the soul,
and therefore it is, that we are to raise her up firm and erect against
the power of this adversary. For, as it is impossible she should ever be
at rest, whilst she stands in fear of it; so, if she once can assure
herself, she may boast (which is a thing as it were surpassing human
condition) that it is impossible that disquiet, anxiety, or fear, or any
other disturbance, should inhabit or have any place in her:
"Non vulnus instants Tyranni
Mentha cadi solida, neque Auster
Dux inquieti turbidus Adriae,
Nec fulminantis magna Jovis manus."
["Not the menacing look of a tyrant shakes her well-settled soul,
nor turbulent Auster, the prince of the stormy Adriatic, nor yet the
strong hand of thundering Jove, such a temper moves."
—Hor., Od., iii. 3, 3.]
She is then become sovereign of all her lusts and passions, mistress
of necessity, shame, poverty, and all the other injuries of fortune. Let
us, therefore, as many of us as can, get this advantage; 'tis the true
and sovereign liberty here on earth, that fortifies us wherewithal to
defy violence and injustice, and to contemn prisons and chains:
"In manicis et
Compedibus saevo te sub custode tenebo.
Ipse Deus, simul atque volam, me solvet. Opinor,
Hoc sentit; moriar; mors ultima linea rerum est."
["I will keep thee in fetters and chains, in custody of a
savage keeper.—A god will when I ask Him, set me free.
This god I think is death. Death is the term of all things."
—Hor., Ep., i. 16, 76.]
Our very religion itself has no surer human foundation than the
contempt of death. Not only the argument of reason invites us to it—for
why should we fear to lose a thing, which being lost, cannot be
lamented? —but, also, seeing we are threatened by so many sorts of
death, is it not infinitely worse eternally to fear them all, than once
to undergo one of them? And what matters it, when it shall happen, since
it is inevitable? To him that told Socrates, "The thirty tyrants have
sentenced thee to death"; "And nature them," said he.—[Socrates was not
condemned to death by the thirty tyrants, but by the Athenians.-Diogenes
Laertius, ii.35.]— What a ridiculous thing it is to trouble ourselves
about taking the only step that is to deliver us from all trouble! As
our birth brought us the birth of all things, so in our death is the
death of all things included. And therefore to lament that we shall not
be alive a hundred years hence, is the same folly as to be sorry we were
not alive a hundred years ago. Death is the beginning of another life.
So did we weep, and so much it cost us to enter into this, and so did we
put off our former veil in entering into it. Nothing can be a grievance
that is but once. Is it reasonable so long to fear a thing that will so
soon be despatched? Long life, and short, are by death made all one; for
there is no long, nor short, to things that are no more. Aristotle tells
us that there are certain little beasts upon the banks of the river
Hypanis, that never live above a day: they which die at eight of the
clock in the morning, die in their youth, and those that die at five in
the evening, in their decrepitude: which of us would not laugh to see
this moment of continuance put into the consideration of weal or woe?
The most and the least, of ours, in comparison with eternity, or yet
with the duration of mountains, rivers, stars, trees, and even of some
animals, is no less ridiculous.—[ Seneca, Consol. ad Marciam, c. 20.]
But nature compels us to it. "Go out of this world," says she, "as
you entered into it; the same pass you made from death to life, without
passion or fear, the same, after the same manner, repeat from life to
death. Your death is a part of the order of the universe, 'tis a part of
the life of the world.
"Inter se mortales mutua vivunt
................................
Et, quasi cursores, vitai lampada tradunt."
["Mortals, amongst themselves, live by turns, and, like the runners
in the games, give up the lamp, when they have won the race, to the
next comer.—" Lucretius, ii. 75, 78.]
"Shall I exchange for you this beautiful contexture of things? 'Tis
the condition of your creation; death is a part of you, and whilst you
endeavour to evade it, you evade yourselves. This very being of yours
that you now enjoy is equally divided betwixt life and death. The day of
your birth is one day's advance towards the grave:
"Prima, qux vitam dedit, hora carpsit."
["The first hour that gave us life took away also an hour."
—Seneca, Her. Fur., 3 Chor. 874.]
"Nascentes morimur, finisque ab origine pendet."
["As we are born we die, and the end commences with the beginning."
—Manilius, Ast., iv. 16.]
"All the whole time you live, you purloin from life and live at the
expense of life itself. The perpetual work of your life is but to lay
the foundation of death. You are in death, whilst you are in life,
because you still are after death, when you are no more alive; or, if
you had rather have it so, you are dead after life, but dying all the
while you live; and death handles the dying much more rudely than the
dead, and more sensibly and essentially. If you have made your profit of
life, you have had enough of it; go your way satisfied.
"Cur non ut plenus vita; conviva recedis?"
["Why not depart from life as a sated guest from a feast?
"Lucretius, iii. 951.]
"If you have not known how to make the best use of it, if it was
unprofitable to you, what need you care to lose it, to what end would
you desire longer to keep it?
"'Cur amplius addere quaeris,
Rursum quod pereat male, et ingratum occidat omne?'
["Why seek to add longer life, merely to renew ill-spent time, and
be again tormented?"—Lucretius, iii. 914.]
"Life in itself is neither good nor evil; it is the scene of good or
evil as you make it.' And, if you have lived a day, you have seen all:
one day is equal and like to all other days. There is no other light, no
other shade; this very sun, this moon, these very stars, this very order
and disposition of things, is the same your ancestors enjoyed, and that
shall also entertain your posterity:
"'Non alium videre patres, aliumve nepotes
Aspicient.'
["Your grandsires saw no other thing; nor will your posterity."
—Manilius, i. 529.]
"And, come the worst that can come, the distribution and variety of
all the acts of my comedy are performed in a year. If you have observed
the revolution of my four seasons, they comprehend the infancy, the
youth, the virility, and the old age of the world: the year has played
his part, and knows no other art but to begin again; it will always be
the same thing:
"'Versamur ibidem, atque insumus usque.'
["We are turning in the same circle, ever therein confined."
—Lucretius, iii. 1093.]
"'Atque in se sua per vestigia volvitur annus.'
["The year is ever turning around in the same footsteps."
—Virgil, Georg., ii. 402.]
"I am not prepared to create for you any new recreations:
"'Nam tibi prxterea quod machiner, inveniamque
Quod placeat, nihil est; eadem sunt omnia semper.'
["I can devise, nor find anything else to please you: 'tis the same
thing over and over again."—Lucretius iii. 957]
"Give place to others, as others have given place to you. Equality is
the soul of equity. Who can complain of being comprehended in the same
destiny, wherein all are involved? Besides, live as long as you can, you
shall by that nothing shorten the space you are to be dead; 'tis all to
no purpose; you shall be every whit as long in the condition you so much
fear, as if you had died at nurse:
"'Licet quot vis vivendo vincere secla,
Mors aeterna tamen nihilominus illa manebit.'
["Live triumphing over as many ages as you will, death still will
remain eternal."—Lucretius, iii. 1103]
"And yet I will place you in such a condition as you shall have no
reason to be displeased.
"'In vera nescis nullum fore morte alium te,
Qui possit vivus tibi to lugere peremptum,
Stansque jacentem.'
["Know you not that, when dead, there can be no other living self to
lament you dead, standing on your grave."—Idem., ibid., 898.]
"Nor shall you so much as wish for the life you are so concerned
about:
"'Nec sibi enim quisquam tum se vitamque requirit.
..................................................
"'Nec desiderium nostri nos afficit ullum.'
"Death is less to be feared than nothing, if there could be anything
less than nothing.
"'Multo . . . mortem minus ad nos esse putandium,
Si minus esse potest, quam quod nihil esse videmus.'
"Neither can it any way concern you, whether you are living or dead:
living, by reason that you are still in being; dead, because you are no
more. Moreover, no one dies before his hour: the time you leave behind
was no more yours than that was lapsed and gone before you came into the
world; nor does it any more concern you.
"'Respice enim, quam nil ad nos anteacta vetustas
Temporis aeterni fuerit.'
["Consider how as nothing to us is the old age of times past."
—Lucretius iii. 985]
Wherever your life ends, it is all there. The utility of living
consists not in the length of days, but in the use of time; a man may
have lived long, and yet lived but a little. Make use of time while it
is present with you. It depends upon your will, and not upon the number
of days, to have a sufficient length of life. Is it possible you can
imagine never to arrive at the place towards which you are continually
going? and yet there is no journey but hath its end. And, if company
will make it more pleasant or more easy to you, does not all the world
go the self-same way?
"'Omnia te, vita perfuncta, sequentur.'
["All things, then, life over, must follow thee."
—Lucretius, iii. 981.]
"Does not all the world dance the same brawl that you do? Is there
anything that does not grow old, as well as you? A thousand men, a
thousand animals, a thousand other creatures, die at the same moment
that you die:
"'Nam nox nulla diem, neque noctem aurora sequuta est,
Quae non audierit mistos vagitibus aegris
Ploratus, mortis comites et funeris atri.'
["No night has followed day, no day has followed night, in which
there has not been heard sobs and sorrowing cries, the companions of
death and funerals."—Lucretius, v. 579.]
"To what end should you endeavour to draw back, if there be no
possibility to evade it? you have seen examples enough of those who have
been well pleased to die, as thereby delivered from heavy miseries; but
have you ever found any who have been dissatisfied with dying? It must,
therefore, needs be very foolish to condemn a thing you have neither
experimented in your own person, nor by that of any other. Why dost thou
complain of me and of destiny? Do we do thee any wrong? Is it for thee
to govern us, or for us to govern thee? Though, peradventure, thy age
may not be accomplished, yet thy life is: a man of low stature is as
much a man as a giant; neither men nor their lives are measured by the
ell. Chiron refused to be immortal, when he was acquainted with the
conditions under which he was to enjoy it, by the god of time itself and
its duration, his father Saturn. Do but seriously consider how much more
insupportable and painful an immortal life would be to man than what I
have already given him. If you had not death, you would eternally curse
me for having deprived you of it; I have mixed a little bitterness with
it, to the end, that seeing of what convenience it is, you might not too
greedily and indiscreetly seek and embrace it: and that you might be so
established in this moderation, as neither to nauseate life, nor have
any antipathy for dying, which I have decreed you shall once do, I have
tempered the one and the other betwixt pleasure and pain. It was I that
taught Thales, the most eminent of your sages, that to live and to die
were indifferent; which made him, very wisely, answer him, 'Why then he
did not die?' 'Because,' said he, 'it is indifferent.'—[Diogenes
Laertius, i. 35.]—Water, earth, air, and fire, and the other parts of
this creation of mine, are no more instruments of thy life than they are
of thy death. Why dost thou fear thy last day? it contributes no more to
thy dissolution, than every one of the rest: the last step is not the
cause of lassitude: it does not confess it. Every day travels towards
death; the last only arrives at it." These are the good lessons our
mother Nature teaches.
I have often considered with myself whence it should proceed, that in
war the image of death, whether we look upon it in ourselves or in
others, should, without comparison, appear less dreadful than at home in
our own houses (for if it were not so, it would be an army of doctors
and whining milksops), and that being still in all places the same,
there should be, notwithstanding, much more assurance in peasants and
the meaner sort of people, than in others of better quality. I believe,
in truth, that it is those terrible ceremonies and preparations
wherewith we set it out, that more terrify us than the thing itself; a
new, quite contrary way of living; the cries of mothers, wives, and
children; the visits of astounded and afflicted friends; the attendance
of pale and blubbering servants; a dark room, set round with burning
tapers; our beds environed with physicians and divines; in sum, nothing
but ghostliness and horror round about us; we seem dead and buried
already. Children are afraid even of those they are best acquainted
with, when disguised in a visor; and so 'tis with us; the visor must be
removed as well from things as from persons, that being taken away, we
shall find nothing underneath but the very same death that a mean
servant or a poor chambermaid died a day or two ago, without any manner
of apprehension. Happy is the death that deprives us of leisure for
preparing such ceremonials.
CHAPTER XX——OF THE FORCE OF IMAGINATION
"Fortis imaginatio generat casum," say the schoolmen.
["A strong imagination begets the event itself."—Axiom. Scholast.]
I am one of those who are most sensible of the power of imagination:
every one is jostled by it, but some are overthrown by it. It has a very
piercing impression upon me; and I make it my business to avoid, wanting
force to resist it. I could live by the sole help of healthful and jolly
company: the very sight of another's pain materially pains me, and I
often usurp the sensations of another person. A perpetual cough in
another tickles my lungs and throat. I more unwillingly visit the sick
in whom by love and duty I am interested, than those I care not for, to
whom I less look. I take possession of the disease I am concerned at,
and take it to myself. I do not at all wonder that fancy should give
fevers and sometimes kill such as allow it too much scope, and are too
willing to entertain it. Simon Thomas was a great physician of his time:
I remember, that happening one day at Toulouse to meet him at a rich old
fellow's house, who was troubled with weak lungs, and discoursing with
the patient about the method of his cure, he told him, that one thing
which would be very conducive to it, was to give me such occasion to be
pleased with his company, that I might come often to see him, by which
means, and by fixing his eyes upon the freshness of my complexion, and
his imagination upon the sprightliness and vigour that glowed in my
youth, and possessing all his senses with the flourishing age wherein I
then was, his habit of body might, peradventure, be amended; but he
forgot to say that mine, at the same time, might be made worse. Gallus
Vibius so much bent his mind to find out the essence and motions of
madness, that, in the end, he himself went out of his wits, and to such
a degree, that he could never after recover his judgment, and might brag
that he was become a fool by too much wisdom. Some there are who through
fear anticipate the hangman; and there was the man, whose eyes being
unbound to have his pardon read to him, was found stark dead upon the
scaffold, by the stroke of imagination. We start, tremble, turn pale,
and blush, as we are variously moved by imagination; and, being a-bed,
feel our bodies agitated with its power to that degree, as even
sometimes to expiring. And boiling youth, when fast asleep, grows so
warm with fancy, as in a dream to satisfy amorous desires:—
"Ut, quasi transactis saepe omnibu rebu, profundant
Fluminis ingentes, fluctus, vestemque cruentent."
Although it be no new thing to see horns grown in a night on the
forehead of one that had none when he went to bed, notwithstanding, what
befell Cippus, King of Italy, is memorable; who having one day been a
very delighted spectator of a bullfight, and having all the night
dreamed that he had horns on his head, did, by the force of imagination,
really cause them to grow there. Passion gave to the son of Croesus the
voice which nature had denied him. And Antiochus fell into a fever,
inflamed with the beauty of Stratonice, too deeply imprinted in his
soul. Pliny pretends to have seen Lucius Cossitius, who from a woman was
turned into a man upon her very wedding-day. Pontanus and others report
the like metamorphosis to have happened in these latter days in Italy.
And, through the vehement desire of him and his mother:
"Volta puer solvit, quae foemina voverat, Iphis."
Myself passing by Vitry le Francois, saw a man the Bishop of Soissons
had, in confirmation, called Germain, whom all the inhabitants of the
place had known to be a girl till two-and-twenty years of age, called
Mary. He was, at the time of my being there, very full of beard, old,
and not married. He told us, that by straining himself in a leap his
male organs came out; and the girls of that place have, to this day, a
song, wherein they advise one another not to take too great strides, for
fear of being turned into men, as Mary Germain was. It is no wonder if
this sort of accident frequently happen; for if imagination have any
power in such things, it is so continually and vigorously bent upon this
subject, that to the end it may not so often relapse into the same
thought and violence of desire, it were better, once for all, to give
these young wenches the things they long for.
Some attribute the scars of King Dagobert and of St. Francis to the
force of imagination. It is said, that by it bodies will sometimes be
removed from their places; and Celsus tells us of a priest whose soul
would be ravished into such an ecstasy that the body would, for a long
time, remain without sense or respiration. St. Augustine makes mention
of another, who, upon the hearing of any lamentable or doleful cries,
would presently fall into a swoon, and be so far out of himself, that it
was in vain to call, bawl in his ears, pinch or burn him, till he
voluntarily came to himself; and then he would say, that he had heard
voices as it were afar off, and did feel when they pinched and burned
him; and, to prove that this was no obstinate dissimulation in defiance
of his sense of feeling, it was manifest, that all the while he had
neither pulse nor breathing.
'Tis very probable, that visions, enchantments, and all extraordinary
effects of that nature, derive their credit principally from the power
of imagination, working and making its chiefest impression upon vulgar
and more easy souls, whose belief is so strangely imposed upon, as to
think they see what they do not see.
I am not satisfied whether those pleasant ligatures—[Les nouements
d'aiguillettes, as they were called, knots tied by some one, at a
wedding, on a strip of leather, cotton, or silk, and which, especially
when passed through the wedding-ring, were supposed to have the magical
effect of preventing a consummation of the marriage until they were
untied. See Louandre, La Sorcellerie, 1853, p. 73. The same superstition
and appliance existed in England.]—with which this age of ours is so
occupied, that there is almost no other talk, are not mere voluntary
impressions of apprehension and fear; for I know, by experience, in the
case of a particular friend of mine, one for whom I can be as
responsible as for myself, and a man that cannot possibly fall under any
manner of suspicion of insufficiency, and as little of being enchanted,
who having heard a companion of his make a relation of an unusual
frigidity that surprised him at a very unseasonable time; being
afterwards himself engaged upon the same account, the horror of the
former story on a sudden so strangely possessed his imagination, that he
ran the same fortune the other had done; and from that time forward, the
scurvy remembrance of his disaster running in his mind and tyrannising
over him, he was subject to relapse into the same misfortune. He found
some remedy, however, for this fancy in another fancy, by himself
frankly confessing and declaring beforehand to the party with whom he
was to have to do, this subjection of his, by which means, the agitation
of his soul was, in some sort, appeased; and knowing that, now, some
such misbehaviour was expected from him, the restraint upon his
faculties grew less. And afterwards, at such times as he was in no such
apprehension, when setting about the act (his thoughts being then
disengaged and free, and his body in its true and natural estate) he was
at leisure to cause the part to be handled and communicated to the
knowledge of the other party, he was totally freed from that vexatious
infirmity. After a man has once done a woman right, he is never after in
danger of misbehaving himself with that person, unless upon the account
of some excusable weakness. Neither is this disaster to be feared, but
in adventures, where the soul is overextended with desire or respect,
and, especially, where the opportunity is of an unforeseen and pressing
nature; in those cases, there is no means for a man to defend himself
from such a surprise, as shall put him altogether out of sorts. I have
known some, who have secured themselves from this mischance, by coming
half sated elsewhere, purposely to abate the ardour of the fury, and
others, who, being grown old, find themselves less impotent by being
less able; and one, who found an advantage in being assured by a friend
of his, that he had a counter-charm of enchantments that would secure
him from this disgrace. The story itself is not, much amiss, and
therefore you shall have it.
A Count of a very great family, and with whom I was very intimate,
being married to a fair lady, who had formerly been courted by one who
was at the wedding, all his friends were in very great fear; but
especially an old lady his kinswoman, who had the ordering of the
solemnity, and in whose house it was kept, suspecting his rival would
offer foul play by these sorceries. Which fear she communicated to me. I
bade her rely upon me: I had, by chance, about me a certain flat plate
of gold, whereon were graven some celestial figures, supposed good
against sunstroke or pains in the head, being applied to the suture:
where, that it might the better remain firm, it was sewed to a ribbon to
be tied under the chin; a foppery cousin-german to this of which I am
speaking. Jaques Pelletier, who lived in my house, had presented this to
me for a singular rarity. I had a fancy to make some use of this knack,
and therefore privately told the Count, that he might possibly run the
same fortune other bridegrooms had sometimes done, especially some one
being in the house, who, no doubt, would be glad to do him such a
courtesy: but let him boldly go to bed. For I would do him the office of
a friend, and, if need were, would not spare a miracle it was in my
power to do, provided he would engage to me, upon his honour, to keep it
to himself; and only, when they came to bring him his caudle,—[A custom
in France to bring the bridegroom a caudle in the middle of the night on
his wedding-night]— if matters had not gone well with him, to give me
such a sign, and leave the rest to me. Now he had had his ears so
battered, and his mind so prepossessed with the eternal tattle of this
business, that when he came to't, he did really find himself tied with
the trouble of his imagination, and, accordingly, at the time appointed,
gave me the sign. Whereupon, I whispered him in the ear, that he should
rise, under pretence of putting us out of the room, and after a jesting
manner pull my nightgown from my shoulders—we were of much about the
same height— throw it over his own, and there keep it till he had
performed what I had appointed him to do, which was, that when we were
all gone out of the chamber, he should withdraw to make water, should
three times repeat such and such words, and as often do such and such
actions; that at every of the three times, he should tie the ribbon I
put into his hand about his middle, and be sure to place the medal that
was fastened to it, the figures in such a posture, exactly upon his
reins, which being done, and having the last of the three times so well
girt and fast tied the ribbon that it could neither untie nor slip from
its place, let him confidently return to his business, and withal not
forget to spread my gown upon the bed, so that it might be sure to cover
them both. These ape's tricks are the main of the effect, our fancy
being so far seduced as to believe that such strange means must, of
necessity, proceed from some abstruse science: their very inanity gives
them weight and reverence. And, certain it is, that my figures approved
themselves more venereal than solar, more active than prohibitive. 'Twas
a sudden whimsey, mixed with a little curiosity, that made me do a thing
so contrary to my nature; for I am an enemy to all subtle and
counterfeit actions, and abominate all manner of trickery, though it be
for sport, and to an advantage; for though the action may not be vicious
in itself, its mode is vicious.
Amasis, King of Egypt, having married Laodice, a very beautiful Greek
virgin, though noted for his abilities elsewhere, found himself quite
another man with his wife, and could by no means enjoy her; at which he
was so enraged, that he threatened to kill her, suspecting her to be a
witch. As 'tis usual in things that consist in fancy, she put him upon
devotion, and having accordingly made his vows to Venus, he found
himself divinely restored the very first night after his oblations and
sacrifices. Now women are to blame to entertain us with that disdainful,
coy, and angry countenance, which extinguishes our vigour, as it kindles
our desire; which made the daughter-in-law of Pythagoras—[Theano, the
lady in question was the wife, not the daughter-in-law of Pythagoras.]—
say, "That the woman who goes to bed to a man, must put off her modesty
with her petticoat, and put it on again with the same." The soul of the
assailant, being disturbed with many several alarms, readily loses the
power of performance; and whoever the imagination has once put this
trick upon, and confounded with the shame of it (and she never does it
but at the first acquaintance, by reason men are then more ardent and
eager, and also, at this first account a man gives of himself, he is
much more timorous of miscarrying), having made an ill beginning, he
enters into such fever and despite at the accident, as are apt to remain
and continue with him upon following occasions.
Married people, having all their time before them, ought never to
compel or so much as to offer at the feat, if they do not find
themselves quite ready: and it is less unseemly to fail of handselling
the nuptial sheets, when a man perceives himself full of agitation and
trembling, and to await another opportunity at more private and more
composed leisure, than to make himself perpetually miserable, for having
misbehaved himself and been baffled at the first assault. Till
possession be taken, a man that knows himself subject to this infirmity,
should leisurely and by degrees make several little trials and light
offers, without obstinately attempting at once, to Force an absolute
conquest over his own mutinous and indisposed faculties. Such as know
their members to be naturally obedient, need take no other care but only
to counterplot their fantasies.
The indocile liberty of this member is very remarkable, so
importunately unruly in its tumidity and impatience, when we do not
require it, and so unseasonably disobedient, when we stand most in need
of it: so imperiously contesting in authority with the will, and with so
much haughty obstinacy denying all solicitation, both of hand and mind.
And yet, though his rebellion is so universally complained of, and that
proof is thence deduced to condemn him, if he had, nevertheless, feed me
to plead his cause, I should peradventure, bring the rest of his
fellow-members into suspicion of complotting this mischief against him,
out of pure envy at the importance and pleasure especial to his
employment; and to have, by confederacy, armed the whole world against
him, by malevolently charging him alone, with their common offence. For
let any one consider, whether there is any one part of our bodies that
does not often refuse to perform its office at the precept of the will,
and that does not often exercise its function in defiance of her
command. They have every one of them passions of their own, that rouse
and awaken, stupefy and benumb them, without our leave or consent. How
often do the involuntary motions of the countenance discover our inward
thoughts, and betray our most private secrets to the bystanders. The
same cause that animates this member, does also, without our knowledge,
animate the lungs, pulse, and heart, the sight of a pleasing object
imperceptibly diffusing a flame through all our parts, with a feverish
motion. Is there nothing but these veins and muscles that swell and flag
without the consent, not only of the will, but even of our knowledge
also? We do not command our hairs to stand on end, nor our skin to
shiver either with fear or desire; the hands often convey themselves to
parts to which we do not direct them; the tongue will be interdict, and
the voice congealed, when we know not how to help it. When we have
nothing to eat, and would willingly forbid it, the appetite does not,
for all that, forbear to stir up the parts that are subject to it, no
more nor less than the other appetite we were speaking of, and in like
manner, as unseasonably leaves us, when it thinks fit. The vessels that
serve to discharge the belly have their own proper dilatations and
compressions, without and beyond our concurrence, as well as those which
are destined to purge the reins; and that which, to justify the
prerogative of the will, St. Augustine urges, of having seen a man who
could command his rear to discharge as often together as he pleased,
Vives, his commentator, yet further fortifies with another example in
his time,—of one that could break wind in tune; but these cases do not
suppose any more pure obedience in that part; for is anything commonly
more tumultuary or indiscreet? To which let me add, that I myself knew
one so rude and ungoverned, as for forty years together made his master
vent with one continued and unintermitted outbursting, and 'tis like
will do so till he die of it. And I could heartily wish, that I only
knew by reading, how often a man's belly, by the denial of one single
puff, brings him to the very door of an exceeding painful death; and
that the emperor,—[The Emperor Claudius, who, however, according to
Suetonius (Vita, c. 32), only intended to authorise this singular
privilege by an edict.]—who gave liberty to let fly in all places, had,
at the same time, given us power to do it. But for our will, in whose
behalf we prefer this accusation, with how much greater probability may
we reproach herself with mutiny and sedition, for her irregularity and
disobedience? Does she always will what we would have her to do? Does
she not often will what we forbid her to will, and that to our manifest
prejudice? Does she suffer herself, more than any of the rest, to be
governed and directed by the results of our reason? To conclude, I
should move, in the behalf of the gentleman, my client, it might be
considered, that in this fact, his cause being inseparably and
indistinctly conjoined with an accessory, yet he only is called in
question, and that by arguments and accusations, which cannot be charged
upon the other; whose business, indeed, it is sometimes inopportunely to
invite, but never to refuse, and invite, moreover, after a tacit and
quiet manner; and therefore is the malice and injustice of his accusers
most manifestly apparent. But be it how it will, protesting against the
proceedings of the advocates and judges, nature will, in the meantime,
proceed after her own way, who had done but well, had she endowed this
member with some particular privilege; the author of the sole immortal
work of mortals; a divine work, according to Socrates; and love, the
desire of immortality, and himself an immortal demon.
Some one, perhaps, by such an effect of imagination may have had the
good luck to leave behind him here, the scrofula, which his companion
who has come after, has carried with him into Spain. And 'tis for this
reason you may see why men in such cases require a mind prepared for the
thing that is to be done. Why do the physicians possess, before hand,
their patients' credulity with so many false promises of cure, if not to
the end, that the effect of imagination may supply the imposture of
their decoctions? They know very well, that a great master of their
trade has given it under his hand, that he has known some with whom the
very sight of physic would work. All which conceits come now into my
head, by the remembrance of a story was told me by a domestic apothecary
of my father's, a blunt Swiss, a nation not much addicted to vanity and
lying, of a merchant he had long known at Toulouse, who being a
valetudinary, and much afflicted with the stone, had often occasion to
take clysters, of which he caused several sorts to be prescribed him by
the physicians, acccording to the accidents of his disease; which, being
brought him, and none of the usual forms, as feeling if it were not too
hot, and the like, being omitted, he lay down, the syringe advanced, and
all ceremonies performed, injection alone excepted; after which, the
apothecary being gone, and the patient accommodated as if he had really
received a clyster, he found the same operation and effect that those do
who have taken one indeed; and if at any time the physician did not find
the operation sufficient, he would usually give him two or three more
doses, after the same manner. And the fellow swore, that to save charges
(for he paid as if he had really taken them) this sick man's wife,
having sometimes made trial of warm water only, the effect discovered
the cheat, and finding these would do no good, was fain to return to the
old way.
A woman fancying she had swallowed a pin in a piece of bread, cried
and lamented as though she had an intolerable pain in her throat, where
she thought she felt it stick; but an ingenious fellow that was brought
to her, seeing no outward tumour nor alteration, supposing it to be only
a conceit taken at some crust of bread that had hurt her as it went
down, caused her to vomit, and, unseen, threw a crooked pin into the
basin, which the woman no sooner saw, but believing she had cast it up,
she presently found herself eased of her pain. I myself knew a
gentleman, who having treated a large company at his house, three or
four days after bragged in jest (for there was no such thing), that he
had made them eat of a baked cat; at which, a young gentlewoman, who had
been at the feast, took such a horror, that falling into a violent
vomiting and fever, there was no possible means to save her. Even brute
beasts are subject to the force of imagination as well as we; witness
dogs, who die of grief for the loss of their masters; and bark and
tremble and start in their sleep; so horses will kick and whinny in
their sleep.
Now all this may be attributed to the close affinity and relation
betwixt the soul and the body intercommunicating their fortunes; but
'tis quite another thing when the imagination works not only upon one's
own particular body, but upon that of others also. And as an infected
body communicates its malady to those that approach or live near it, as
we see in the plague, the smallpox, and sore eyes, that run through
whole families and cities:—
"Dum spectant oculi laesos, laeduntur et ipsi;
Multaque corporibus transitione nocent."
["When we look at people with sore eyes, our own eyes become sore.
Many things are hurtful to our bodies by transition."
—Ovid, De Rem. Amor., 615.]
—so the imagination, being vehemently agitated, darts out infection
capable of offending the foreign object. The ancients had an opinion of
certain women of Scythia, that being animated and enraged against any
one, they killed him only with their looks. Tortoises and ostriches
hatch their eggs with only looking on them, which infers that their eyes
have in them some ejaculative virtue. And the eyes of witches are said
to be assailant and hurtful:—
"Nescio quis teneros oculus mihi fascinat agnos."
["Some eye, I know not whose is bewitching my tender lambs."
—Virgil, Eclog., iii. 103.]
Magicians are no very good authority with me. But we experimentally
see that women impart the marks of their fancy to the children they
carry in the womb; witness her that was brought to bed of a Moor; and
there was presented to Charles the Emperor and King of Bohemia, a girl
from about Pisa, all over rough and covered with hair, whom her mother
said to be so conceived by reason of a picture of St. John the Baptist,
that hung within the curtains of her bed.
It is the same with beasts; witness Jacob's sheep, and the hares and
partridges that the snow turns white upon the mountains. There was at my
house, a little while ago, a cat seen watching a bird upon the top of a
tree: these, for some time, mutually fixing their eyes one upon another,
the bird at last let herself fall dead into the cat's claws, either
dazzled by the force of its own imagination, or drawn by some attractive
power of the cat. Such as are addicted to the pleasures of the field,
have, I make no question, heard the story of the falconer, who having
earnestly fixed his eyes upon a kite in the air; laid a wager that he
would bring her down with the sole power of his sight, and did so, as it
was said; for the tales I borrow I charge upon the consciences of those
from whom I have them. The discourses are my own, and found themselves
upon the proofs of reason, not of experience; to which every one has
liberty to add his own examples; and who has none, let him not forbear,
the number and varieties of accidents considered, to believe that there
are plenty of them; if I do not apply them well, let some other do it
for me. And, also, in the subject of which I treat, our manners and
motions, testimonies and instances; how fabulous soever, provided they
are possible, serve as well as the true; whether they have really
happened or no, at Rome or Paris, to John or Peter, 'tis still within
the verge of human capacity, which serves me to good use. I see, and
make my advantage of it, as well in shadow as in substance; and amongst
the various readings thereof in history, I cull out the most rare and
memorable to fit my own turn. There are authors whose only end and
design it is to give an account of things that have happened; mine, if I
could arrive unto it, should be to deliver of what may happen. There is
a just liberty allowed in the schools, of supposing similitudes, when
they have none at hand. I do not, however, make any use of that
privilege, and as to that matter, in superstitious religion, surpass all
historical authority. In the examples which I here bring in, of what I
have heard, read, done, or said, I have forbidden myself to dare to
alter even the most light and indifferent circumstances; my conscience
does not falsify one tittle; what my ignorance may do, I cannot say.
And this it is that makes me sometimes doubt in my own mind, whether
a divine, or a philosopher, and such men of exact and tender prudence
and conscience, are fit to write history: for how can they stake their
reputation upon a popular faith? how be responsible for the opinions of
men they do not know? and with what assurance deliver their conjectures
for current pay? Of actions performed before their own eyes, wherein
several persons were actors, they would be unwilling to give evidence
upon oath before a judge; and there is no man, so familiarly known to
them, for whose intentions they would become absolute caution. For my
part, I think it less hazardous to write of things past, than present,
by how much the writer is only to give an account of things every one
knows he must of necessity borrow upon trust.
I am solicited to write the affairs of my own time by some, who fancy
I look upon them with an eye less blinded with passion than another, and
have a clearer insight into them by reason of the free access fortune
has given me to the heads of various factions; but they do not consider,
that to purchase the glory of Sallust, I would not give myself the
trouble, sworn enemy as I am to obligation, assiduity, or perseverance:
that there is nothing so contrary to my style, as a continued narrative,
I so often interrupt and cut myself short in my writing for want of
breath; I have neither composition nor explanation worth anything, and
am ignorant, beyond a child, of the phrases and even the very words
proper to express the most common things; and for that reason it is,
that I have undertaken to say only what I can say, and have accommodated
my subject to my strength. Should I take one to be my guide,
peradventure I should not be able to keep pace with him; and in the
freedom of my liberty might deliver judgments, which upon better
thoughts, and according to reason, would be illegitimate and punishable.
Plutarch would say of what he has delivered to us, that it is the work
of others: that his examples are all and everywhere exactly true: that
they are useful to posterity, and are presented with a lustre that will
light us the way to virtue, is his own work. It is not of so dangerous
consequence, as in a medicinal drug, whether an old story be so or so.
CHAPTER XXI——THAT THE PROFIT OF ONE MAN IS THE DAMAGE OF ANOTHER
Demades the Athenian—[Seneca, De Beneficiis, vi. 38, whence nearly
the whole of this chapter is taken.]—condemned one of his city, whose
trade it was to sell the necessaries for funeral ceremonies, upon
pretence that he demanded unreasonable profit, and that that profit
could not accrue to him, but by the death of a great number of people. A
judgment that appears to be ill grounded, forasmuch as no profit
whatever can possibly be made but at the expense of another, and that by
the same rule he should condemn all gain of what kind soever. The
merchant only thrives by the debauchery of youth, the husband man by the
dearness of grain, the architect by the ruin of buildings, lawyers and
officers of justice by the suits and contentions of men: nay, even the
honour and office of divines are derived from our death and vices. A
physician takes no pleasure in the health even of his friends, says the
ancient Greek comic writer, nor a soldier in the peace of his country,
and so of the rest. And, which is yet worse, let every one but dive into
his own bosom, and he will find his private wishes spring and his secret
hopes grow up at another's expense. Upon which consideration it comes
into my head, that nature does not in this swerve from her general
polity; for physicians hold, that the birth, nourishment, and increase
of every thing is the dissolution and corruption of another:
"Nam quodcumque suis mutatum finibus exit,
Continuo hoc mors est illius, quod fuit ante."
["For, whatever from its own confines passes changed, this is at
once the death of that which before it was."—Lucretius, ii. 752.]
CHAPTER XXII——OF CUSTOM, AND THAT WE SHOULD NOT EASILY CHANGE A LAW
RECEIVED
He seems to me to have had a right and true apprehension of the power
of custom, who first invented the story of a country-woman who, having
accustomed herself to play with and carry a young calf in her arms, and
daily continuing to do so as it grew up, obtained this by custom, that,
when grown to be a great ox, she was still able to bear it. For, in
truth, custom is a violent and treacherous schoolmistress. She, by
little and little, slily and unperceived, slips in the foot of her
authority, but having by this gentle and humble beginning, with the
benefit of time, fixed and established it, she then unmasks a furious
and tyrannic countenance, against which we have no more the courage or
the power so much as to lift up our eyes. We see her, at every turn,
forcing and violating the rules of nature:
"Usus efficacissimus rerum omnium magister."
["Custom is the best master of all things."
—Pliny, Nat. Hist.,xxvi. 2.]
I refer to her Plato's cave in his Republic, and the physicians, who
so often submit the reasons of their art to her authority; as the story
of that king, who by custom brought his stomach to that pass, as to live
by poison, and the maid that Albertus reports to have lived upon
spiders. In that new world of the Indies, there were found great
nations, and in very differing climates, who were of the same diet, made
provision of them, and fed them for their tables; as also, they did
grasshoppers, mice, lizards, and bats; and in a time of scarcity of such
delicacies, a toad was sold for six crowns, all which they cook, and
dish up with several sauces. There were also others found, to whom our
diet, and the flesh we eat, were venomous and mortal:
"Consuetudinis magna vis est: pernoctant venatores in nive:
in montibus uri se patiuntur: pugiles, caestibus contusi,
ne ingemiscunt quidem."
["The power of custom is very great: huntsmen will lie out all
night in the snow, or suffer themselves to be burned up by the sun
on the mountains; boxers, hurt by the caestus, never utter a
groan."—Cicero, Tusc., ii. 17]
These strange examples will not appear so strange if we consider what
we have ordinary experience of, how much custom stupefies our senses. We
need not go to what is reported of the people about the cataracts of the
Nile; and what philosophers believe of the music of the spheres, that
the bodies of those circles being solid and smooth, and coming to touch
and rub upon one another, cannot fail of creating a marvellous harmony,
the changes and cadences of which cause the revolutions and dances of
the stars; but that the hearing sense of all creatures here below, being
universally, like that of the Egyptians, deafened, and stupefied with
the continual noise, cannot, how great soever, perceive it—[This passage
is taken from Cicero, "Dream of Scipio"; see his De Republica, vi. II.
The Egyptians were said to be stunned by the noise of the Cataracts.]—
Smiths, millers, pewterers, forgemen, and armourers could never be able
to live in the perpetual noise of their own trades, did it strike their
ears with the same violence that it does ours.
My perfumed doublet gratifies my own scent at first; but after I have
worn it three days together, 'tis only pleasing to the bystanders. This
is yet more strange, that custom, notwithstanding long intermissions and
intervals, should yet have the power to unite and establish the effect
of its impressions upon our senses, as is manifest in such as live near
unto steeples and the frequent noise of the bells. I myself lie at home
in a tower, where every morning and evening a very great bell rings out
the Ave Maria: the noise shakes my very tower, and at first seemed
insupportable to me; but I am so used to it, that I hear it without any
manner of offence, and often without awaking at it.
Plato—[Diogenes Laertius, iii. 38. But he whom Plato censured was not
a boy playing at nuts, but a man throwing dice.]—reprehending a boy for
playing at nuts, "Thou reprovest me," says the boy, "for a very little
thing." "Custom," replied Plato, "is no little thing." I find that our
greatest vices derive their first propensity from our most tender
infancy, and that our principal education depends upon the nurse.
Mothers are mightily pleased to see a child writhe off the neck of a
chicken, or to please itself with hurting a dog or a cat; and such wise
fathers there are in the world, who look upon it as a notable mark of a
martial spirit, when they hear a son miscall, or see him domineer over a
poor peasant, or a lackey, that dares not reply, nor turn again; and a
great sign of wit, when they see him cheat and overreach his playfellow
by some malicious treachery and deceit. Yet these are the true seeds and
roots of cruelty, tyranny, and treason; they bud and put out there, and
afterwards shoot up vigorously, and grow to prodigious bulk, cultivated
by custom. And it is a very dangerous mistake to excuse these vile
inclinations upon the tenderness of their age, and the triviality of the
subject: first, it is nature that speaks, whose declaration is then more
sincere, and inward thoughts more undisguised, as it is more weak and
young; secondly, the deformity of cozenage does not consist nor depend
upon the difference betwixt crowns and pins; but I rather hold it more
just to conclude thus: why should he not cozen in crowns since he does
it in pins, than as they do, who say they only play for pins, they would
not do it if it were for money? Children should carefully be instructed
to abhor vices for their own contexture; and the natural deformity of
those vices ought so to be represented to them, that they may not only
avoid them in their actions, but especially so to abominate them in
their hearts, that the very thought should be hateful to them, with what
mask soever they may be disguised.
I know very well, for what concerns myself, that from having been
brought up in my childhood to a plain and straightforward way of
dealing, and from having had an aversion to all manner of juggling and
foul play in my childish sports and recreations (and, indeed, it is to
be noted, that the plays of children are not performed in play, but are
to be judged in them as their most serious actions), there is no game so
small wherein from my own bosom naturally, and without study or
endeavour, I have not an extreme aversion from deceit. I shuffle and cut
and make as much clatter with the cards, and keep as strict account for
farthings, as it were for double pistoles; when winning or losing
against my wife and daughter, 'tis indifferent to me, as when I play in
good earnest with others, for round sums. At all times, and in all
places, my own eyes are sufficient to look to my fingers; I am not so
narrowly watched by any other, neither is there any I have more respect
to.
I saw the other day, at my own house, a little fellow, a native of
Nantes, born without arms, who has so well taught his feet to perform
the services his hands should have done him, that truly these have half
forgotten their natural office; and, indeed, the fellow calls them his
hands; with them he cuts anything, charges and discharges a pistol,
threads a needle, sews, writes, puts off his hat, combs his head, plays
at cards and dice, and all this with as much dexterity as any other
could do who had more, and more proper limbs to assist him. The money I
gave him—for he gains his living by shewing these feats—he took in his
foot, as we do in our hand. I have seen another who, being yet a boy,
flourished a two-handed sword, and, if I may so say, handled a halberd
with the mere motions of his neck and shoulders for want of hands;
tossed them into the air, and caught them again, darted a dagger, and
cracked a whip as well as any coachman in France.
But the effects of custom are much more manifest in the strange
impressions she imprints in our minds, where she meets with less
resistance. What has she not the power to impose upon our judgments and
beliefs? Is there any so fantastic opinion (omitting the gross
impostures of religions, with which we see so many great nations, and so
many understanding men, so strangely besotted; for this being beyond the
reach of human reason, any error is more excusable in such as are not
endued, through the divine bounty, with an extraordinary illumination
from above), but, of other opinions, are there any so extravagant, that
she has not planted and established for laws in those parts of the world
upon which she has been pleased to exercise her power? And therefore
that ancient exclamation was exceeding just:
"Non pudet physicum, id est speculatorem venatoremque naturae,
ab animis consuetudine imbutis petere testimonium veritatis?"
["Is it not a shame for a natural philosopher, that is, for an
observer and hunter of nature, to seek testimony of the truth from
minds prepossessed by custom?"—Cicero, De Natura Deor., i. 30.]
I do believe, that no so absurd or ridiculous fancy can enter into
human imagination, that does not meet with some example of public
practice, and that, consequently, our reason does not ground and back
up. There are people, amongst whom it is the fashion to turn their backs
upon him they salute, and never look upon the man they intend to honour.
There is a place, where, whenever the king spits, the greatest ladies of
his court put out their hands to receive it; and another nation, where
the most eminent persons about him stoop to take up his ordure in a
linen cloth. Let us here steal room to insert a story.
A French gentleman was always wont to blow his nose with his fingers
(a thing very much against our fashion), and he justifying himself for
so doing, and he was a man famous for pleasant repartees, he asked me,
what privilege this filthy excrement had, that we must carry about us a
fine handkerchief to receive it, and, which was more, afterwards to lap
it carefully up, and carry it all day about in our pockets, which, he
said, could not but be much more nauseous and offensive, than to see it
thrown away, as we did all other evacuations. I found that what he said
was not altogether without reason, and by being frequently in his
company, that slovenly action of his was at last grown familiar to me;
which nevertheless we make a face at, when we hear it reported of
another country. Miracles appear to be so, according to our ignorance of
nature, and not according to the essence of nature the continually being
accustomed to anything, blinds the eye of our judgment. Barbarians are
no more a wonder to us, than we are to them; nor with any more reason,
as every one would confess, if after having travelled over those remote
examples, men could settle themselves to reflect upon, and rightly to
confer them, with their own. Human reason is a tincture almost equally
infused into all our opinions and manners, of what form soever they are;
infinite in matter, infinite in diversity. But I return to my subject.
There are peoples, where, his wife and children excepted, no one
speaks to the king but through a tube. In one and the same nation, the
virgins discover those parts that modesty should persuade them to hide,
and the married women carefully cover and conceal them. To which, this
custom, in another place, has some relation, where chastity, but in
marriage, is of no esteem, for unmarried women may prostitute themselves
to as many as they please, and being got with child, may lawfully take
physic, in the sight of every one, to destroy their fruit. And, in
another place, if a tradesman marry, all of the same condition, who are
invited to the wedding, lie with the bride before him; and the greater
number of them there is, the greater is her honour, and the opinion of
her ability and strength: if an officer marry, 'tis the same, the same
with a labourer, or one of mean condition; but then it belongs to the
lord of the place to perform that office; and yet a severe loyalty
during marriage is afterward strictly enjoined. There are places where
brothels of young men are kept for the pleasure of women; where the
wives go to war as well as the husbands, and not only share in the
dangers of battle, but, moreover, in the honours of command. Others,
where they wear rings not only through their noses, lips, cheeks, and on
their toes, but also weighty gimmals of gold thrust through their paps
and buttocks; where, in eating, they wipe their fingers upon their
thighs, genitories, and the soles of their feet: where children are
excluded, and brothers and nephews only inherit; and elsewhere, nephews
only, saving in the succession of the prince: where, for the regulation
of community in goods and estates, observed in the country, certain
sovereign magistrates have committed to them the universal charge and
overseeing of the agriculture, and distribution of the fruits, according
to the necessity of every one where they lament the death of children,
and feast at the decease of old men: where they lie ten or twelve in a
bed, men and their wives together: where women, whose husbands come to
violent ends, may marry again, and others not: where the condition of
women is looked upon with such contempt, that they kill all the native
females, and buy wives of their neighbours to supply their use; where
husbands may repudiate their wives, without showing any cause, but wives
cannot part from their husbands, for what cause soever; where husbands
may sell their wives in case of sterility; where they boil the bodies of
their dead, and afterward pound them to a pulp, which they mix with
their wine, and drink it; where the most coveted sepulture is to be
eaten by dogs, and elsewhere by birds; where they believe the souls of
the blessed live in all manner of liberty, in delightful fields,
furnished with all sorts of delicacies, and that it is these souls,
repeating the words we utter, which we call Echo; where they fight in
the water, and shoot their arrows with the most mortal aim, swimming;
where, for a sign of subjection, they lift up their shoulders, and hang
down their heads; where they put off their shoes when they enter the
king's palace; where the eunuchs, who take charge of the sacred women,
have, moreover, their lips and noses cut off, that they may not be
loved; where the priests put out their own eyes, to be better acquainted
with their demons, and the better to receive their oracles; where every
one makes to himself a deity of what he likes best; the hunter of a lion
or a fox, the fisher of some fish; idols of every human action or
passion; in which place, the sun, the moon, and the earth are the
'principal deities, and the form of taking an oath is, to touch the
earth, looking up to heaven; where both flesh and fish is eaten raw;
where the greatest oath they take is, to swear by the name of some dead
person of reputation, laying their hand upon his tomb; where the
newyear's gift the king sends every year to the princes, his vassals, is
fire, which being brought, all the old fire is put out, and the
neighbouring people are bound to fetch of the new, every one for
themselves, upon pain of high treason; where, when the king, to betake
himself wholly to devotion, retires from his administration (which often
falls out), his next successor is obliged to do the same, and the right
of the kingdom devolves to the third in succession: where they vary the
form of government, according to the seeming necessity of affairs:
depose the king when they think good, substituting certain elders to
govern in his stead, and sometimes transferring it into the hands of the
commonality: where men and women are both circumcised and also baptized:
where the soldier, who in one or several engagements, has been so
fortunate as to present seven of the enemies' heads to the king, is made
noble: where they live in that rare and unsociable opinion of the
mortality of the soul: where the women are delivered without pain or
fear: where the women wear copper leggings upon both legs, and if a
louse bite them, are bound in magnanimity to bite them again, and dare
not marry, till first they have made their king a tender of their
virginity, if he please to accept it: where the ordinary way of
salutation is by putting a finger down to the earth, and then pointing
it up toward heaven: where men carry burdens upon their heads, and women
on their shoulders; where the women make water standing, and the men
squatting: where they send their blood in token of friendship, and offer
incense to the men they would honour, like gods: where, not only to the
fourth, but in any other remote degree, kindred are not permitted to
marry: where the children are four years at nurse, and often twelve; in
which place, also, it is accounted mortal to give the child suck the
first day after it is born: where the correction of the male children is
peculiarly designed to the fathers, and to the mothers of the girls; the
punishment being to hang them by the heels in the smoke: where they
circumcise the women: where they eat all sorts of herbs, without other
scruple than of the badness of the smell: where all things are open the
finest houses, furnished in the richest manner, without doors, windows,
trunks, or chests to lock, a thief being there punished double what they
are in other places: where they crack lice with their teeth like
monkeys, and abhor to see them killed with one's nails: where in all
their lives they neither cut their hair nor pare their nails; and, in
another place, pare those of the right hand only, letting the left grow
for ornament and bravery: where they suffer the hair on the right side
to grow as long as it will, and shave the other; and in the neighbouring
provinces, some let their hair grow long before, and some behind,
shaving close the rest: where parents let out their children, and
husbands their wives, to their guests to hire: where a man may get his
own mother with child, and fathers make use of their own daughters or
sons, without scandal: where, at their solemn feasts, they
interchangeably lend their children to one another, without any
consideration of nearness of blood. In one place, men feed upon human
flesh; in another, 'tis reputed a pious office for a man to kill his
father at a certain age; elsewhere, the fathers dispose of their
children, whilst yet in their mothers' wombs, some to be preserved and
carefully brought up, and others to be abandoned or made away. Elsewhere
the old husbands lend their wives to young men; and in another place
they are in common without offence; in one place particularly, the women
take it for a mark of honour to have as many gay fringed tassels at the
bottom of their garment, as they have lain with several men. Moreover,
has not custom made a republic of women separately by themselves? has it
not put arms into their hands, and made them raise armies and fight
battles? And does she not, by her own precept, instruct the most
ignorant vulgar, and make them perfect in things which all the
philosophy in the world could never beat into the heads of the wisest
men? For we know entire nations, where death was not only despised, but
entertained with the greatest triumph; where children of seven years old
suffered themselves to be whipped to death, without changing
countenance; where riches were in such contempt, that the meanest
citizen would not have deigned to stoop to take up a purse of crowns.
And we know regions, very fruitful in all manner of provisions, where,
notwithstanding, the most ordinary diet, and that they are most pleased
with, is only bread, cresses, and water. Did not custom, moreover, work
that miracle in Chios that, in seven hundred years, it was never known
that ever maid or wife committed any act to the prejudice of her honour?
To conclude; there is nothing, in my opinion, that she does not, or
may not do; and therefore, with very good reason it is that Pindar calls
her the ruler of the world. He that was seen to beat his father, and
reproved for so doing, made answer, that it was the custom of their
family; that, in like manner, his father had beaten his grandfather, his
grandfather his great-grandfather, "And this," says he, pointing to his
son, "when he comes to my age, shall beat me." And the father, whom the
son dragged and hauled along the streets, commanded him to stop at a
certain door, for he himself, he said, had dragged his father no
farther, that being the utmost limit of the hereditary outrage the sons
used to practise upon the fathers in their family. It is as much by
custom as infirmity, says Aristotle, that women tear their hair, bite
their nails, and eat coals and earth, and more by custom than nature
that men abuse themselves with one another.
The laws of conscience, which we pretend to be derived from nature,
proceed from custom; every one, having an inward veneration for the
opinions and manners approved and received amongst his own people,
cannot, without very great reluctance, depart from them, nor apply
himself to them without applause. In times past, when those of Crete
would curse any one, they prayed the gods to engage him in some ill
custom. But the principal effect of its power is, so to seize and
ensnare us, that it is hardly in us to disengage ourselves from its
gripe, or so to come to ourselves, as to consider of and to weigh the
things it enjoins. To say the truth, by reason that we suck it in with
our milk, and that the face of the world presents itself in this posture
to our first sight, it seems as if we were born upon condition to follow
on this track; and the common fancies that we find in repute everywhere
about us, and infused into our minds with the seed of our fathers,
appear to be the most universal and genuine; from whence it comes to
pass, that whatever is off the hinges of custom, is believed to be also
off the hinges of reason; how unreasonably for the most part, God knows.
If, as we who study ourselves have learned to do, every one who hears
a good sentence, would immediately consider how it does in any way touch
his own private concern, every one would find, that it was not so much a
good saying, as a severe lash to the ordinary stupidity of his own
judgment: but men receive the precepts and admonitions of truth, as
directed to the common sort, and never to themselves; and instead of
applying them to their own manners, do only very ignorantly and
unprofitably commit them to memory. But let us return to the empire of
custom.
Such people as have been bred up to liberty, and subject to no other
dominion but the authority of their own will, look upon all other form
of government as monstrous and contrary to nature. Those who are inured
to monarchy do the same; and what opportunity soever fortune presents
them with to change, even then, when with the greatest difficulties they
have disengaged themselves from one master, that was troublesome and
grievous to them, they presently run, with the same difficulties, to
create another; being unable to take into hatred subjection itself.
'Tis by the mediation of custom, that every one is content with the
place where he is planted by nature; and the Highlanders of Scotland no
more pant after Touraine; than the Scythians after Thessaly. Darius
asking certain Greeks what they would take to assume the custom of the
Indians, of eating the dead bodies of their fathers (for that was their
use, believing they could not give them a better nor more noble
sepulture than to bury them in their own bodies), they made answer, that
nothing in the world should hire them to do it; but having also tried to
persuade the Indians to leave their custom, and, after the Greek manner,
to burn the bodies of their fathers, they conceived a still greater
horror at the motion.—[Herodotus, iii. 38.]—Every one does the same, for
use veils from us the true aspect of things.
"Nil adeo magnum, nec tam mirabile quidquam
Principio, quod non minuant mirarier omnes Paullatim."
["There is nothing at first so grand, so admirable, which by degrees
people do not regard with less admiration."—Lucretius, ii. 1027]
Taking upon me once to justify something in use amongst us, and that
was received with absolute authority for a great many leagues round
about us, and not content, as men commonly do, to establish it only by
force of law and example, but inquiring still further into its origin, I
found the foundation so weak, that I who made it my business to confirm
others, was very near being dissatisfied myself. 'Tis by this receipt
that Plato —[Laws, viii. 6.]—undertakes to cure the unnatural and
preposterous loves of his time, as one which he esteems of sovereign
virtue, namely, that the public opinion condemns them; that the poets,
and all other sorts of writers, relate horrible stories of them; a
recipe, by virtue of which the most beautiful daughters no more allure
their fathers' lust; nor brothers, of the finest shape and fashion,
their sisters' desire; the very fables of Thyestes, OEdipus, and
Macareus, having with the harmony of their song, infused this wholesome
opinion and belief into the tender brains of children. Chastity is, in
truth, a great and shining virtue, and of which the utility is
sufficiently known; but to treat of it, and to set it off in its true
value, according to nature, is as hard as 'tis easy to do so according
to custom, laws, and precepts. The fundamental and universal reasons are
of very obscure and difficult research, and our masters either lightly
pass them over, or not daring so much as to touch them, precipitate
themselves into the liberty and protection of custom, there puffing
themselves out and triumphing to their heart's content: such as will not
suffer themselves to be withdrawn from this original source, do yet
commit a greater error, and subject themselves to wild opinions; witness
Chrysippus,—[Sextus Empiricus, Pyyrhon. Hypotyp., i. 14.]—who, in so
many of his writings, has strewed the little account he made of
incestuous conjunctions, committed with how near relations soever.
Whoever would disengage himself from this violent prejudice of
custom, would find several things received with absolute and undoubting
opinion, that have no other support than the hoary head and rivelled
face of ancient usage. But the mask taken off, and things being referred
to the decision of truth and reason, he will find his judgment as it
were altogether overthrown, and yet restored to a much more sure estate.
For example, I shall ask him, what can be more strange than to see a
people obliged to obey laws they never understood; bound in all their
domestic affairs, as marriages, donations, wills, sales, and purchases,
to rules they cannot possibly know, being neither written nor published
in their own language, and of which they are of necessity to purchase
both the interpretation and the use? Not according to the ingenious
opinion of Isocrates,—[Discourse to Nicocles.]—who counselled his king
to make the traffics and negotiations of his subjects, free, frank, and
of profit to them, and their quarrels and disputes burdensome, and laden
with heavy impositions and penalties; but, by a prodigious opinion, to
make sale of reason itself, and to give to laws a course of merchandise.
I think myself obliged to fortune that, as our historians report, it was
a Gascon gentleman, a countryman of mine, who first opposed Charlemagne,
when he attempted to impose upon us Latin and imperial laws.
What can be more savage, than to see a nation where, by lawful
custom, the office of a judge is bought and sold, where judgments are
paid for with ready money, and where justice may legitimately be denied
to him that has not wherewithal to pay; a merchandise in so great
repute, as in a government to create a fourth estate of wrangling
lawyers, to add to the three ancient ones of the church, nobility, and
people; which fourth estate, having the laws in their own hands, and
sovereign power over men's lives and fortunes, makes another body
separate from nobility: whence it comes to pass, that there are double
laws, those of honour and those of justice, in many things altogether
opposite one to another; the nobles as rigorously condemning a lie
taken, as the other do a lie revenged: by the law of arms, he shall be
degraded from all nobility and honour who puts up with an affront; and
by the civil law, he who vindicates his reputation by revenge incurs a
capital punishment: he who applies himself to the law for reparation of
an offence done to his honour, disgraces himself; and he who does not,
is censured and punished by the law. Yet of these two so different
things, both of them referring to one head, the one has the charge of
peace, the other of war; those have the profit, these the honour; those
the wisdom, these the virtue; those the word, these the action; those
justice, these valour; those reason, these force; those the long robe,
these the short;—divided betwixt them.
For what concerns indifferent things, as clothes, who is there
seeking to bring them back to their true use, which is the body's
service and convenience, and upon which their original grace and fitness
depend; for the most fantastic, in my opinion, that can be imagined, I
will instance amongst others, our flat caps, that long tail of velvet
that hangs down from our women's heads, with its party-coloured
trappings; and that vain and futile model of a member we cannot in
modesty so much as name, which, nevertheless, we make show and parade of
in public. These considerations, notwithstanding, will not prevail upon
any understanding man to decline the common mode; but, on the contrary,
methinks, all singular and particular fashions are rather marks of folly
and vain affectation than of sound reason, and that a wise man, within,
ought to withdraw and retire his soul from the crowd, and there keep it
at liberty and in power to judge freely of things; but as to externals,
absolutely to follow and conform himself to the fashion of the time.
Public society has nothing to do with our thoughts, but the rest, as our
actions, our labours, our fortunes, and our lives, we are to lend and
abandon them to its service and to the common opinion, as did that good
and great Socrates who refused to preserve his life by a disobedience to
the magistrate, though a very wicked and unjust one for it is the rule
of rules, the general law of laws, that every one observe those of the
place wherein he lives.
["It is good to obey the laws of one's country."
—Excerpta ex Trag. Gyaecis, Grotio interp., 1626, p. 937.]
And now to another point. It is a very great doubt, whether any so
manifest benefit can accrue from the alteration of a law received, let
it be what it will, as there is danger and inconvenience in altering it;
forasmuch as government is a structure composed of divers parts and
members joined and united together, with so strict connection, that it
is impossible to stir so much as one brick or stone, but the whole body
will be sensible of it. The legislator of the Thurians—[Charondas; Diod.
Sic., xii. 24.]—ordained, that whosoever would go about either to
abolish an old law, or to establish a new, should present himself with a
halter about his neck to the people, to the end, that if the innovation
he would introduce should not be approved by every one, he might
immediately be hanged; and he of the Lacedaemonians employed his life to
obtain from his citizens a faithful promise that none of his laws should
be violated.—[Lycurgus; Plutarch, in Vita, c. 22.]—The Ephoros who so
rudely cut the two strings that Phrynis had added to music never stood
to examine whether that addition made better harmony, or that by its
means the instrument was more full and complete; it was enough for him
to condemn the invention, that it was a novelty, and an alteration of
the old fashion. Which also is the meaning of the old rusty sword
carried before the magistracy of Marseilles.
For my own part, I have a great aversion from a novelty, what face or
what pretence soever it may carry along with it, and have reason, having
been an eyewitness of the great evils it has produced. For those which
for so many years have lain so heavy upon us, it is not wholly
accountable; but one may say, with colour enough, that it has
accidentally produced and begotten the mischiefs and ruin that have
since happened, both without and against it; it, principally, we are to
accuse for these disorders:
"Heu! patior telis vulnera facta meis."
["Alas! The wounds were made by my own weapons."
—Ovid, Ep. Phyll. Demophoonti, vers. 48.]
They who give the first shock to a state, are almost naturally the
first overwhelmed in its ruin the fruits of public commotion are seldom
enjoyed by him who was the first motor; he beats and disturbs the water
for another's net. The unity and contexture of this monarchy, of this
grand edifice, having been ripped and torn in her old age, by this thing
called innovation, has since laid open a rent, and given sufficient
admittance to such injuries: the royal majesty with greater difficulty
declines from the summit to the middle, then it falls and tumbles
headlong from the middle to the bottom. But if the inventors do the
greater mischief, the imitators are more vicious to follow examples of
which they have felt and punished both the horror and the offence. And
if there can be any degree of honour in ill-doing, these last must yield
to the others the glory of contriving, and the courage of making the
first attempt. All sorts of new disorders easily draw, from this
primitive and ever-flowing fountain, examples and precedents to trouble
and discompose our government: we read in our very laws, made for the
remedy of this first evil, the beginning and pretences of all sorts of
wicked enterprises; and that befalls us, which Thucydides said of the
civil wars of his time, that, in favour of public vices, they gave them
new and more plausible names for their excuse, sweetening and disguising
their true titles; which must be done, forsooth, to reform our
conscience and belief:
"Honesta oratio est;"
["Fine words truly."—Ter. And., i. I, 114.]
but the best pretence for innovation is of very dangerous
consequence:
"Aden nihil motum ex antiquo probabile est."
["We are ever wrong in changing ancient ways."—Livy, xxxiv. 54]
And freely to speak my thoughts, it argues a strange self-love and
great presumption to be so fond of one's own opinions, that a public
peace must be overthrown to establish them, and to introduce so many
inevitable mischiefs, and so dreadful a corruption of manners, as a
civil war and the mutations of state consequent to it, always bring in
their train, and to introduce them, in a thing of so high concern, into
the bowels of one's own country. Can there be worse husbandry than to
set up so many certain and knowing vices against errors that are only
contested and disputable? And are there any worse sorts of vices than
those committed against a man's own conscience, and the natural light of
his own reason? The Senate, upon the dispute betwixt it and the people
about the administration of their religion, was bold enough to return
this evasion for current pay:
"Ad deos id magis, quam ad se, pertinere: ipsos visuros,
ne sacra sua polluantur;"
["Those things belong to the gods to determine than to them; let the
gods, therefore, take care that their sacred mysteries were not
profaned."—Livy, x. 6.]
according to what the oracle answered to those of Delphos who,
fearing to be invaded by the Persians in the Median war, inquired of
Apollo, how they should dispose of the holy treasure of his temple;
whether they should hide, or remove it to some other place? He returned
them answer, that they should stir nothing from thence, and only take
care of themselves, for he was sufficient to look to what belonged to
him. —[Herodotus, viii. 36.].—
The Christian religion has all the marks of the utmost utility and
justice: but none more manifest than the severe injunction it lays
indifferently upon all to yield absolute obedience to the civil
magistrate, and to maintain and defend the laws. Of which, what a
wonderful example has the divine wisdom left us, that, to establish the
salvation of mankind, and to conduct His glorious victory over death and
sin, would do it after no other way, but at the mercy of our ordinary
forms of justice subjecting the progress and issue of so high and so
salutiferous an effect, to the blindness and injustice of our customs
and observances; sacrificing the innocent blood of so many of His elect,
and so long a loss of so many years, to the maturing of this inestimable
fruit? There is a vast difference betwixt the case of one who follows
the forms and laws of his country, and of another who will undertake to
regulate and change them; of whom the first pleads simplicity,
obedience, and example for his excuse, who, whatever he shall do, it
cannot be imputed to malice; 'tis at the worst but misfortune:
"Quis est enim, quem non moveat clarissimis monumentis
testata consignataque antiquitas?"
["For who is there that antiquity, attested and confirmed by the
fairest monuments, cannot move?"—Cicero, De Divin., i. 40.]
besides what Isocrates says, that defect is nearer allied to
moderation than excess: the other is a much more ruffling gamester; for
whosoever shall take upon him to choose and alter, usurps the authority
of judging, and should look well about him, and make it his business to
discern clearly the defect of what he would abolish, and the virtue of
what he is about to introduce.
This so vulgar consideration is that which settled me in my station,
and kept even my most extravagant and ungoverned youth under the rein,
so as not to burden my shoulders with so great a weight, as to render
myself responsible for a science of that importance, and in this to
dare, what in my better and more mature judgment, I durst not do in the
most easy and indifferent things I had been instructed in, and wherein
the temerity of judging is of no consequence at all; it seeming to me
very unjust to go about to subject public and established customs and
institutions, to the weakness and instability of a private and
particular fancy (for private reason has but a private jurisdiction),
and to attempt that upon the divine, which no government will endure a
man should do, upon the civil laws; with which, though human reason has
much more commerce than with the other, yet are they sovereignly judged
by their own proper judges, and the extreme sufficiency serves only to
expound and set forth the law and custom received, and neither to wrest
it, nor to introduce anything, of innovation. If, sometimes, the divine
providence has gone beyond the rules to which it has necessarily bound
and obliged us men, it is not to give us any dispensation to do the
same; those are masterstrokes of the divine hand, which we are not to
imitate, but to admire, and extraordinary examples, marks of express and
particular purposes, of the nature of miracles, presented before us for
manifestations of its almightiness, equally above both our rules and
force, which it would be folly and impiety to attempt to represent and
imitate; and that we ought not to follow, but to contemplate with the
greatest reverence: acts of His personage, and not for us. Cotta very
opportunely declares:
"Quum de religione agitur, Ti. Coruncanium, P. Scipionem,
P. Scaevolam, pontifices maximos, non Zenonem, aut Cleanthem,
aut Chrysippum, sequor."
["When matter of religion is in question, I follow the high priests
T. Coruncanius, P. Scipio, P. Scaevola, and not Zeno, Cleanthes, or
Chrysippus."—Cicero, De Natura Deor., iii. 2.]
God knows, in the present quarrel of our civil war, where there are a
hundred articles to dash out and to put in, great and very considerable,
how many there are who can truly boast, they have exactly and perfectly
weighed and understood the grounds and reasons of the one and the other
party; 'tis a number, if they make any number, that would be able to
give us very little disturbance. But what becomes of all the rest, under
what ensigns do they march, in what quarter do they lie? Theirs have the
same effect with other weak and ill-applied medicines; they have only
set the humours they would purge more violently in work, stirred and
exasperated by the conflict, and left them still behind. The potion was
too weak to purge, but strong enough to weaken us; so that it does not
work, but we keep it still in our bodies, and reap nothing from the
operation but intestine gripes and dolours.
So it is, nevertheless, that Fortune still reserving her authority in
defiance of whatever we are able to do or say, sometimes presents us
with a necessity so urgent, that 'tis requisite the laws should a little
yield and give way; and when one opposes the increase of an innovation
that thus intrudes itself by violence, to keep a man's self in so doing,
in all places and in all things within bounds and rules against those
who have the power, and to whom all things are lawful that may in any
way serve to advance their design, who have no other law nor rule but
what serves best to their own purpose, 'tis a dangerous obligation and
an intolerable inequality:
"Aditum nocendi perfido praestat fides,"
["Putting faith in a treacherous person, opens the door to
harm."—Seneca, OEdip., act iii., verse 686.]
forasmuch as the ordinary discipline of a healthful state does not
provide against these extraordinary accidents; it presupposes a body
that supports itself in its principal members and offices, and a common
consent to its obedience and observation. A legitimate proceeding is
cold, heavy, and constrained, and not fit to make head against a
headstrong and unbridled proceeding. 'Tis known to be to this day cast
in the dish of those two great men, Octavius and Cato, in the two civil
wars of Sylla and Caesar, that they would rather suffer their country to
undergo the last extremities, than relieve their fellow-citizens at the
expense of its laws, or be guilty of any innovation; for in truth, in
these last necessities, where there is no other remedy, it would,
peradventure, be more discreetly done, to stoop and yield a little to
receive the blow, than, by opposing without possibility of doing good,
to give occasion to violence to trample all under foot; and better to
make the laws do what they can, when they cannot do what they would.
After this manner did he—[Agesilaus.]—who suspended them for
four-and-twenty hours, and he who, for once shifted a day in the
calendar, and that other—[Alexander the Great.]—who of the month of June
made a second of May. The Lacedaemonians themselves, who were so
religious observers of the laws of their country, being straitened by
one of their own edicts, by which it was expressly forbidden to choose
the same man twice to be admiral; and on the other side, their affairs
necessarily requiring, that Lysander should again take upon him that
command, they made one Aratus admiral; 'tis true, but withal, Lysander
went general of the navy; and, by the same subtlety, one of their
ambassadors being sent to the Athenians to obtain the revocation of some
decree, and Pericles remonstrating to him, that it was forbidden to take
away the tablet wherein a law had once been engrossed, he advised him to
turn it only, that being not forbidden; and Plutarch commends
Philopoemen, that being born to command, he knew how to do it, not only
according to the laws, but also to overrule even the laws themselves,
when the public necessity so required.
CHAPTER XXIII——VARIOUS EVENTS FROM THE SAME COUNSEL
Jacques Amiot, grand almoner of France, one day related to me this
story, much to the honour of a prince of ours (and ours he was upon
several very good accounts, though originally of foreign
extraction),—[The Duc de Guise, surnamed Le Balafre.]—that in the time
of our first commotions, at the siege of Rouen,—[In 1562]—this prince,
having been advertised by the queen-mother of a conspiracy against his
life, and in her letters particular notice being given him of the person
who was to execute the business (who was a gentleman of Anjou or of
Maine, and who to this effect ordinarily frequented this prince's
house), discovered not a syllable of this intelligence to any one
whatever; but going the next day to the St. Catherine's Mount,—[An
eminence outside Rouen overlooking the Seine. D.W.]—from which our
battery played against the town (for it was during the time of the
siege), and having in company with him the said lord almoner, and
another bishop, he saw this gentleman, who had been denoted to him, and
presently sent for him; to whom, being come before him, seeing him
already pale and trembling with the conscience of his guilt, he thus
said, "Monsieur," such an one, "you guess what I have to say to you;
your countenance discovers it; 'tis in vain to disguise your practice,
for I am so well informed of your business, that it will but make worse
for you, to go about to conceal or deny it: you know very well such and
such passages" (which were the most secret circumstances of his
conspiracy), "and therefore be sure, as you tender your own life, to
confess to me the whole truth of the design." The poor man seeing
himself thus trapped and convicted (for the whole business had been
discovered to the queen by one of the accomplices), was in such a
taking, he knew not what to do; but, folding his hands, to beg and sue
for mercy, he threw himself at his prince's feet, who taking him up,
proceeded to say, "Come, sir; tell me, have I at any time done you
offence? or have I, through private hatred or malice, offended any
kinsman or friend of yours? It is not above three weeks that I have
known you; what inducement, then, could move you to attempt my death?"
To which the gentleman with a trembling voice replied, "That it was no
particular grudge he had to his person, but the general interest and
concern of his party, and that he had been put upon it by some who had
persuaded him it would be a meritorious act, by any means, to extirpate
so great and so powerful an enemy of their religion." "Well," said the
prince, "I will now let you see, how much more charitable the religion
is that I maintain, than that which you profess: yours has counselled
you to kill me, without hearing me speak, and without ever having given
you any cause of offence; and mine commands me to forgive you, convict
as you are, by your own confession, of a design to kill me without
reason.—[Imitated by Voltaire. See Nodier, Questions, p. 165.]—Get you
gone; let me see you no more; and, if you are wise, choose henceforward
honester men for your counsellors in your designs."—[Dampmartin, La
Fortune de la Coup, liv. ii., p. 139]
The Emperor Augustus,—[This story is taken from Seneca, De Clementia,
i. 9.]—being in Gaul, had certain information of a conspiracy L. Cinna
was contriving against him; he therefore resolved to make him an
example; and, to that end, sent to summon his friends to meet the next
morning in counsel. But the night between he passed in great unquietness
of mind, considering that he was about to put to death a young man, of
an illustrious family, and nephew to the great Pompey, and this made him
break out into several passionate complainings. "What then," said he,
"is it possible that I am to live in perpetual anxiety and alarm, and
suffer my would-be assassin, meantime, to walk abroad at liberty? Shall
he go unpunished, after having conspired against my life, a life that I
have hitherto defended in so many civil wars, in so many battles by land
and by sea? And after having settled the universal peace of the whole
world, shall this man be pardoned, who has conspired not only to murder,
but to sacrifice me?"—for the conspiracy was to kill him at sacrifice.
After which, remaining for some time silent, he began again, in louder
tones, and exclaimed against himself, saying: "Why livest thou, if it be
for the good of so many that thou shouldst die? must there be no end of
thy revenges and cruelties? Is thy life of so great value, that so many
mischiefs must be done to preserve it?" His wife Livia, seeing him in
this perplexity: "Will you take a woman's counsel?" said she. "Do as the
physicians do, who, when the ordinary recipes will do no good, make
trial of the contrary. By severity you have hitherto prevailed nothing;
Lepidus has followed Salvidienus; Murena, Lepidus; Caepio, Murena;
Egnatius, Caepio. Begin now, and try how sweetness and clemency will
succeed. Cinna is convict; forgive him, he will never henceforth have
the heart to hurt thee, and it will be an act to thy glory." Augustus
was well pleased that he had met with an advocate of his own humour;
wherefore, having thanked his wife, and, in the morning, countermanded
his friends he had before summoned to council, he commanded Cinna all
alone to be brought to him; who being accordingly come, and a chair by
his appointment set him, having ordered all the rest out of the room, he
spake to him after this manner: "In the first place, Cinna, I demand of
thee patient audience; do not interrupt me in what I am about to say,
and I will afterwards give thee time and leisure to answer. Thou
knowest, Cinna,—[This passage, borrowed from Seneca, has been
paraphrased in verse by Corneille. See Nodier, Questions de la
Literature llgale, 1828, pp. 7, 160. The monologue of Augustus in this
chapter is also from Seneca. Ibid., 164.]—that having taken thee
prisoner in the enemy's camp, and thou an enemy, not only so become, but
born so, I gave thee thy life, restored to thee all thy goods, and,
finally, put thee in so good a posture, by my bounty, of living well and
at thy ease, that the victorious envied the conquered. The sacerdotal
office which thou madest suit to me for, I conferred upon thee, after
having denied it to others, whose fathers have ever borne arms in my
service. After so many obligations, thou hast undertaken to kill me." At
which Cinna crying out that he was very far from entertaining any so
wicked a thought: "Thou dost not keep thy promise, Cinna," continued
Augustus, "that thou wouldst not interrupt me. Yes, thou hast undertaken
to murder me in such a place, on such a day, in such and such company,
and in such a manner." At which words, seeing Cinna astounded and
silent, not upon the account of his promise so to be, but interdict with
the weight of his conscience: "Why," proceeded Augustus, "to what end
wouldst thou do it? Is it to be emperor? Believe me, the Republic is in
very ill condition, if I am the only man betwixt thee and the empire.
Thou art not able so much as to defend thy own house, and but t'other
day was baffled in a suit, by the opposed interest of a mere manumitted
slave. What, hast thou neither means nor power in any other thing, but
only to undertake Caesar? I quit the throne, if there be no other than I
to obstruct thy hopes. Canst thou believe that Paulus, that Fabius, that
the Cossii and the Servilii, and so many noble Romans, not only so in
title, but who by their virtue honour their nobility, would suffer or
endure thee?" After this, and a great deal more that he said to him (for
he was two long hours in speaking), "Now go, Cinna, go thy way: I give
thee that life as traitor and parricide, which I before gave thee in the
quality of an enemy. Let friendship from this time forward begin betwixt
us, and let us show whether I have given, or thou hast received thy life
with the better faith"; and so departed from him. Some time after, he
preferred him to the consular dignity, complaining that he had not the
confidence to demand it; had him ever after for his very great friend,
and was, at last, made by him sole heir to all his estate. Now, from the
time of this accident which befell Augustus in the fortieth year of his
age, he never had any conspiracy or attempt against him, and so reaped
the due reward of this his so generous clemency. But it did not so
happen with our prince, his moderation and mercy not so securing him,
but that he afterwards fell into the toils of the like treason,—[The Duc
de Guise was assassinated in 1563 by Poltrot.]—so vain and futile a
thing is human prudence; throughout all our projects, counsels and
precautions, Fortune will still be mistress of events.
We repute physicians fortunate when they hit upon a lucky cure, as if
there was no other art but theirs that could not stand upon its own
legs, and whose foundations are too weak to support itself upon its own
basis; as if no other art stood in need of Fortune's hand to help it.
For my part, I think of physic as much good or ill as any one would have
me: for, thanks be to God, we have no traffic together. I am of a quite
contrary humour to other men, for I always despise it; but when I am
sick, instead of recanting, or entering into composition with it, I
begin, moreover, to hate and fear it, telling them who importune me to
take physic, that at all events they must give me time to recover my
strength and health, that I may be the better able to support and
encounter the violence and danger of their potions. I let nature work,
supposing her to be sufficiently armed with teeth and claws to defend
herself from the assaults of infirmity, and to uphold that contexture,
the dissolution of which she flies and abhors. I am afraid, lest,
instead of assisting her when close grappled and struggling with
disease, I should assist her adversary, and burden her still more with
work to do.
Now, I say, that not in physic only, but in other more certain arts,
fortune has a very great part.
The poetic raptures, the flights of fancy, that ravish and transport
the author out of himself, why should we not attribute them to his good
fortune, since he himself confesses that they exceed his sufficiency and
force, and acknowledges them to proceed from something else than
himself, and that he has them no more in his power than the orators say
they have those extraordinary motions and agitations that sometimes push
them beyond their design. It is the same in painting, where touches
shall sometimes slip from the hand of the painter, so surpassing both
his conception and his art, as to beget his own admiration and
astonishment. But Fortune does yet more evidently manifest the share she
has in all things of this kind, by the graces and elegances we find in
them, not only beyond the intention, but even without the knowledge of
the workman: a competent reader often discovers in other men's writings
other perfections than the author himself either intended or perceived,
a richer sense and more quaint expression.
As to military enterprises, every one sees how great a hand Fortune
has in them. Even in our counsels and deliberations there must,
certainly, be something of chance and good-luck mixed with human
prudence; for all that our wisdom can do alone is no great matter; the
more piercing, quick, and apprehensive it is, the weaker it finds
itself, and is by so much more apt to mistrust itself. I am of Sylla's
opinion;—["Who freed his great deeds from envy by ever attributing them
to his good fortune, and finally by surnaming himself Faustus, the
Lucky."—Plutarch, How far a Man may praise Himself, c. 9.]—and when I
closely examine the most glorious exploits of war, I perceive, methinks,
that those who carry them on make use of counsel and debate only for
custom's sake, and leave the best part of the enterprise to Fortune, and
relying upon her aid, transgress, at every turn, the bounds of military
conduct and the rules of war. There happen, sometimes, fortuitous
alacrities and strange furies in their deliberations, that for the most
part prompt them to follow the worst grounded counsels, and swell their
courage beyond the limits of reason. Whence it happened that several of
the great captains of old, to justify those rash resolutions, have been
fain to tell their soldiers that they were invited to such attempts by
some inspiration, some sign and prognostic.
Wherefore, in this doubt and uncertainty, that the shortsightedness
of human wisdom to see and choose the best (by reason of the
difficulties that the various accidents and circumstances of things
bring along with them) perplexes us withal, the surest way, in my
opinion, did no other consideration invite us to it, is to pitch upon
that wherein is the greatest appearance of honesty and justice; and not,
being certain of the shortest, to keep the straightest and most direct
way; as in the two examples I have just given, there is no question but
it was more noble and generous in him who had received the offence, to
pardon it, than to do otherwise. If the former—[The Duc de
Guise.]—miscarried in it, he is not, nevertheless, to be blamed for his
good intention; neither does any one know if he had proceeded otherwise,
whether by that means he had avoided the end his destiny had appointed
for him; and he had, moreover, lost the glory of so humane an act.
You will read in history, of many who have been in such apprehension,
that the most part have taken the course to meet and anticipate
conspiracies against them by punishment and revenge; but I find very few
who have reaped any advantage by this proceeding; witness so many Roman
emperors. Whoever finds himself in this danger, ought not to expect much
either from his vigilance or power; for how hard a thing is it for a man
to secure himself from an enemy, who lies concealed under the
countenance of the most assiduous friend we have, and to discover and
know the wills and inward thoughts of those who are in our personal
service. 'Tis to much purpose to have a guard of foreigners about one,
and to be always fenced about with a pale of armed men; whosoever
despises his own life, is always master of that of another man.—[Seneca,
Ep., 4.]—And moreover, this continual suspicion, that makes a prince
jealous of all the world, must of necessity be a strange torment to him.
Therefore it was, that Dion, being advertised that Callippus watched all
opportunities to take away his life, had never the heart to inquire more
particularly into it, saying, that he had rather die than live in that
misery, that he must continually stand upon his guard, not only against
his enemies, but his friends also;—[Plutarch, Apothegms.]—which
Alexander much more vividly and more roundly manifested in effect, when,
having notice by a letter from Parmenio, that Philip, his most beloved
physician, was by Darius' money corrupted to poison him, at the same
time he gave the letter to Philip to read, drank off the potion he had
brought him. Was not this to express a resolution, that if his friends
had a mind to despatch him out of the world, he was willing to give them
opportunity to do it? This prince is, indeed, the sovereign pattern of
hazardous actions; but I do not know whether there be another passage in
his life wherein there is so much firm courage as in this, nor so
illustrious an image of the beauty and greatness of his mind.
Those who preach to princes so circumspect and vigilant a jealousy
and distrust, under colour of security, preach to them ruin and
dishonour: nothing noble can be performed without danger. I know a
person, naturally of a very great daring and enterprising courage, whose
good fortune is continually marred by such persuasions, that he keep
himself close surrounded by his friends, that he must not hearken to any
reconciliation with his ancient enemies, that he must stand aloof, and
not trust his person in hands stronger than his own, what promises or
offers soever they may make him, or what advantages soever he may see
before him. And I know another, who has unexpectedly advanced his
fortunes by following a clear contrary advice.
Courage, the reputation and glory of which men seek with so greedy an
appetite, presents itself, when need requires, as magnificently in
cuerpo, as in full armour; in a closet, as in a camp; with arms pendant,
as with arms raised.
This over-circumspect and wary prudence is a mortal enemy to all high
and generous exploits. Scipio, to sound Syphax's intention, leaving his
army, abandoning Spain, not yet secure nor well settled in his new
conquest, could pass over into Africa in two small ships, to commit
himself, in an enemy's country, to the power of a barbarian king, to a
faith untried and unknown, without obligation, without hostage, under
the sole security of the grandeur of his own courage, his good fortune,
and the promise of his high hopes.—[ Livy, xxviii. 17.]
"Habita fides ipsam plerumque fidem obligat."
["Trust often obliges fidelity."—Livy, xxii. 22.]
In a life of ambition and glory, it is necessary to hold a stiff rein
upon suspicion: fear and distrust invite and draw on offence. The most
mistrustful of our kings—[ Louis XI.]—established his affairs
principally by voluntarily committing his life and liberty into his
enemies' hands, by that action manifesting that he had absolute
confidence in them, to the end they might repose as great an assurance
in him. Caesar only opposed the authority of his countenance and the
haughty sharpness of his rebukes to his mutinous legions in arms against
him:
"Stetit aggere fulti
Cespitis, intrepidus vultu: meruitque timeri,
Nil metuens."
["He stood on a mound, his countenance intrepid, and merited to be
feared, he fearing nothing."—Lucan, v. 316.]
But it is true, withal, that this undaunted assurance is not to be
represented in its simple and entire form, but by such whom the
apprehension of death, and the worst that can happen, does not terrify
and affright; for to represent a pretended resolution with a pale and
doubtful countenance and trembling limbs, for the service of an
important reconciliation, will effect nothing to purpose. 'Tis an
excellent way to gain the heart and will of another, to submit and
intrust one's self to him, provided it appear to be freely done, and
without the constraint of necessity, and in such a condition, that a man
manifestly does it out of a pure and entire confidence in the party, at
least, with a countenance clear from any cloud of suspicion. I saw, when
I was a boy, a gentleman, who was governor of a great city, upon
occasion of a popular commotion and fury, not knowing what other course
to take, go out of a place of very great strength and security, and
commit himself to the mercy of the seditious rabble, in hopes by that
means to appease the tumult before it grew to a more formidable head;
but it was ill for him that he did so, for he was there miserably slain.
But I am not, nevertheless, of opinion, that he committed so great an
error in going out, as men commonly reproach his memory withal, as he
did in choosing a gentle and submissive way for the effecting his
purpose, and in endeavouring to quiet this storm, rather by obeying than
commanding, and by entreaty rather than remonstrance; and I am inclined
to believe, that a gracious severity, with a soldierlike way of
commanding, full of security and confidence, suitable to the quality of
his person, and the dignity of his command, would have succeeded better
with him; at least, he had perished with greater decency and,
reputation. There is nothing so little to be expected or hoped for from
this many-headed monster, in its fury, as humanity and good nature; it
is much more capable of reverence and fear. I should also reproach him,
that having taken a resolution (in my judgment rather brave than rash)
to expose himself, weak and naked, in this tempestuous sea of enraged
madmen, he ought to have stuck to his text, and not for an instant to
have abandoned the high part he had undertaken; whereas, coming to
discover his danger nearer hand, and his nose happening to bleed, he
again changed that demiss and fawning countenance he had at first put
on, into another of fear and amazement, filling his voice with
entreaties and his eyes with tears, and, endeavouring so to withdraw and
secure his person, that carriage more inflamed their fury, and soon
brought the effects of it upon him.
It was upon a time intended that there should be a general muster of
several troops in arms (and that is the most proper occasion of secret
revenges, and there is no place where they can be executed with greater
safety), and there were public and manifest appearances, that there was
no safe coming for some, whose principal and necessary office it was to
review them. Whereupon a consultation was held, and several counsels
were proposed, as in a case that was very nice and of great difficulty;
and moreover of grave consequence. Mine, amongst the rest, was, that
they should by all means avoid giving any sign of suspicion, but that
the officers who were most in danger should boldly go, and with cheerful
and erect countenances ride boldly and confidently through the ranks,
and that instead of sparing fire (which the counsels of the major part
tended to) they should entreat the captains to command the soldiers to
give round and full volleys in honour of the spectators, and not to
spare their powder. This was accordingly done, and served so good use,
as to please and gratify the suspected troops, and thenceforward to
beget a mutual and wholesome confidence and intelligence amongst them.
I look upon Julius Caesar's way of winning men to him as the best and
finest that can be put in practice. First, he tried by clemency to make
himself beloved even by his very enemies, contenting himself, in
detected conspiracies, only publicly to declare, that he was
pre-acquainted with them; which being done, he took a noble resolution
to await without solicitude or fear, whatever might be the event, wholly
resigning himself to the protection of the gods and fortune: for,
questionless, in this state he was at the time when he was killed.
A stranger having publicly said, that he could teach Dionysius, the
tyrant of Syracuse, an infallible way to find out and discover all the
conspiracies his subjects could contrive against him, if he would give
him a good sum of money for his pains, Dionysius hearing of it, caused
the man to be brought to him, that he might learn an art so necessary to
his preservation. The man made answer, that all the art he knew, was,
that he should give him a talent, and afterwards boast that he had
obtained a singular secret from him. Dionysius liked the invention, and
accordingly caused six hundred crowns to be counted out to him.
—[Plutarch, Apothegms.]—It was not likely he should give so great a sum
to a person unknown, but upon the account of some extraordinary
discovery, and the belief of this served to keep his enemies in awe.
Princes, however, do wisely to publish the informations they receive of
all the practices against their lives, to possess men with an opinion
they have so good intelligence that nothing can be plotted against them,
but they have present notice of it. The Duke of Athens did a great many
foolish things in the establishment of his new tyranny over Florence:
but this especially was most notable, that having received the first
intimation of the conspiracies the people were hatching against him,
from Matteo di Morozzo, one of the conspirators, he presently put him to
death, to suppress that rumour, that it might not be thought any of the
city disliked his government.
I remember I have formerly read a story—[In Appian's Civil Wars, book
iv..]—of some Roman of great quality who, flying the tyranny of the
Triumvirate, had a thousand times by the subtlety of as many inventions
escaped from falling into the hands of those that pursued him. It
happened one day that a troop of horse, which was sent out to take him,
passed close by a brake where he was squat, and missed very narrowly of
spying him: but he considering, at this point, the pains and
difficulties wherein he had so long continued to evade the strict and
incessant searches that were every day made for him, the little pleasure
he could hope for in such a kind of life, and how much better it was for
him to die once for all, than to be perpetually at this pass, he started
from his seat, called them back, showed them his form,—[as of a
squatting hare.]—and voluntarily delivered himself up to their cruelty,
by that means to free both himself and them from further trouble. To
invite a man's enemies to come and cut his throat, seems a resolution a
little extravagant and odd; and yet I think he did better to take that
course, than to live in continual feverish fear of an accident for which
there was no cure. But seeing all the remedies a man can apply to such a
disease, are full of unquietness and uncertainty, 'tis better with a
manly courage to prepare one's self for the worst that can happen, and
to extract some consolation from this, that we are not certain the thing
we fear will ever come to pass.
CHAPTER XXIV——OF PEDANTRY
I was often, when a boy, wonderfully concerned to see, in the Italian
farces, a pedant always brought in for the fool of the play, and that
the title of Magister was in no greater reverence amongst us: for being
delivered up to their tuition, what could I do less than be jealous of
their honour and reputation? I sought indeed to excuse them by the
natural incompatibility betwixt the vulgar sort and men of a finer
thread, both in judgment and knowledge, forasmuch as they go a quite
contrary way to one another: but in this, the thing I most stumbled at
was, that the finest gentlemen were those who most despised them;
witness our famous poet Du Bellay—
"Mais je hay par sur tout un scavoir pedantesque."
["Of all things I hate pedantic learning."—Du Bellay]
And 'twas so in former times; for Plutarch says that Greek and
Scholar were terms of reproach and contempt amongst the Romans. But
since, with the better experience of age, I find they had very great
reason so to do, and that—
"Magis magnos clericos non sunt magis magnos sapientes."
["The greatest clerks are not the wisest men." A proverb given in
Rabelais' Gargantua, i. 39.]
But whence it should come to pass, that a mind enriched with the
knowledge of so many things should not become more quick and sprightly,
and that a gross and vulgar understanding should lodge within it,
without correcting and improving itself, all the discourses and
judgments of the greatest minds the world ever had, I am yet to seek. To
admit so many foreign conceptions, so great, and so high fancies, it is
necessary (as a young lady, one of the greatest princesses of the
kingdom, said to me once, speaking of a certain person) that a man's own
brain must be crowded and squeezed together into a less compass, to make
room for the others; I should be apt to conclude, that as plants are
suffocated and drowned with too much nourishment, and lamps with too
much oil, so with too much study and matter is the active part of the
understanding which, being embarrassed, and confounded with a great
diversity of things, loses the force and power to disengage itself, and
by the pressure of this weight, is bowed, subjected, and doubled up. But
it is quite otherwise; for our soul stretches and dilates itself
proportionably as it fills; and in the examples of elder times, we see,
quite contrary, men very proper for public business, great captains, and
great statesmen very learned withal.
And, as to the philosophers, a sort of men remote from all public
affairs, they have been sometimes also despised by the comic liberty of
their times; their opinions and manners making them appear, to men of
another sort, ridiculous. Would you make them judges of a lawsuit, of
the actions of men? they are ready to take it upon them, and straight
begin to examine if there be life, if there be motion, if man be any
other than an ox;—["If Montaigne has copied all this from Plato's
Theatetes, p.127, F. as it is plain by all which he has added
immediately after, that he has taken it from that dialogue, he has
grossly mistaken Plato's sentiment, who says here no more than this,
that the philosopher is so ignorant of what his neighbour does, that he
scarce knows whether he is a man, or some other animal:—Coste."]—what it
is to do and to suffer? what animals law and justice are? Do they speak
of the magistrates, or to him, 'tis with a rude, irreverent, and
indecent liberty. Do they hear their prince, or a king commended? they
make no more of him, than of a shepherd, goatherd, or neatherd: a lazy
Coridon, occupied in milking and shearing his herds and flocks, but more
rudely and harshly than the herd or shepherd himself. Do you repute any
man the greater for being lord of two thousand acres of land? they laugh
at such a pitiful pittance, as laying claim themselves to the whole
world for their possession. Do you boast of your nobility, as being
descended from seven rich successive ancestors? they look upon you with
an eye of contempt, as men who have not a right idea of the universal
image of nature, and that do not consider how many predecessors every
one of us has had, rich, poor, kings, slaves, Greeks, and barbarians;
and though you were the fiftieth descendant from Hercules, they look
upon it as a great vanity, so highly to value this, which is only a gift
of fortune. And 'twas so the vulgar sort contemned them, as men ignorant
of the most elementary and ordinary things; as presumptuous and
insolent.
But this Platonic picture is far different from that these pedants
are presented by. Those were envied for raising themselves above the
common sort, for despising the ordinary actions and offices of life, for
having assumed a particular and inimitable way of living, and for using
a certain method of high-flight and obsolete language, quite different
from the ordinary way of speaking: but these are contemned as being as
much below the usual form, as incapable of public employment, as leading
a life and conforming themselves to the mean and vile manners of the
vulgar:
"Odi ignava opera, philosopha sententia."
["I hate men who jabber about philosophy, but do nothing."
—Pacuvius, ap Gellium, xiii. 8.]
For what concerns the philosophers, as I have said, if they were in
science, they were yet much greater in action. And, as it is said of the
geometrician of Syracuse,—[Archimedes.]—who having been disturbed from
his contemplation, to put some of his skill in practice for the defence
of his country, that he suddenly set on foot dreadful and prodigious
engines, that wrought effects beyond all human expectation; himself,
notwithstanding, disdaining all his handiwork, and thinking in this he
had played the mere mechanic, and violated the dignity of his art, of
which these performances of his he accounted but trivial experiments and
playthings so they, whenever they have been put upon the proof of
action, have been seen to fly to so high a pitch, as made it very well
appear, their souls were marvellously elevated, and enriched by the
knowledge of things. But some of them, seeing the reins of government in
the hands of incapable men, have avoided all management of political
affairs; and he who demanded of Crates, how long it was necessary to
philosophise, received this answer: "Till our armies are no more
commanded by fools." —[Diogenes Laertius, vi. 92.]—Heraclitus resigned
the royalty to his brother; and, to the Ephesians, who reproached him
that he spent his time in playing with children before the temple: "Is
it not better," said he, "to do so, than to sit at the helm of affairs
in your company?" Others having their imagination advanced above the
world and fortune, have looked upon the tribunals of justice, and even
the thrones of kings, as paltry and contemptible; insomuch, that
Empedocles refused the royalty that the Agrigentines offered to him.
Thales, once inveighing in discourse against the pains and care men put
themselves to to become rich, was answered by one in the company, that
he did like the fox, who found fault with what he could not obtain.
Whereupon, he had a mind, for the jest's sake, to show them to the
contrary; and having, for this occasion, made a muster of all his wits,
wholly to employ them in the service of profit and gain, he set a
traffic on foot, which in one year brought him in so great riches, that
the most experienced in that trade could hardly in their whole lives,
with all their industry, have raked so much together.—[Diogenes
Laertius, Life of Thales, i. 26; Cicero, De Divin., i. 49.]—That which
Aristotle reports of some who called both him and Anaxagoras, and others
of their profession, wise but not prudent, in not applying their study
to more profitable things—though I do not well digest this verbal
distinction—that will not, however, serve to excuse my pedants, for to
see the low and necessitous fortune wherewith they are content, we have
rather reason to pronounce that they are neither wise nor prudent.
But letting this first reason alone, I think it better to say, that
this evil proceeds from their applying themselves the wrong way to the
study of the sciences; and that, after the manner we are instructed, it
is no wonder if neither the scholars nor the masters become, though more
learned, ever the wiser, or more able. In plain truth, the cares and
expense our parents are at in our education, point at nothing, but to
furnish our heads with knowledge; but not a word of judgment and virtue.
Cry out, of one that passes by, to the people: "O, what a learned man!"
and of another, "O, what a good man!"—[Translated from Seneca, Ep.,
88.]—they will not fail to turn their eyes, and address their respect to
the former. There should then be a third crier, "O, the blockheads!" Men
are apt presently to inquire, does such a one understand Greek or Latin?
Is he a poet? or does he write in prose? But whether he be grown better
or more discreet, which are qualities of principal concern, these are
never thought of. We should rather examine, who is better learned, than
who is more learned.
We only labour to stuff the memory, and leave the conscience and the
understanding unfurnished and void. Like birds who fly abroad to forage
for grain, and bring it home in the beak, without tasting it themselves,
to feed their young; so our pedants go picking knowledge here and there,
out of books, and hold it at the tongue's end, only to spit it out and
distribute it abroad. And here I cannot but smile to think how I have
paid myself in showing the foppery of this kind of learning, who myself
am so manifest an example; for, do I not the same thing throughout
almost this whole composition? I go here and there, culling out of
several books the sentences that best please me, not to keep them (for I
have no memory to retain them in), but to transplant them into this;
where, to say the truth, they are no more mine than in their first
places. We are, I conceive, knowing only in present knowledge, and not
at all in what is past, or more than is that which is to come. But the
worst on't is, their scholars and pupils are no better nourished by this
kind of inspiration; and it makes no deeper impression upon them, but
passes from hand to hand, only to make a show to be tolerable company,
and to tell pretty stories, like a counterfeit coin in counters, of no
other use or value, but to reckon with, or to set up at cards:
"Apud alios loqui didicerunt non ipsi secum."
["They have learned to speak from others, not from themselves."
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes, v. 36.]
"Non est loquendum, sed gubernandum."
["Speaking is not so necessary as governing."—Seneca, Ep., 108.]
Nature, to shew that there is nothing barbarous where she has the
sole conduct, oftentimes, in nations where art has the least to do,
causes productions of wit, such as may rival the greatest effect of art
whatever. In relation to what I am now speaking of, the Gascon proverb,
derived from a cornpipe, is very quaint and subtle:
"Bouha prou bouha, mas a remuda lous dits quem."
["You may blow till your eyes start out; but if once you offer to
stir your fingers, it is all over."]
We can say, Cicero says thus; these were the manners of Plato; these
are the very words of Aristotle: but what do we say ourselves? What do
we judge? A parrot would say as much as that.
And this puts me in mind of that rich gentleman of Rome,—[Calvisius
Sabinus. Seneca, Ep., 27.]—who had been solicitous, with very great
expense, to procure men that were excellent in all sorts of science,
whom he had always attending his person, to the end, that when amongst
his friends any occasion fell out of speaking of any subject whatsoever,
they might supply his place, and be ready to prompt him, one with a
sentence of Seneca, another with a verse of Homer, and so forth, every
one according to his talent; and he fancied this knowledge to be his
own, because it was in the heads of those who lived upon his bounty; as
they also do, whose learning consists in having noble libraries. I know
one, who, when I question him what he knows, he presently calls for a
book to shew me, and dares not venture to tell me so much, as that he
has piles in his posteriors, till first he has consulted his dictionary,
what piles and what posteriors are.
We take other men's knowledge and opinions upon trust; which is an
idle and superficial learning. We must make it our own. We are in this
very like him, who having need of fire, went to a neighbour's house to
fetch it, and finding a very good one there, sat down to warm himself
without remembering to carry any with him home.—[Plutarch, How a Man
should Listen.]—What good does it do us to have the stomach full of
meat, if it do not digest, if it be not incorporated with us, if it does
not nourish and support us? Can we imagine that Lucullus, whom letters,
without any manner of experience, made so great a captain, learned to be
so after this perfunctory manner?—[Cicero, Acad., ii. I.]—We suffer
ourselves to lean and rely so strongly upon the arm of another, that we
destroy our own strength and vigour. Would I fortify myself against the
fear of death, it must be at the expense of Seneca: would I extract
consolation for myself or my friend, I borrow it from Cicero. I might
have found it in myself, had I been trained to make use of my own
reason. I do not like this relative and mendicant understanding; for
though we could become learned by other men's learning, a man can never
be wise but by his own wisdom:
["I hate the wise man, who in his own concern is not wise."
—Euripides, ap. Cicero, Ep. Fam., xiii. 15.]
Whence Ennius:
"Nequidquam sapere sapientem, qui ipse sibi prodesse non quiret."
["That wise man knows nothing, who cannot profit himself by his
wisdom."—Cicero, De Offic., iii. 15.]
"Si cupidus, si
Vanus, et Euganea quantumvis mollior agna."
["If he be grasping, or a boaster, and something softer than an
Euganean lamb."—Juvenal, Sat., viii. 14.]
"Non enim paranda nobis solum, sed fruenda sapientia est."
["For wisdom is not only to be acquired, but to be utilised."
—Cicero, De Finib., i. I.]
Dionysius—[It was not Dionysius, but Diogenes the cynic. Diogenes
Laertius, vi. 27.]—laughed at the grammarians, who set themselves to
inquire into the miseries of Ulysses, and were ignorant of their own; at
musicians, who were so exact in tuning their instruments, and never
tuned their manners; at orators, who made it a study to declare what is
justice, but never took care to do it. If the mind be not better
disposed, if the judgment be no better settled, I had much rather my
scholar had spent his time at tennis, for, at least, his body would by
that means be in better exercise and breath. Do but observe him when he
comes back from school, after fifteen or sixteen years that he has been
there; there is nothing so unfit for employment; all you shall find he
has got, is, that his Latin and Greek have only made him a greater
coxcomb than when he went from home. He should bring back his soul
replete with good literature, and he brings it only swelled and puffed
up with vain and empty shreds and patches of learning; and has really
nothing more in him than he had before.—[Plato's Dialogues: Protagoras.]
These pedants of ours, as Plato says of the Sophists, their
cousin-germans, are, of all men, they who most pretend to be useful to
mankind, and who alone, of all men, not only do not better and improve
that which is committed to them, as a carpenter or a mason would do, but
make them much worse, and make us pay them for making them worse, to
boot. If the rule which Protagoras proposed to his pupils were followed
—either that they should give him his own demand, or make affidavit upon
oath in the temple how much they valued the profit they had received
under his tuition, and satisfy him accordingly—my pedagogues would find
themselves sorely gravelled, if they were to be judged by the affidavits
of my experience. My Perigordin patois very pleasantly calls these
pretenders to learning, 'lettre-ferits', as a man should say,
letter-marked—men on whom letters have been stamped by the blow of a
mallet. And, in truth, for the most part, they appear to be deprived
even of common sense; for you see the husbandman and the cobbler go
simply and fairly about their business, speaking only of what they know
and understand; whereas these fellows, to make parade and to get
opinion, mustering this ridiculous knowledge of theirs, that floats on
the superficies of the brain, are perpetually perplexing, and entangling
themselves in their own nonsense. They speak fine words sometimes, 'tis
true, but let somebody that is wiser apply them. They are wonderfully
well acquainted with Galen, but not at all with the disease of the
patient; they have already deafened you with a long ribble-row of laws,
but understand nothing of the case in hand; they have the theory of all
things, let who will put it in practice.
I have sat by, when a friend of mine, in my own house, for
sport-sake, has with one of these fellows counterfeited a jargon of
Galimatias, patched up of phrases without head or tail, saving that he
interlarded here and there some terms that had relation to their
dispute, and held the coxcomb in play a whole afternoon together, who
all the while thought he had answered pertinently and learnedly to all
his objections; and yet this was a man of letters, and reputation, and a
fine gentleman of the long robe:
"Vos, O patricius sanguis, quos vivere par est
Occipiti caeco, posticae occurrite sannae."
["O you, of patrician blood, to whom it is permitted to live
with(out) eyes in the back of your head, beware of grimaces at you
from behind."—Persius, Sat., i. 61.]
Whosoever shall narrowly pry into and thoroughly sift this sort of
people, wherewith the world is so pestered, will, as I have done, find,
that for the most part, they neither understand others, nor themselves;
and that their memories are full enough, but the judgment totally void
and empty; some excepted, whose own nature has of itself formed them
into better fashion. As I have observed, for example, in Adrian
Turnebus, who having never made other profession than that of mere
learning only, and in that, in my opinion, he was the greatest man that
has been these thousand years, had nothing at all in him of the pedant,
but the wearing of his gown, and a little exterior fashion, that could
not be civilised to courtier ways, which in themselves are nothing. I
hate our people, who can worse endure an ill-contrived robe than an
ill-contrived mind, and take their measure by the leg a man makes, by
his behaviour, and so much as the very fashion of his boots, what kind
of man he is. For within there was not a more polished soul upon earth.
I have often purposely put him upon arguments quite wide of his
profession, wherein I found he had so clear an insight, so quick an
apprehension, so solid a judgment, that a man would have thought he had
never practised any other thing but arms, and been all his life employed
in affairs of State. These are great and vigorous natures,
"Queis arte benigna
Et meliore luto finxit praecordia Titan."
["Whom benign Titan (Prometheus) has framed of better clay."
—Juvenal, xiv. 34.]
that can keep themselves upright in despite of a pedantic education.
But it is not enough that our education does not spoil us; it must,
moreover, alter us for the better.
Some of our Parliaments, when they are to admit officers, examine
only their learning; to which some of the others also add the trial of
understanding, by asking their judgment of some case in law; of these
the latter, methinks, proceed with the better method; for although both
are necessary, and that it is very requisite they should be defective in
neither, yet, in truth, knowledge is not so absolutely necessary as
judgment; the last may make shift without the other, but the other never
without this. For as the Greek verse says—
["To what use serves learning, if understanding be away."
—Apud Stobaeus, tit. iii., p. 37 (1609).]
Would to God that, for the good of our judicature, these societies
were as well furnished with understanding and conscience as they are
with knowledge.
"Non vita, sed scolae discimus."
["We do not study for life, but only for the school."
—Seneca, Ep., 106.]
We are not to tie learning to the soul, but to work and incorporate
them together: not to tincture it only, but to give it a thorough and
perfect dye; which, if it will not take colour, and meliorate its
imperfect state, it were without question better to let it alone. 'Tis a
dangerous weapon, that will hinder and wound its master, if put into an
awkward and unskilful hand:
"Ut fuerit melius non didicisse."
["So that it were better not to have learned."
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 4.]
And this, peradventure, is the reason why neither we nor theology
require much learning in women; and that Francis, Duke of Brittany, son
of John V., one talking with him about his marriage with Isabella the
daughter of Scotland, and adding that she was homely bred, and without
any manner of learning, made answer, that he liked her the better, and
that a woman was wise enough, if she could distinguish her husband's
shirt from his doublet. So that it is no so great wonder, as they make
of it, that our ancestors had letters in no greater esteem, and that
even to this day they are but rarely met with in the principal councils
of princes; and if the end and design of acquiring riches, which is the
only thing we propose to ourselves, by the means of law, physic,
pedantry, and even divinity itself, did not uphold and keep them in
credit, you would, with doubt, see them in as pitiful a condition as
ever. And what loss would this be, if they neither instruct us to think
well nor to do well?
"Postquam docti prodierunt, boni desunt."
[Seneca, Ep., 95. "Since the 'savans' have made their appearance
among us, the good people have become eclipsed."
—Rousseau, Discours sur les Lettres.]
All other knowledge is hurtful to him who has not the science of
goodness.
But the reason I glanced upon but now, may it not also hence proceed,
that, our studies in France having almost no other aim but profit,
except as to those who, by nature born to offices and employments rather
of glory than gain, addict themselves to letters, if at all, only for so
short a time (being taken from their studies before they can come to
have any taste of them, to a profession that has nothing to do with
books), there ordinarily remain no others to apply themselves wholly to
learning, but people of mean condition, who in that only seek the means
to live; and by such people, whose souls are, both by nature and by
domestic education and example, of the basest alloy the fruits of
knowledge are immaturely gathered and ill digested, and delivered to
their recipients quite another thing. For it is not for knowledge to
enlighten a soul that is dark of itself, nor to make a blind man see.
Her business is not to find a man's eyes, but to guide, govern, and
direct them, provided he have sound feet and straight legs to go upon.
Knowledge is an excellent drug, but no drug has virtue enough to
preserve itself from corruption and decay, if the vessel be tainted and
impure wherein it is put to keep. Such a one may have a sight clear
enough who looks asquint, and consequently sees what is good, but does
not follow it, and sees knowledge, but makes no use of it. Plato's
principal institution in his Republic is to fit his citizens with
employments suitable to their nature. Nature can do all, and does all.
Cripples are very unfit for exercises of the body, and lame souls for
exercises of the mind. Degenerate and vulgar souls are unworthy of
philosophy. If we see a shoemaker with his shoes out at the toes, we
say, 'tis no wonder; for, commonly, none go worse shod than they. In
like manner, experience often presents us a physician worse physicked, a
divine less reformed, and (constantly) a scholar of less sufficiency,
than other people.
Old Aristo of Chios had reason to say that philosophers did their
auditors harm, forasmuch as most of the souls of those that heard them
were not capable of deriving benefit from instruction, which, if not
applied to good, would certainly be applied to ill:
["They proceeded effeminate debauchees from the school of
Aristippus, cynics from that of Zeno."
—Cicero, De Natura Deor., iii., 31.]
In that excellent institution that Xenophon attributes to the
Persians, we find that they taught their children virtue, as other
nations do letters. Plato tells us that the eldest son in their royal
succession was thus brought up; after his birth he was delivered, not to
women, but to eunuchs of the greatest authority about their kings for
their virtue, whose charge it was to keep his body healthful and in good
plight; and after he came to seven years of age, to teach him to ride
and to go a-hunting. When he arrived at fourteen he was transferred into
the hands of four, the wisest, the most just, the most temperate, and
most valiant of the nation; of whom the first was to instruct him in
religion, the second to be always upright and sincere, the third to
conquer his appetites and desires, and the fourth to despise all danger.
It is a thing worthy of very great consideration, that in that
excellent, and, in truth, for its perfection, prodigious form of civil
regimen set down by Lycurgus, though so solicitous of the education of
children, as a thing of the greatest concern, and even in the very seat
of the Muses, he should make so little mention of learning; as if that
generous youth, disdaining all other subjection but that of virtue,
ought to be supplied, instead of tutors to read to them arts and
sciences, with such masters as should only instruct them in valour,
prudence, and justice; an example that Plato has followed in his laws.
The manner of their discipline was to propound to them questions in
judgment upon men and their actions; and if they commended or condemned
this or that person or fact, they were to give a reason for so doing; by
which means they at once sharpened their understanding, and learned what
was right. Astyages, in Xenophon, asks Cyrus to give an account of his
last lesson; and thus it was, "A great boy in our school, having a
little short cassock, by force took a longer from another that was not
so tall as he, and gave him his own in exchange: whereupon I, being
appointed judge of the controversy, gave judgment, that I thought it
best each should keep the coat he had, for that they both of them were
better fitted with that of one another than with their own: upon which
my master told me, I had done ill, in that I had only considered the
fitness of the garments, whereas I ought to have considered the justice
of the thing, which required that no one should have anything forcibly
taken from him that is his own." And Cyrus adds that he was whipped for
his pains, as we are in our villages for forgetting the first aorist
of———.
[Cotton's version of this story commences differently, and includes
a passage which is not in any of the editions of the original before
me:
"Mandane, in Xenophon, asking Cyrus how he would do to learn
justice, and the other virtues amongst the Medes, having left all
his masters behind him in Persia? He made answer, that he had
learned those things long since; that his master had often made him
a judge of the differences amongst his schoolfellows, and had one
day whipped him for giving a wrong sentence."—W.C.H.]
My pedant must make me a very learned oration, 'in genere
demonstrativo', before he can persuade me that his school is like unto
that. They knew how to go the readiest way to work; and seeing that
science, when most rightly applied and best understood, can do no more
but teach us prudence, moral honesty, and resolution, they thought fit,
at first hand, to initiate their children with the knowledge of effects,
and to instruct them, not by hearsay and rote, but by the experiment of
action, in lively forming and moulding them; not only by words and
precepts, but chiefly by works and examples; to the end it might not be
a knowledge in the mind only, but its complexion and habit: not an
acquisition, but a natural possession. One asking to this purpose,
Agesilaus, what he thought most proper for boys to learn? "What they
ought to do when they come to be men," said he.—[Plutarch, Apothegms of
the Lacedamonians. Rousseau adopts the expression in his Diswuys sur tes
Lettres.]—It is no wonder, if such an institution produced so admirable
effects.
They used to go, it is said, to the other cities of Greece, to
inquire out rhetoricians, painters, and musicians; but to Lacedaemon for
legislators, magistrates, and generals of armies; at Athens they learned
to speak well: here to do well; there to disengage themselves from a
sophistical argument, and to unravel the imposture of captious
syllogisms; here to evade the baits and allurements of pleasure, and
with a noble courage and resolution to conquer the menaces of fortune
and death; those cudgelled their brains about words, these made it their
business to inquire into things; there was an eternal babble of the
tongue, here a continual exercise of the soul. And therefore it is
nothing strange if, when Antipater demanded of them fifty children for
hostages, they made answer, quite contrary to what we should do, that
they would rather give him twice as many full-grown men, so much did
they value the loss of their country's education. When Agesilaus courted
Xenophon to send his children to Sparta to be bred, "it is not," said
he, "there to learn logic or rhetoric, but to be instructed in the
noblest of all sciences, namely, the science to obey and to
command."—[Plutarch, Life of Agesilaus, c. 7.]
It is very pleasant to see Socrates, after his manner, rallying
Hippias, —[Plato's Dialogues: Hippias Major.]—who recounts to him what a
world of money he has got, especially in certain little villages of
Sicily, by teaching school, and that he made never a penny at Sparta:
"What a sottish and stupid people," said Socrates, "are they, without
sense or understanding, that make no account either of grammar or
poetry, and only busy themselves in studying the genealogies and
successions of their kings, the foundations, rises, and declensions of
states, and such tales of a tub!" After which, having made Hippias from
one step to another acknowledge the excellency of their form of public
administration, and the felicity and virtue of their private life, he
leaves him to guess at the conclusion he makes of the inutilities of his
pedantic arts.
Examples have demonstrated to us that in military affairs, and all
others of the like active nature, the study of sciences more softens and
untempers the courages of men than it in any way fortifies and excites
them. The most potent empire that at this day appears to be in the whole
world is that of the Turks, a people equally inured to the estimation of
arms and the contempt of letters. I find Rome was more valiant before
she grew so learned. The most warlike nations at this time in being are
the most rude and ignorant: the Scythians, the Parthians, Tamerlane,
serve for sufficient proof of this. When the Goths overran Greece, the
only thing that preserved all the libraries from the fire was, that some
one possessed them with an opinion that they were to leave this kind of
furniture entire to the enemy, as being most proper to divert them from
the exercise of arms, and to fix them to a lazy and sedentary life. When
our King Charles VIII., almost without striking a blow, saw himself
possessed of the kingdom of Naples and a considerable part of Tuscany,
the nobles about him attributed this unexpected facility of conquest to
this, that the princes and nobles of Italy, more studied to render
themselves ingenious and learned, than vigorous and warlike.
CHAPTER XXV——OF THE EDUCATION OF CHILDREN
TO MADAME DIANE DE FOIX, Comtesse de Gurson
I never yet saw that father, but let his son be never so decrepit or
deformed, would not, notwithstanding, own him: not, nevertheless, if he
were not totally besotted, and blinded with his paternal affection, that
he did not well enough discern his defects; but that with all defaults
he was still his. Just so, I see better than any other, that all I write
here are but the idle reveries of a man that has only nibbled upon the
outward crust of sciences in his nonage, and only retained a general and
formless image of them; who has got a little snatch of everything and
nothing of the whole, 'a la Francoise'. For I know, in general, that
there is such a thing as physic, as jurisprudence: four parts in
mathematics, and, roughly, what all these aim and point at; and,
peradventure, I yet know farther, what sciences in general pretend unto,
in order to the service of our life: but to dive farther than that, and
to have cudgelled my brains in the study of Aristotle, the monarch of
all modern learning, or particularly addicted myself to any one science,
I have never done it; neither is there any one art of which I am able to
draw the first lineaments and dead colour; insomuch that there is not a
boy of the lowest form in a school, that may not pretend to be wiser
than I, who am not able to examine him in his first lesson, which, if I
am at any time forced upon, I am necessitated in my own defence, to ask
him, unaptly enough, some universal questions, such as may serve to try
his natural understanding; a lesson as strange and unknown to him, as
his is to me.
I never seriously settled myself to the reading any book of solid
learning but Plutarch and Seneca; and there, like the Danaides, I
eternally fill, and it as constantly runs out; something of which drops
upon this paper, but little or nothing stays with me. History is my
particular game as to matter of reading, or else poetry, for which I
have particular kindness and esteem: for, as Cleanthes said, as the
voice, forced through the narrow passage of a trumpet, comes out more
forcible and shrill: so, methinks, a sentence pressed within the harmony
of verse darts out more briskly upon the understanding, and strikes my
ear and apprehension with a smarter and more pleasing effect. As to the
natural parts I have, of which this is the essay, I find them to bow
under the burden; my fancy and judgment do but grope in the dark,
tripping and stumbling in the way; and when I have gone as far as I can,
I am in no degree satisfied; I discover still a new and greater extent
of land before me, with a troubled and imperfect sight and wrapped up in
clouds, that I am not able to penetrate. And taking upon me to write
indifferently of whatever comes into my head, and therein making use of
nothing but my own proper and natural means, if it befall me, as
oft-times it does, accidentally to meet in any good author, the same
heads and commonplaces upon which I have attempted to write (as I did
but just now in Plutarch's "Discourse of the Force of Imagination"), to
see myself so weak and so forlorn, so heavy and so flat, in comparison
of those better writers, I at once pity or despise myself. Yet do I
please myself with this, that my opinions have often the honour and good
fortune to jump with theirs, and that I go in the same path, though at a
very great distance, and can say, "Ah, that is so." I am farther
satisfied to find that I have a quality, which every one is not blessed
withal, which is, to discern the vast difference between them and me;
and notwithstanding all that, suffer my own inventions, low and feeble
as they are, to run on in their career, without mending or plastering up
the defects that this comparison has laid open to my own view. And, in
plain truth, a man had need of a good strong back to keep pace with
these people. The indiscreet scribblers of our times, who, amongst their
laborious nothings, insert whole sections and pages out of ancient
authors, with a design, by that means, to illustrate their own writings,
do quite contrary; for this infinite dissimilitude of ornaments renders
the complexion of their own compositions so sallow and deformed, that
they lose much more than they get.
The philosophers, Chrysippus and Epicurus, were in this of two quite
contrary humours: the first not only in his books mixed passages and
sayings of other authors, but entire pieces, and, in one, the whole
Medea of Euripides; which gave Apollodorus occasion to say, that should
a man pick out of his writings all that was none of his, he would leave
him nothing but blank paper: whereas the latter, quite on the contrary,
in three hundred volumes that he left behind him, has not so much as one
quotation.—[Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Chyysippus, vii. 181, and
Epicurus, x. 26.]
I happened the other day upon this piece of fortune; I was reading a
French book, where after I had a long time run dreaming over a great
many words, so dull, so insipid, so void of all wit or common sense,
that indeed they were only French words: after a long and tedious
travel, I came at last to meet with a piece that was lofty, rich, and
elevated to the very clouds; of which, had I found either the declivity
easy or the ascent gradual, there had been some excuse; but it was so
perpendicular a precipice, and so wholly cut off from the rest of the
work, that by the first six words, I found myself flying into the other
world, and thence discovered the vale whence I came so deep and low,
that I have never had since the heart to descend into it any more. If I
should set out one of my discourses with such rich spoils as these, it
would but too evidently manifest the imperfection of my own writing. To
reprehend the fault in others that I am guilty of myself, appears to me
no more unreasonable, than to condemn, as I often do, those of others in
myself: they are to be everywhere reproved, and ought to have no
sanctuary allowed them. I know very well how audaciously I myself, at
every turn, attempt to equal myself to my thefts, and to make my style
go hand in hand with them, not without a temerarious hope of deceiving
the eyes of my reader from discerning the difference; but withal it is
as much by the benefit of my application, that I hope to do it, as by
that of my invention or any force of my own. Besides, I do not offer to
contend with the whole body of these champions, nor hand to hand with
anyone of them: 'tis only by flights and little light attempts that I
engage them; I do not grapple with them, but try their strength only,
and never engage so far as I make a show to do. If I could hold them in
play, I were a brave fellow; for I never attack them; but where they are
most sinewy and strong. To cover a man's self (as I have seen some do)
with another man's armour, so as not to discover so much as his fingers'
ends; to carry on a design (as it is not hard for a man that has
anything of a scholar in him, in an ordinary subject to do) under old
inventions patched up here and there with his own trumpery, and then to
endeavour to conceal the theft, and to make it pass for his own, is
first injustice and meanness of spirit in those who do it, who having
nothing in them of their own fit to procure them a reputation, endeavour
to do it by attempting to impose things upon the world in their own
name, which they have no manner of title to; and next, a ridiculous
folly to content themselves with acquiring the ignorant approbation of
the vulgar by such a pitiful cheat, at the price at the same time of
degrading themselves in the eyes of men of understanding, who turn up
their noses at all this borrowed incrustation, yet whose praise alone is
worth the having. For my own part, there is nothing I would not sooner
do than that, neither have I said so much of others, but to get a better
opportunity to explain myself. Nor in this do I glance at the composers
of centos, who declare themselves for such; of which sort of writers I
have in my time known many very ingenious, and particularly one under
the name of Capilupus, besides the ancients. These are really men of
wit, and that make it appear they are so, both by that and other ways of
writing; as for example, Lipsius, in that learned and laborious
contexture of his Politics.
But, be it how it will, and how inconsiderable soever these
ineptitudes may be, I will say I never intended to conceal them, no more
than my old bald grizzled likeness before them, where the painter has
presented you not with a perfect face, but with mine. For these are my
own particular opinions and fancies, and I deliver them as only what I
myself believe, and not for what is to be believed by others. I have no
other end in this writing, but only to discover myself, who, also shall,
peradventure, be another thing to-morrow, if I chance to meet any new
instruction to change me. I have no authority to be believed, neither do
I desire it, being too conscious of my own inerudition to be able to
instruct others.
Some one, then, having seen the preceding chapter, the other day told
me at my house, that I should a little farther have extended my
discourse on the education of children.—["Which, how fit I am to do, let
my friends flatter me if they please, I have in the meantime no such
opinion of my own talent, as to promise myself any very good success
from my endeavour." This passage would appear to be an interpolation by
Cotton. At all events, I do not find it in the original editions before
me, or in Coste.]—
Now, madam, if I had any sufficiency in this subject, I could not
possibly better employ it, than to present my best instructions to the
little man that threatens you shortly with a happy birth (for you are
too generous to begin otherwise than with a male); for, having had so
great a hand in the treaty of your marriage, I have a certain particular
right and interest in the greatness and prosperity of the issue that
shall spring from it; beside that, your having had the best of my
services so long in possession, sufficiently obliges me to desire the
honour and advantage of all wherein you shall be concerned. But, in
truth, all I understand as to that particular is only this, that the
greatest and most important difficulty of human science is the education
of children. For as in agriculture, the husbandry that is to precede
planting, as also planting itself, is certain, plain, and well known;
but after that which is planted comes to life, there is a great deal
more to be done, more art to be used, more care to be taken, and much
more difficulty to cultivate and bring it to perfection so it is with
men; it is no hard matter to get children; but after they are born, then
begins the trouble, solicitude, and care rightly to train, principle,
and bring them up. The symptoms of their inclinations in that tender age
are so obscure, and the promises so uncertain and fallacious, that it is
very hard to establish any solid judgment or conjecture upon them. Look
at Cimon, for example, and Themistocles, and a thousand others, who very
much deceived the expectation men had of them. Cubs of bears and puppies
readily discover their natural inclination; but men, so soon as ever
they are grownup, applying themselves to certain habits, engaging
themselves in certain opinions, and conforming themselves to particular
laws and customs, easily alter, or at least disguise, their true and
real disposition; and yet it is hard to force the propension of nature.
Whence it comes to pass, that for not having chosen the right course, we
often take very great pains, and consume a good part of our time in
training up children to things, for which, by their natural
constitution, they are totally unfit. In this difficulty, nevertheless,
I am clearly of opinion, that they ought to be elemented in the best and
most advantageous studies, without taking too much notice of, or being
too superstitious in those light prognostics they give of themselves in
their tender years, and to which Plato, in his Republic, gives,
methinks, too much authority.
Madam, science is a very great ornament, and a thing of marvellous
use, especially in persons raised to that degree of fortune in which you
are. And, in truth, in persons of mean and low condition, it cannot
perform its true and genuine office, being naturally more prompt to
assist in the conduct of war, in the government of peoples, in
negotiating the leagues and friendships of princes and foreign nations,
than in forming a syllogism in logic, in pleading a process in law, or
in prescribing a dose of pills in physic. Wherefore, madam, believing
you will not omit this so necessary feature in the education of your
children, who yourself have tasted its sweetness, and are of a learned
extraction (for we yet have the writings of the ancient Counts of Foix,
from whom my lord, your husband, and yourself, are both of you
descended, and Monsieur de Candale, your uncle, every day obliges the
world with others, which will extend the knowledge of this quality in
your family for so many succeeding ages), I will, upon this occasion,
presume to acquaint your ladyship with one particular fancy of my own,
contrary to the common method, which is all I am able to contribute to
your service in this affair.
The charge of the tutor you shall provide for your son, upon the
choice of whom depends the whole success of his education, has several
other great and considerable parts and duties required in so important a
trust, besides that of which I am about to speak: these, however, I
shall not mention, as being unable to add anything of moment to the
common rules: and in this, wherein I take upon me to advise, he may
follow it so far only as it shall appear advisable.
For a, boy of quality then, who pretends to letters not upon the
account of profit (for so mean an object is unworthy of the grace and
favour of the Muses, and moreover, in it a man directs his service to
and depends upon others), nor so much for outward ornament, as for his
own proper and peculiar use, and to furnish and enrich himself within,
having rather a desire to come out an accomplished cavalier than a mere
scholar or learned man; for such a one, I say, I would, also, have his
friends solicitous to find him out a tutor, who has rather a well-made
than a well-filled head;—["'Tete bien faite', an expression created by
Montaigne, and which has remained a part of our language."—Servan.]—
seeking, indeed, both the one and the other, but rather of the two to
prefer manners and judgment to mere learning, and that this man should
exercise his charge after a new method.
'Tis the custom of pedagogues to be eternally thundering in their
pupil's ears, as they were pouring into a funnel, whilst the business of
the pupil is only to repeat what the others have said: now I would have
a tutor to correct this error, and, that at the very first, he should
according to the capacity he has to deal with, put it to the test,
permitting his pupil himself to taste things, and of himself to discern
and choose them, sometimes opening the way to him, and sometimes leaving
him to open it for himself; that is, I would not have him alone to
invent and speak, but that he should also hear his pupil speak in turn.
Socrates, and since him Arcesilaus, made first their scholars speak, and
then they spoke to them—[Diogenes Laertius, iv. 36.]
"Obest plerumque iis, qui discere volunt,
auctoritas eorum, qui docent."
["The authority of those who teach, is very often an impediment to
those who desire to learn."—Cicero, De Natura Deor., i. 5.]
It is good to make him, like a young horse, trot before him, that he
may judge of his going, and how much he is to abate of his own speed, to
accommodate himself to the vigour and capacity of the other. For want of
which due proportion we spoil all; which also to know how to adjust, and
to keep within an exact and due measure, is one of the hardest things I
know, and 'tis the effect of a high and well-tempered soul, to know how
to condescend to such puerile motions and to govern and direct them. I
walk firmer and more secure up hill than down.
Such as, according to our common way of teaching, undertake, with one
and the same lesson, and the same measure of direction, to instruct
several boys of differing and unequal capacities, are infinitely
mistaken; and 'tis no wonder, if in a whole multitude of scholars, there
are not found above two or three who bring away any good account of
their time and discipline. Let the master not only examine him about the
grammatical construction of the bare words of his lesson, but about the
sense and let him judge of the profit he has made, not by the testimony
of his memory, but by that of his life. Let him make him put what he has
learned into a hundred several forms, and accommodate it to so many
several subjects, to see if he yet rightly comprehends it, and has made
it his own, taking instruction of his progress by the pedagogic
institutions of Plato. 'Tis a sign of crudity and indigestion to
disgorge what we eat in the same condition it was swallowed; the stomach
has not performed its office unless it have altered the form and
condition of what was committed to it to concoct. Our minds work only
upon trust, when bound and compelled to follow the appetite of another's
fancy, enslaved and captivated under the authority of another's
instruction; we have been so subjected to the trammel, that we have no
free, nor natural pace of our own; our own vigour and liberty are
extinct and gone:
"Nunquam tutelae suae fiunt."
["They are ever in wardship."—Seneca, Ep., 33.]
I was privately carried at Pisa to see a very honest man, but so
great an Aristotelian, that his most usual thesis was: "That the
touchstone and square of all solid imagination, and of all truth, was an
absolute conformity to Aristotle's doctrine; and that all besides was
nothing but inanity and chimera; for that he had seen all, and said
all." A position, that for having been a little too injuriously and
broadly interpreted, brought him once and long kept him in great danger
of the Inquisition at Rome.
Let him make him examine and thoroughly sift everything he reads, and
lodge nothing in his fancy upon simple authority and upon trust.
Aristotle's principles will then be no more principles to him, than
those of Epicurus and the Stoics: let this diversity of opinions be
propounded to, and laid before him; he will himself choose, if he be
able; if not, he will remain in doubt.
"Che non men the saver, dubbiar m' aggrata."
["I love to doubt, as well as to know."—Dante, Inferno, xi. 93]
for, if he embrace the opinions of Xenophon and Plato, by his own
reason, they will no more be theirs, but become his own. Who follows
another, follows nothing, finds nothing, nay, is inquisitive after
nothing.
"Non sumus sub rege; sibi quisque se vindicet."
["We are under no king; let each vindicate himself."
—Seneca, Ep.,33]
Let him, at least, know that he knows. It will be necessary that he
imbibe their knowledge, not that he be corrupted with their precepts;
and no matter if he forget where he had his learning, provided he know
how to apply it to his own use. Truth and reason are common to every
one, and are no more his who spake them first, than his who speaks them
after: 'tis no more according to Plato, than according to me, since both
he and I equally see and understand them. Bees cull their several sweets
from this flower and that blossom, here and there where they find them,
but themselves afterwards make the honey, which is all and purely their
own, and no more thyme and marjoram: so the several fragments he borrows
from others, he will transform and shuffle together to compile a work
that shall be absolutely his own; that is to say, his judgment: his
instruction, labour and study, tend to nothing else but to form that. He
is not obliged to discover whence he got the materials that have
assisted him, but only to produce what he has himself done with them.
Men that live upon pillage and borrowing, expose their purchases and
buildings to every one's view: but do not proclaim how they came by the
money. We do not see the fees and perquisites of a gentleman of the long
robe; but we see the alliances wherewith he fortifies himself and his
family, and the titles and honours he has obtained for him and his. No
man divulges his revenue; or, at least, which way it comes in but every
one publishes his acquisitions. The advantages of our study are to
become better and more wise. 'Tis, says Epicharmus, the understanding
that sees and hears, 'tis the understanding that improves everything,
that orders everything, and that acts, rules, and reigns: all other
faculties are blind, and deaf, and without soul. And certainly we render
it timorous and servile, in not allowing it the liberty and privilege to
do anything of itself. Whoever asked his pupil what he thought of
grammar and rhetoric, or of such and such a sentence of Cicero? Our
masters stick them, full feathered, in our memories, and there establish
them like oracles, of which the letters and syllables are of the
substance of the thing. To know by rote, is no knowledge, and signifies
no more but only to retain what one has intrusted to our memory. That
which a man rightly knows and understands, he is the free disposer of at
his own full liberty, without any regard to the author from whence he
had it, or fumbling over the leaves of his book. A mere bookish learning
is a poor, paltry learning; it may serve for ornament, but there is yet
no foundation for any superstructure to be built upon it, according to
the opinion of Plato, who says, that constancy, faith, and sincerity,
are the true philosophy, and the other sciences, that are directed to
other ends; mere adulterate paint. I could wish that Paluel or Pompey,
those two noted dancers of my time, could have taught us to cut capers,
by only seeing them do it, without stirring from our places, as these
men pretend to inform the understanding without ever setting it to work,
or that we could learn to ride, handle a pike, touch a lute, or sing
without the trouble of practice, as these attempt to make us judge and
speak well, without exercising us in judging or speaking. Now in this
initiation of our studies in their progress, whatsoever presents itself
before us is book sufficient; a roguish trick of a page, a sottish
mistake of a servant, a jest at the table, are so many new subjects.
And for this reason, conversation with men is of very great use and
travel into foreign countries; not to bring back (as most of our young
monsieurs do) an account only of how many paces Santa Rotonda—[The
Pantheon of Agrippa.]—is in circuit; or of the richness of Signora
Livia's petticoats; or, as some others, how much Nero's face, in a
statue in such an old ruin, is longer and broader than that made for him
on some medal; but to be able chiefly to give an account of the humours,
manners, customs, and laws of those nations where he has been, and that
we may whet and sharpen our wits by rubbing them against those of
others. I would that a boy should be sent abroad very young, and first,
so as to kill two birds with one stone, into those neighbouring nations
whose language is most differing from our own, and to which, if it be
not formed betimes, the tongue will grow too stiff to bend.
And also 'tis the general opinion of all, that a child should not be
brought up in his mother's lap. Mothers are too tender, and their
natural affection is apt to make the most discreet of them all so
overfond, that they can neither find in their hearts to give them due
correction for the faults they may commit, nor suffer them to be inured
to hardships and hazards, as they ought to be. They will not endure to
see them return all dust and sweat from their exercise, to drink cold
drink when they are hot, nor see them mount an unruly horse, nor take a
foil in hand against a rude fencer, or so much as to discharge a
carbine. And yet there is no remedy; whoever will breed a boy to be good
for anything when he comes to be a man, must by no means spare him when
young, and must very often transgress the rules of physic:
"Vitamque sub dio, et trepidis agat
In rebus."
["Let him live in open air, and ever in movement about something."
—Horace, Od. ii., 3, 5.]
It is not enough to fortify his soul; you are also to make his sinews
strong; for the soul will be oppressed if not assisted by the members,
and would have too hard a task to discharge two offices alone. I know
very well to my cost, how much mine groans under the burden, from being
accommodated with a body so tender and indisposed, as eternally leans
and presses upon her; and often in my reading perceive that our masters,
in their writings, make examples pass for magnanimity and fortitude of
mind, which really are rather toughness of skin and hardness of bones;
for I have seen men, women, and children, naturally born of so hard and
insensible a constitution of body, that a sound cudgelling has been less
to them than a flirt with a finger would have been to me, and that would
neither cry out, wince, nor shrink, for a good swinging beating; and
when wrestlers counterfeit the philosophers in patience, 'tis rather
strength of nerves than stoutness of heart. Now to be inured to undergo
labour, is to be accustomed to endure pain:
"Labor callum obducit dolori."
["Labour hardens us against pain."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 15.]
A boy is to be broken in to the toil and roughness of exercise, so as
to be trained up to the pain and suffering of dislocations, cholics,
cauteries, and even imprisonment and the rack itself; for he may come by
misfortune to be reduced to the worst of these, which (as this world
goes) is sometimes inflicted on the good as well as the bad. As for
proof, in our present civil war whoever draws his sword against the
laws, threatens the honestest men with the whip and the halter.
And, moreover, by living at home, the authority of this governor,
which ought to be sovereign over the boy he has received into his
charge, is often checked and hindered by the presence of parents; to
which may also be added, that the respect the whole family pay him, as
their master's son, and the knowledge he has of the estate and greatness
he is heir to, are, in my opinion, no small inconveniences in these
tender years.
And yet, even in this conversing with men I spoke of but now, I have
observed this vice, that instead of gathering observations from others,
we make it our whole business to lay ourselves open to them, and are
more concerned how to expose and set out our own commodities, than how
to increase our stock by acquiring new. Silence, therefore, and modesty
are very advantageous qualities in conversation. One should, therefore,
train up this boy to be sparing and an husband of his knowledge when he
has acquired it; and to forbear taking exceptions at or reproving every
idle saying or ridiculous story that is said or told in his presence;
for it is a very unbecoming rudeness to carp at everything that is not
agreeable to our own palate. Let him be satisfied with correcting
himself, and not seem to condemn everything in another he would not do
himself, nor dispute it as against common customs.
"Licet sapere sine pompa, sine invidia."
["Let us be wise without ostentation, without envy."
—Seneca, Ep., 103.]
Let him avoid these vain and uncivil images of authority, this
childish ambition of coveting to appear better bred and more
accomplished, than he really will, by such carriage, discover himself to
be. And, as if opportunities of interrupting and reprehending were not
to be omitted, to desire thence to derive the reputation of something
more than ordinary. For as it becomes none but great poets to make use
of the poetical licence, so it is intolerable for any but men of great
and illustrious souls to assume privilege above the authority of custom:
"Si quid Socrates ant Aristippus contra morem et consuetudinem
fecerunt, idem sibi ne arbitretur licere: magnis enim illi et
divinis bonis hanc licentiam assequebantur."
["If Socrates and Aristippus have committed any act against manners
and custom, let him not think that he is allowed to do the same; for
it was by great and divine benefits that they obtained this
privilege."—Cicero, De Offic., i. 41.]
Let him be instructed not to engage in discourse or dispute but with
a champion worthy of him, and, even there, not to make use of all the
little subtleties that may seem pat for his purpose, but only such
arguments as may best serve him. Let him be taught to be curious in the
election and choice of his reasons, to abominate impertinence, and
consequently, to affect brevity; but, above all, let him be lessoned to
acquiesce and submit to truth so soon as ever he shall discover it,
whether in his opponent's argument, or upon better consideration of his
own; for he shall never be preferred to the chair for a mere clatter of
words and syllogisms, and is no further engaged to any argument
whatever, than as he shall in his own judgment approve it: nor yet is
arguing a trade, where the liberty of recantation and getting off upon
better thoughts, are to be sold for ready money:
"Neque, ut omnia, qux praescripta et imperata sint,
defendat, necessitate ulla cogitur."
["Neither is their any necessity upon him, that he should defend
all things that are prescribed and enjoined him."
—Cicero, Acad., ii. 3.]
If his governor be of my humour, he will form his will to be a very
good and loyal subject to his prince, very affectionate to his person,
and very stout in his quarrel; but withal he will cool in him the desire
of having any other tie to his service than public duty. Besides several
other inconveniences that are inconsistent with the liberty every honest
man ought to have, a man's judgment, being bribed and prepossessed by
these particular obligations, is either blinded and less free to
exercise its function, or is blemished with ingratitude and
indiscretion. A man that is purely a courtier, can neither have power
nor will to speak or think otherwise than favourably and well of a
master, who, amongst so many millions of other subjects, has picked out
him with his own hand to nourish and advance; this favour, and the
profit flowing from it, must needs, and not without some show of reason,
corrupt his freedom and dazzle him; and we commonly see these people
speak in another kind of phrase than is ordinarily spoken by others of
the same nation, though what they say in that courtly language is not
much to be believed.
Let his conscience and virtue be eminently manifest in his speaking,
and have only reason for their guide. Make him understand, that to
acknowledge the error he shall discover in his own argument, though only
found out by himself, is an effect of judgment and sincerity, which are
the principal things he is to seek after; that obstinacy and contention
are common qualities, most appearing in mean souls; that to revise and
correct himself, to forsake an unjust argument in the height and heat of
dispute, are rare, great, and philosophical qualities.
Let him be advised, being in company, to have his eye and ear in
every corner; for I find that the places of greatest honour are commonly
seized upon by men that have least in them, and that the greatest
fortunes are seldom accompanied with the ablest parts. I have been
present when, whilst they at the upper end of the chamber have been only
commenting the beauty of the arras, or the flavour of the wine, many
things that have been very finely said at the lower end of the table
have been lost and thrown away. Let him examine every man's talent; a
peasant, a bricklayer, a passenger: one may learn something from every
one of these in their several capacities, and something will be picked
out of their discourse whereof some use may be made at one time or
another; nay, even the folly and impertinence of others will contribute
to his instruction. By observing the graces and manners of all he sees,
he will create to himself an emulation of the good, and a contempt of
the bad.
Let an honest curiosity be suggested to his fancy of being
inquisitive after everything; whatever there is singular and rare near
the place where he is, let him go and see it; a fine house, a noble
fountain, an eminent man, the place where a battle has been anciently
fought, the passages of Caesar and Charlemagne:
"Qux tellus sit lenta gelu, quae putris ab aestu,
Ventus in Italiam quis bene vela ferat."
["What country is bound in frost, what land is friable with heat,
what wind serves fairest for Italy."—Propertius, iv. 3, 39.]
Let him inquire into the manners, revenues, and alliances of princes,
things in themselves very pleasant to learn, and very useful to know.
In this conversing with men, I mean also, and principally, those who
only live in the records of history; he shall, by reading those books,
converse with the great and heroic souls of the best ages. 'Tis an idle
and vain study to those who make it so by doing it after a negligent
manner, but to those who do it with care and observation, 'tis a study
of inestimable fruit and value; and the only study, as Plato reports,
that the Lacedaemonians reserved to themselves. What profit shall he not
reap as to the business of men, by reading the Lives of Plutarch? But,
withal, let my governor remember to what end his instructions are
principally directed, and that he do not so much imprint in his pupil's
memory the date of the ruin of Carthage, as the manners of Hannibal and
Scipio; nor so much where Marcellus died, as why it was unworthy of his
duty that he died there. Let him not teach him so much the narrative
parts of history as to judge them; the reading of them, in my opinion,
is a thing that of all others we apply ourselves unto with the most
differing measure. I have read a hundred things in Livy that another has
not, or not taken notice of at least; and Plutarch has read a hundred
more there than ever I could find, or than, peradventure, that author
ever wrote; to some it is merely a grammar study, to others the very
anatomy of philosophy, by which the most abstruse parts of our human
nature penetrate. There are in Plutarch many long discourses very worthy
to be carefully read and observed, for he is, in my opinion, of all
others the greatest master in that kind of writing; but there are a
thousand others which he has only touched and glanced upon, where he
only points with his finger to direct us which way we may go if we will,
and contents himself sometimes with giving only one brisk hit in the
nicest article of the question, whence we are to grope out the rest. As,
for example, where he says'—[In the Essay on False Shame.]—that the
inhabitants of Asia came to be vassals to one only, for not having been
able to pronounce one syllable, which is No. Which saying of his gave
perhaps matter and occasion to La Boetie to write his "Voluntary
Servitude." Only to see him pick out a light action in a man's life, or
a mere word that does not seem to amount even to that, is itself a whole
discourse. 'Tis to our prejudice that men of understanding should so
immoderately affect brevity; no doubt their reputation is the better by
it, but in the meantime we are the worse. Plutarch had rather we should
applaud his judgment than commend his knowledge, and had rather leave us
with an appetite to read more, than glutted with that we have already
read. He knew very well, that a man may say too much even upon the best
subjects, and that Alexandridas justly reproached him who made very
good. but too long speeches to the Ephori, when he said: "O stranger!
thou speakest the things thou shouldst speak, but not as thou shouldst
speak them."—[Plutarch, Apothegms of the Lacedamonians.]—Such as have
lean and spare bodies stuff themselves out with clothes; so they who are
defective in matter endeavour to make amends with words.
Human understanding is marvellously enlightened by daily conversation
with men, for we are, otherwise, compressed and heaped up in ourselves,
and have our sight limited to the length of our own noses. One asking
Socrates of what country he was, he did not make answer, of Athens, but
of the world;—[Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., v. 37; Plutarch, On Exile, c. 4.]—
he whose imagination was fuller and wider, embraced the whole world for
his country, and extended his society and friendship to all mankind; not
as we do, who look no further than our feet. When the vines of my
village are nipped with the frost, my parish priest presently concludes,
that the indignation of God has gone out against all the human race, and
that the cannibals have already got the pip. Who is it that, seeing the
havoc of these civil wars of ours, does not cry out, that the machine of
the world is near dissolution, and that the day of judgment is at hand;
without considering, that many worse things have been seen, and that in
the meantime, people are very merry in a thousand other parts of the
earth for all this? For my part, considering the licence and impunity
that always attend such commotions, I wonder they are so moderate, and
that there is no more mischief done. To him who feels the hailstones
patter about his ears, the whole hemisphere appears to be in storm and
tempest; like the ridiculous Savoyard, who said very gravely, that if
that simple king of France could have managed his fortune as he should
have done, he might in time have come to have been steward of the
household to the duke his master: the fellow could not, in his shallow
imagination, conceive that there could be anything greater than a Duke
of Savoy. And, in truth, we are all of us, insensibly, in this error, an
error of a very great weight and very pernicious consequence. But
whoever shall represent to his fancy, as in a picture, that great image
of our mother nature, in her full majesty and lustre, whoever in her
face shall read so general and so constant a variety, whoever shall
observe himself in that figure, and not himself but a whole kingdom, no
bigger than the least touch or prick of a pencil in comparison of the
whole, that man alone is able to value things according to their true
estimate and grandeur.
This great world which some do yet multiply as several species under
one genus, is the mirror wherein we are to behold ourselves, to be able
to know ourselves as we ought to do in the true bias. In short, I would
have this to be the book my young gentleman should study with the most
attention. So many humours, so many sects, so many judgments, opinions,
laws, and customs, teach us to judge aright of our own, and inform our
understanding to discover its imperfection and natural infirmity, which
is no trivial speculation. So many mutations of states and kingdoms, and
so many turns and revolutions of public fortune, will make us wise
enough to make no great wonder of our own. So many great names, so many
famous victories and conquests drowned and swallowed in oblivion, render
our hopes ridiculous of eternising our names by the taking of
half-a-score of light horse, or a henroost, which only derives its
memory from its ruin. The pride and arrogance of so many foreign pomps,
the inflated majesty of so many courts and grandeurs, accustom and
fortify our sight without closing our eyes to behold the lustre of our
own; so many trillions of men, buried before us, encourage us not to
fear to go seek such good company in the other world: and so of the rest
Pythagoras was want to say,—[Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., v. 3.]—that our life
resembles the great and populous assembly of the Olympic games, wherein
some exercise the body, that they may carry away the glory of the prize:
others bring merchandise to sell for profit: there are also some (and
those none of the worst sort) who pursue no other advantage than only to
look on, and consider how and why everything is done, and to be
spectators of the lives of other men, thereby the better to judge of and
regulate their own.
To examples may fitly be applied all the profitable discourses of
philosophy, to which all human actions, as to their best rule, ought to
be especially directed: a scholar shall be taught to know—
"Quid fas optare: quid asper
Utile nummus habet: patrix carisque propinquis
Quantum elargiri deceat: quern te Deus esse
Jussit, et humana qua parte locatus es in re;
Quid sumus, et quidnam victuri gignimur."
["Learn what it is right to wish; what is the true use of coined
money; how much it becomes us to give in liberality to our country
and our dear relations; whom and what the Deity commanded thee to
be; and in what part of the human system thou art placed; what we
are ant to what purpose engendered."—Persius, iii. 69]
what it is to know, and what to be ignorant; what ought to be the end
and design of study; what valour, temperance, and justice are; the
difference betwixt ambition and avarice, servitude and subjection,
licence and liberty; by what token a man may know true and solid
contentment; how far death, affliction, and disgrace are to be
apprehended;
"Et quo quemque modo fugiatque feratque laborem."
["And how you may shun or sustain every hardship."
—Virgil, AEneid, iii. 459.]
by what secret springs we move, and the reason of our various
agitations and irresolutions: for, methinks the first doctrine with
which one should season his understanding, ought to be that which
regulates his manners and his sense; that teaches him to know himself,
and how both well to dig and well to live. Amongst the liberal sciences,
let us begin with that which makes us free; not that they do not all
serve in some measure to the instruction and use of life, as all other
things in some sort also do; but let us make choice of that which
directly and professedly serves to that end. If we are once able to
restrain the offices of human life within their just and natural limits,
we shall find that most of the sciences in use are of no great use to
us, and even in those that are, that there are many very unnecessary
cavities and dilatations which we had better let alone, and, following
Socrates' direction, limit the course of our studies to those things
only where is a true and real utility:
"Sapere aude;
Incipe; Qui recte vivendi prorogat horam,
Rusticus exspectat, dum defluat amnis; at ille
Labitur, et labetur in omne volubilis oevum."
["Dare to be wise; begin! he who defers the hour of living well is
like the clown, waiting till the river shall have flowed out: but
the river still flows, and will run on, with constant course, to
ages without end."—Horace, Ep., i. 2.]
'Tis a great foolery to teach our children:
"Quid moveant Pisces, animosaque signa Leonis,
Lotus et Hesperia quid Capricornus aqua,"
["What influence Pisces have, or the sign of angry Leo, or
Capricorn, washed by the Hesperian wave."—Propertius, iv. I, 89.]
the knowledge of the stars and the motion of the eighth sphere before
their own:
["What care I about the Pleiades or the stars of Taurus?"
—Anacreon, Ode, xvii. 10.]
Anaximenes writing to Pythagoras, "To what purpose," said he, "should
I trouble myself in searching out the secrets of the stars, having death
or slavery continually before my eyes?" for the kings of Persia were at
that time preparing to invade his country. Every one ought to say thus,
"Being assaulted, as I am by ambition, avarice, temerity, superstition,
and having within so many other enemies of life, shall I go ponder over
the world's changes?"
After having taught him what will make him more wise and good, you
may then entertain him with the elements of logic, physics, geometry,
rhetoric, and the science which he shall then himself most incline to,
his judgment being beforehand formed and fit to choose, he will quickly
make his own. The way of instructing him ought to be sometimes by
discourse, and sometimes by reading; sometimes his governor shall put
the author himself, which he shall think most proper for him, into his
hands, and sometimes only the marrow and substance of it; and if himself
be not conversant enough in books to turn to all the fine discourses the
books contain for his purpose, there may some man of learning be joined
to him, that upon every occasion shall supply him with what he stands in
need of, to furnish it to his pupil. And who can doubt but that this way
of teaching is much more easy and natural than that of Gaza,—[Theodore
Gaza, rector of the Academy of Ferrara.]—in which the precepts are so
intricate, and so harsh, and the words so vain, lean; and insignificant,
that there is no hold to be taken of them, nothing that quickens and
elevates the wit and fancy, whereas here the mind has what to feed upon
and to digest. This fruit, therefore, is not only without comparison,
much more fair and beautiful; but will also be much more early ripe.
'Tis a thousand pities that matters should be at such a pass in this
age of ours, that philosophy, even with men of understanding, should be,
looked upon as a vain and fantastic name, a thing of no use, no value,
either in opinion or effect, of which I think those ergotisms and petty
sophistries, by prepossessing the avenues to it, are the cause. And
people are much to blame to represent it to children for a thing of so
difficult access, and with such a frowning, grim, and formidable aspect.
Who is it that has disguised it thus, with this false, pale, and ghostly
countenance? There is nothing more airy, more gay, more frolic, and I
had like to have said, more wanton. She preaches nothing but feasting
and jollity; a melancholic anxious look shows that she does not inhabit
there. Demetrius the grammarian finding in the temple of Delphos a knot
of philosophers set chatting together, said to them,—[Plutarch, Treatise
on Oracles which have ceased]—"Either I am much deceived, or by your
cheerful and pleasant countenances, you are engaged in no, very deep
discourse." To which one of them, Heracleon the Megarean, replied: "Tis
for such as are puzzled about inquiring whether the future tense of the
verb ——— is spelt with a double A, or that hunt after the derivation of
the comparatives ——- and ——-, and the superlatives —— and ———, to knit
their brows whilst discoursing of their science: but as to philosophical
discourses, they always divert and cheer up those that entertain them,
and never deject them or make them sad."
"Deprendas animi tormenta latentis in aegro
Corpore; deprendas et gaudia; sumit utrumque
Inde habitum facies."
["You may discern the torments of mind lurking in a sick body; you
may discern its joys: either expression the face assumes from the
mind."—Juvenal, ix. 18]
The soul that lodges philosophy, ought to be of such a constitution
of health, as to render the body in like manner healthful too; she ought
to make her tranquillity and satisfaction shine so as to appear without,
and her contentment ought to fashion the outward behaviour to her own
mould, and consequently to fortify it with a graceful confidence, an
active and joyous carriage, and a serene and contented countenance. The
most manifest sign of wisdom is a continual cheerfulness; her state is
like that of things in the regions above the moon, always clear and
serene. 'Tis Baroco and Baralipton—[Two terms of the ancient scholastic
logic.]—that render their disciples so dirty and ill-favoured, and not
she; they do not so much as know her but by hearsay. What! It is she
that calms and appeases the storms and tempests of the soul, and who
teaches famine and fevers to laugh and sing; and that, not by certain
imaginary epicycles, but by natural and manifest reasons. She has virtue
for her end, which is not, as the schoolmen say, situate upon the summit
of a perpendicular, rugged, inaccessible precipice: such as have
approached her find her, quite on the contrary, to be seated in a fair,
fruitful, and flourishing plain, whence she easily discovers all things
below; to which place any one may, however, arrive, if he know but the
way, through shady, green, and sweetly-flourishing avenues, by a
pleasant, easy, and smooth descent, like that of the celestial vault.
'Tis for not having frequented this supreme, this beautiful, triumphant,
and amiable, this equally delicious and courageous virtue, this so
professed and implacable enemy to anxiety, sorrow, fear, and constraint,
who, having nature for her guide, has fortune and pleasure for her
companions, that they have gone, according to their own weak
imagination, and created this ridiculous, this sorrowful, querulous,
despiteful, threatening, terrible image of it to themselves and others,
and placed it upon a rock apart, amongst thorns and brambles, and made
of it a hobgoblin to affright people.
But the governor that I would have, that is such a one as knows it to
be his duty to possess his pupil with as much or more affection than
reverence to virtue, will be able to inform him, that the poets have
evermore accommodated themselves to the public humour, and make him
sensible, that the gods have planted more toil and sweat in the avenues
of the cabinets of Venus than in those of Minerva. And when he shall
once find him begin to apprehend, and shall represent to him a
Bradamante or an Angelica—[Heroines of Ariosto.]—for a mistress, a
natural, active, generous, and not a viragoish, but a manly beauty, in
comparison of a soft, delicate, artificial simpering, and affected form;
the one in the habit of a heroic youth, wearing a glittering helmet, the
other tricked up in curls and ribbons like a wanton minx; he will then
look upon his own affection as brave and masculine, when he shall choose
quite contrary to that effeminate shepherd of Phrygia.
Such a tutor will make a pupil digest this new lesson, that the
height and value of true virtue consists in the facility, utility, and
pleasure of its exercise; so far from difficulty, that boys, as well as
men, and the innocent as well as the subtle, may make it their own; it
is by order, and not by force, that it is to be acquired. Socrates, her
first minion, is so averse to all manner of violence, as totally to
throw it aside, to slip into the more natural facility of her own
progress; 'tis the nursing mother of all human pleasures, who in
rendering them just, renders them also pure and permanent; in moderating
them, keeps them in breath and appetite; in interdicting those which she
herself refuses, whets our desire to those that she allows; and, like a
kind and liberal mother, abundantly allows all that nature requires,
even to satiety, if not to lassitude: unless we mean to say that the
regimen which stops the toper before he has drunk himself drunk, the
glutton before he has eaten to a surfeit, and the lecher before he has
got the pox, is an enemy to pleasure. If the ordinary fortune fail, she
does without it, and forms another, wholly her own, not so fickle and
unsteady as the other. She can be rich, be potent and wise, and knows
how to lie upon soft perfumed beds: she loves life, beauty, glory, and
health; but her proper and peculiar office is to know how to regulate
the use of all these good things, and how to lose them without concern:
an office much more noble than troublesome, and without which the whole
course of life is unnatural, turbulent, and deformed, and there it is
indeed, that men may justly represent those monsters upon rocks and
precipices.
If this pupil shall happen to be of so contrary a disposition, that
he had rather hear a tale of a tub than the true narrative of some noble
expedition or some wise and learned discourse; who at the beat of drum,
that excites the youthful ardour of his companions, leaves that to
follow another that calls to a morris or the bears; who would not wish,
and find it more delightful and more excellent, to return all dust and
sweat victorious from a battle, than from tennis or from a ball, with
the prize of those exercises; I see no other remedy, but that he be
bound prentice in some good town to learn to make minced pies, though he
were the son of a duke; according to Plato's precept, that children are
to be placed out and disposed of, not according to the wealth,
qualities, or condition of the father, but according to the faculties
and the capacity of their own souls.
Since philosophy is that which instructs us to live, and that infancy
has there its lessons as well as other ages, why is it not communicated
to children betimes?
"Udum et molle lutum est; nunc, nunc properandus, et acri
Fingendus sine fine rota."
["The clay is moist and soft: now, now make haste, and form the
pitcher on the rapid wheel."—Persius, iii. 23.]
They begin to teach us to live when we have almost done living. A
hundred students have got the pox before they have come to read
Aristotle's lecture on temperance. Cicero said, that though he should
live two men's ages, he should never find leisure to study the lyric
poets; and I find these sophisters yet more deplorably unprofitable. The
boy we would breed has a great deal less time to spare; he owes but the
first fifteen or sixteen years of his life to education; the remainder
is due to action. Let us, therefore, employ that short time in necessary
instruction. Away with the thorny subtleties of dialectics; they are
abuses, things by which our lives can never be amended: take the plain
philosophical discourses, learn how rightly to choose, and then rightly
to apply them; they are more easy to be understood than one of
Boccaccio's novels; a child from nurse is much more capable of them,
than of learning to read or to write. Philosophy has discourses proper
for childhood, as well as for the decrepit age of men.
I am of Plutarch's mind, that Aristotle did not so much trouble his
great disciple with the knack of forming syllogisms, or with the
elements of geometry; as with infusing into him good precepts concerning
valour, prowess, magnanimity, temperance, and the contempt of fear; and
with this ammunition, sent him, whilst yet a boy, with no more than
thirty thousand foot, four thousand horse, and but forty-two thousand
crowns, to subjugate the empire of the whole earth. For the other acts
and sciences, he says, Alexander highly indeed commended their
excellence and charm, and had them in very great honour and esteem, but
not ravished with them to that degree as to be tempted to affect the
practice of them In his own person:
"Petite hinc, juvenesque senesque,
Finem ammo certum, miserisque viatica canis."
["Young men and old men, derive hence a certain end to the mind,
and stores for miserable grey hairs."—Persius, v. 64.]
Epicurus, in the beginning of his letter to Meniceus,—[Diogenes
Laertius, x. 122.]—says, "That neither the youngest should refuse to
philosophise, nor the oldest grow weary of it." Who does otherwise,
seems tacitly to imply, that either the time of living happily is not
yet come, or that it is already past. And yet, a for all that, I would
not have this pupil of ours imprisoned and made a slave to his book; nor
would I have him given up to the morosity and melancholic humour of a
sour ill-natured pedant.
I would not have his spirit cowed and subdued, by applying him to the
rack, and tormenting him, as some do, fourteen or fifteen hours a day,
and so make a pack-horse of him. Neither should I think it good, when,
by reason of a solitary and melancholic complexion, he is discovered to
be overmuch addicted to his book, to nourish that humour in him; for
that renders him unfit for civil conversation, and diverts him from
better employments. And how many have I seen in my time totally
brutified by an immoderate thirst after knowledge? Carneades was so
besotted with it, that he would not find time so much as to comb his
head or to pare his nails. Neither would I have his generous manners
spoiled and corrupted by the incivility and barbarism of those of
another. The French wisdom was anciently turned into proverb: "Early,
but of no continuance." And, in truth, we yet see, that nothing can be
more ingenious and pleasing than the children of France; but they
ordinarily deceive the hope and expectation that have been conceived of
them; and grown up to be men, have nothing extraordinary or worth taking
notice of: I have heard men of good understanding say, these colleges of
ours to which we send our young people (and of which we have but too
many) make them such animals as they are.—[Hobbes said that if he Had
been at college as long as other people he should have been as great a
blockhead as they. W.C.H.] [And Bacon before Hobbe's time had discussed
the "futility" of university teaching. D.W.]
But to our little monsieur, a closet, a garden, the table, his bed,
solitude, and company, morning and evening, all hours shall be the same,
and all places to him a study; for philosophy, who, as the formatrix of
judgment and manners, shall be his principal lesson, has that privilege
to have a hand in everything. The orator Isocrates, being at a feast
entreated to speak of his art, all the company were satisfied with and
commended his answer: "It is not now a time," said he, "to do what I can
do; and that which it is now time to do, I cannot do."—[Plutarch, Symp.,
i. I.]—For to make orations and rhetorical disputes in a company met
together to laugh and make good cheer, had been very unreasonable and
improper, and as much might have been said of all the other sciences.
But as to what concerns philosophy, that part of it at least that treats
of man, and of his offices and duties, it has been the common opinion of
all wise men, that, out of respect to the sweetness of her conversation,
she is ever to be admitted in all sports and entertainments. And Plato,
having invited her to his feast, we see after how gentle and obliging a
manner, accommodated both to time and place, she entertained the
company, though in a discourse of the highest and most important nature:
"Aeque pauperibus prodest, locupletibus aeque;
Et, neglecta, aeque pueris senibusque nocebit."
["It profits poor and rich alike, but, neglected, equally hurts old
and young."—Horace, Ep., i. 25.]
By this method of instruction, my young pupil will be much more and
better employed than his fellows of the college are. But as the steps we
take in walking to and fro in a gallery, though three times as many, do
not tire a man so much as those we employ in a formal journey, so our
lesson, as it were accidentally occurring, without any set obligation of
time or place, and falling naturally into every action, will insensibly
insinuate itself. By which means our very exercises and recreations,
running, wrestling, music, dancing, hunting, riding, and fencing, will
prove to be a good part of our study. I would have his outward fashion
and mien, and the disposition of his limbs, formed at the same time with
his mind. 'Tis not a soul, 'tis not a body that we are training up, but
a man, and we ought not to divide him. And, as Plato says, we are not to
fashion one without the other, but make them draw together like two
horses harnessed to a coach. By which saying of his, does he not seem to
allow more time for, and to take more care of exercises for the body,
and to hold that the mind, in a good proportion, does her business at
the same time too?
As to the rest, this method of education ought to be carried on with
a severe sweetness, quite contrary to the practice of our pedants, who,
instead of tempting and alluring children to letters by apt and gentle
ways, do in truth present nothing before them but rods and ferules,
horror and cruelty. Away with this violence! away with this compulsion!
than which, I certainly believe nothing more dulls and degenerates a
well-descended nature. If you would have him apprehend shame and
chastisement, do not harden him to them: inure him to heat and cold, to
wind and sun, and to dangers that he ought to despise; wean him from all
effeminacy and delicacy in clothes and lodging, eating and drinking;
accustom him to everything, that he may not be a Sir Paris, a
carpet-knight, but a sinewy, hardy, and vigorous young man. I have ever
from a child to the age wherein I now am, been of this opinion, and am
still constant to it. But amongst other things, the strict government of
most of our colleges has evermore displeased me; peradventure, they
might have erred less perniciously on the indulgent side. 'Tis a real
house of correction of imprisoned youth. They are made debauched by
being punished before they are so. Do but come in when they are about
their lesson, and you shall hear nothing but the outcries of boys under
execution, with the thundering noise of their pedagogues drunk with
fury. A very pretty way this, to tempt these tender and timorous souls
to love their book, with a furious countenance, and a rod in hand! A
cursed and pernicious way of proceeding! Besides what Quintilian has
very well observed, that this imperious authority is often attended by
very dangerous consequences, and particularly our way of chastising. How
much more decent would it be to see their classes strewed with green
leaves and fine flowers, than with the bloody stumps of birch and
willows? Were it left to my ordering. I should paint the school with the
pictures of joy and gladness; Flora and the Graces, as the philosopher
Speusippus did his. Where their profit is, let them there have their
pleasure too. Such viands as are proper and wholesome for children,
should be sweetened with sugar, and such as are dangerous to them,
embittered with gall. 'Tis marvellous to see how solicitous Plato is in
his Laws concerning the gaiety and diversion of the youth of his city,
and how much and often he enlarges upon the races, sports, songs, leaps,
and dances: of which, he says, that antiquity has given the ordering and
patronage particularly to the gods themselves, to Apollo, Minerva, and
the Muses. He insists long upon, and is very particular in, giving
innumerable precepts for exercises; but as to the lettered sciences,
says very little, and only seems particularly to recommend poetry upon
the account of music.
All singularity in our manners and conditions is to be avoided, as
inconsistent with civil society. Who would not be astonished at so
strange a constitution as that of Demophoon, steward to Alexander the
Great, who sweated in the shade and shivered in the sun? I have seen
those who have run from the smell of a mellow apple with greater
precipitation than from a harquebuss-shot; others afraid of a mouse;
others vomit at the sight of cream; others ready to swoon at the making
of a feather bed; Germanicus could neither endure the sight nor the
crowing of a cock. I will not deny, but that there may, peradventure, be
some occult cause and natural aversion in these cases; but, in my
opinion, a man might conquer it, if he took it in time. Precept has in
this wrought so effectually upon me, though not without some pains on my
part, I confess, that beer excepted, my appetite accommodates itself
indifferently to all sorts of diet. Young bodies are supple; one should,
therefore, in that age bend and ply them to all fashions and customs:
and provided a man can contain the appetite and the will within their
due limits, let a young man, in God's name, be rendered fit for all
nations and all companies, even to debauchery and excess, if need be;
that is, where he shall do it out of complacency to the customs of the
place. Let him be able to do everything, but love to do nothing but what
is good. The philosophers themselves do not justify Callisthenes for
forfeiting the favour of his master Alexander the Great, by refusing to
pledge him a cup of wine. Let him laugh, play, wench with his prince:
nay, I would have him, even in his debauches, too hard for the rest of
the company, and to excel his companions in ability and vigour, and that
he may not give over doing it, either through defect of power or
knowledge how to do it, but for want of will.
"Multum interest, utrum peccare ali quis nolit, an nesciat."
["There is a vast difference betwixt forbearing to sin, and not
knowing how to sin."—Seneca, Ep., 90]
I thought I passed a compliment upon a lord, as free from those
excesses as any man in France, by asking him before a great deal of very
good company, how many times in his life he had been drunk in Germany,
in the time of his being there about his Majesty's affairs; which he
also took as it was intended, and made answer, "Three times"; and withal
told us the whole story of his debauches. I know some who, for want of
this faculty, have found a great inconvenience in negotiating with that
nation. I have often with great admiration reflected upon the wonderful
constitution of Alcibiades, who so easily could transform himself to so
various fashions without any prejudice to his health; one while outdoing
the Persian pomp and luxury, and another, the Lacedaemonian austerity
and frugality; as reformed in Sparta, as voluptuous in Ionia:
"Omnis Aristippum decuit color, et status, et res."
["Every complexion of life, and station, and circumstance became
Aristippus."—Horace, Ep., xvii. 23.]
I would have my pupil to be such an one,
"Quem duplici panno patentia velat,
Mirabor, vitae via si conversa decebit,
Personamque feret non inconcinnus utramque."
["I should admire him who with patience bearing a patched garment,
bears well a changed fortune, acting both parts equally well."
—Horace Ep., xvii. 25.]
These are my lessons, and he who puts them in practice shall reap
more advantage than he who has had them read to him only, and so only
knows them. If you see him, you hear him; if you hear him, you see him.
God forbid, says one in Plato, that to philosophise were only to read a
great many books, and to learn the arts.
"Hanc amplissimam omnium artium bene vivendi disciplinam,
vita magis quam literis, persequuti sunt."
["They have proceeded to this discipline of living well, which of
all arts is the greatest, by their lives, rather than by their
reading."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., iv. 3.]
Leo, prince of the Phliasians, asking Heraclides Ponticus—[It was not
Heraclides of Pontus who made this answer, but Pythagoras.]—of what art
or science he made profession: "I know," said he, "neither art nor
science, but I am a philosopher." One reproaching Diogenes that, being
ignorant, he should pretend to philosophy; "I therefore," answered he,
"pretend to it with so much the more reason." Hegesias entreated that he
would read a certain book to him: "You are pleasant," said he; "you
choose those figs that are true and natural, and not those that are
painted; why do you not also choose exercises which are naturally true,
rather than those written?"
The lad will not so much get his lesson by heart as he will practise
it: he will repeat it in his actions. We shall discover if there be
prudence in his exercises, if there be sincerity and justice in his
deportment, if there be grace and judgment in his speaking; if there be
constancy in his sickness; if there be modesty in his mirth, temperance
in his pleasures, order in his domestic economy, indifference in palate,
whether what he eats or drinks be flesh or fish, wine or water:
"Qui disciplinam suam non ostentationem scientiae, sed legem vitae
putet: quique obtemperet ipse sibi, et decretis pareat."
["Who considers his own discipline, not as a vain ostentation of
science, but as a law and rule of life; and who obeys his own
decrees, and the laws he has prescribed for himself."
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 4.]
The conduct of our lives is the true mirror of our doctrine.
Zeuxidamus, to one who asked him, why the Lacedaemonians did not commit
their constitutions of chivalry to writing, and deliver them to their
young men to read, made answer, that it was because they would inure
them to action, and not amuse them with words. With such a one, after
fifteen or sixteen years' study, compare one of our college Latinists,
who has thrown away so much time in nothing but learning to speak. The
world is nothing but babble; and I hardly ever yet saw that man who did
not rather prate too much, than speak too little. And yet half of our
age is embezzled this way: we are kept four or five years to learn words
only, and to tack them together into clauses; as many more to form them
into a long discourse, divided into four or five parts; and other five
years, at least, to learn succinctly to mix and interweave them after a
subtle and intricate manner let us leave all this to those who make a
profession of it.
Going one day to Orleans, I met in that plain on this side Clery, two
pedants who were travelling towards Bordeaux, about fifty paces distant
from one another; and, a good way further behind them, I discovered a
troop of horse, with a gentleman at the head of them, who was the late
Monsieur le Comte de la Rochefoucauld. One of my people inquired of the
foremost of these masters of arts, who that gentleman was that came
after him; he, having not seen the train that followed after, and
thinking his companion was meant, pleasantly answered, "He is not a
gentleman; he is a grammarian; and I am a logician." Now we who, quite
contrary, do not here pretend to breed a grammarian or a logician, but a
gentleman, let us leave them to abuse their leisure; our business lies
elsewhere. Let but our pupil be well furnished with things, words will
follow but too fast; he will pull them after him if they do not
voluntarily follow. I have observed some to make excuses, that they
cannot express themselves, and pretend to have their fancies full of a
great many very fine things, which yet, for want of eloquence, they
cannot utter; 'tis a mere shift, and nothing else. Will you know what I
think of it? I think they are nothing but shadows of some imperfect
images and conceptions that they know not what to make of within, nor
consequently bring out; they do not yet themselves understand what they
would be at, and if you but observe how they haggle and stammer upon the
point of parturition, you will soon conclude, that their labour is not
to delivery, but about conception, and that they are but licking their
formless embryo. For my part, I hold, and Socrates commands it, that
whoever has in his mind a sprightly and clear imagination, he will
express it well enough in one kind of tongue or another, and, if he be
dumb, by signs—
"Verbaque praevisam rem non invita sequentur;"
["Once a thing is conceived in the mind, the words to express it
soon present themselves." ("The words will not reluctantly follow the
thing preconceived.")—Horace, De Arte Poetica. v. 311]
And as another as poetically says in his prose:
"Quum res animum occupavere, verbs ambiunt,"
["When things are once in the mind, the words offer themselves
readily." ("When things have taken possession of the mind, the
words trip.")—Seneca, Controvers., iii. proem.]
and this other.
"Ipsae res verbs rapiunt."
["The things themselves force the words to express them."
—Cicero, De Finib., iii. 5.]
He knows nothing of ablative, conjunctive, substantive, or grammar,
no more than his lackey, or a fishwife of the Petit Pont; and yet these
will give you a bellyful of talk, if you will hear them, and
peradventure shall trip as little in their language as the best masters
of art in France. He knows no rhetoric, nor how in a preface to bribe
the benevolence of the courteous reader; neither does he care to know
it. Indeed all this fine decoration of painting is easily effaced by the
lustre of a simple and blunt truth; these fine flourishes serve only to
amuse the vulgar, of themselves incapable of more solid and nutritive
diet, as Aper very evidently demonstrates in Tacitus. The ambassadors of
Samos, prepared with a long and elegant oration, came to Cleomenes, king
of Sparta, to incite him to a war against the tyrant Polycrates; who,
after he had heard their harangue with great gravity and patience, gave
them this answer: "As to the exordium, I remember it not, nor
consequently the middle of your speech; and for what concerns your
conclusion, I will not do what you desire:"—[Plutarch, Apothegms of the
Lacedaemonians.]—a very pretty answer this, methinks, and a pack of
learned orators most sweetly gravelled. And what did the other man say?
The Athenians were to choose one of two architects for a very great
building they had designed; of these, the first, a pert affected fellow,
offered his service in a long premeditated discourse upon the subject of
the work in hand, and by his oratory inclined the voices of the people
in his favour; but the other in three words: "O Athenians, what this man
says, I will do."—[Plutarch, Instructions to Statesmen, c. 4.]— When
Cicero was in the height and heat of an eloquent harangue, many were
struck with admiration; but Cato only laughed, saying, "We have a
pleasant (mirth-making) consul." Let it go before, or come after, a good
sentence or a thing well said, is always in season; if it neither suit
well with what went before, nor has much coherence with what follows
after, it is good in itself. I am none of those who think that good
rhyme makes a good poem. Let him make short long, and long short if he
will, 'tis no great matter; if there be invention, and that the wit and
judgment have well performed their offices, I will say, here's a good
poet, but an ill rhymer.
"Emunctae naris, durus componere versus."
["Of delicate humour, but of rugged versification."
—Horace, Sat, iv. 8.]
Let a man, says Horace, divest his work of all method and measure,
"Tempora certa modosque, et, quod prius ordine verbum est,
Posterius facias, praeponens ultima primis
Invenias etiam disjecti membra poetae."
["Take away certain rhythms and measures, and make the word which
was first in order come later, putting that which should be last
first, you will still find the scattered remains of the poet."
—Horace, Sat., i. 4, 58.]
he will never the more lose himself for that; the very pieces will be
fine by themselves. Menander's answer had this meaning, who being
reproved by a friend, the time drawing on at which he had promised a
comedy, that he had not yet fallen in hand with it; "It is made, and
ready," said he, "all but the verses."—[Plutarch, Whether the Athenians
more excelled in Arms or in Letters.]—Having contrived the subject, and
disposed the scenes in his fancy, he took little care for the rest.
Since Ronsard and Du Bellay have given reputation to our French poesy,
every little dabbler, for aught I see, swells his words as high, and
makes his cadences very near as harmonious as they:
"Plus sonat, quam valet."
["More sound than sense"—Seneca, Ep., 40.]
For the vulgar, there were never so many poetasters as now; but
though they find it no hard matter to imitate their rhyme, they yet fall
infinitely short of imitating the rich descriptions of the one, and the
delicate invention of the other of these masters.
But what will become of our young gentleman, if he be attacked with
the sophistic subtlety of some syllogism? "A Westfalia ham makes a man
drink; drink quenches thirst: ergo a Westfalia ham quenches thirst."
Why, let him laugh at it; it will be more discretion to do so, than to
go about to answer it; or let him borrow this pleasant evasion from
Aristippus: "Why should I trouble myself to untie that, which bound as
it is, gives me so much trouble?"—[Diogenes Laertius, ii. 70.]— One
offering at this dialectic juggling against Cleanthes, Chrysippus took
him short, saying, "Reserve these baubles to play with children, and do
not by such fooleries divert the serious thoughts of a man of years." If
these ridiculous subtleties,
"Contorta et aculeata sophismata,"
as Cicero calls them, are designed to possess him with an untruth,
they are dangerous; but if they signify no more than only to make him
laugh, I do not see why a man need to be fortified against them. There
are some so ridiculous, as to go a mile out of their way to hook in a
fine word:
"Aut qui non verba rebus aptant, sed res extrinsecus
arcessunt, quibus verba conveniant."
["Who do not fit words to the subject, but seek out for things
quite from the purpose to fit the words."—Quintilian, viii. 3.]
And as another says,
"Qui, alicujus verbi decore placentis, vocentur ad id,
quod non proposuerant scribere."
["Who by their fondness of some fine sounding word, are tempted to
something they had no intention to treat of."—Seneca, Ep., 59.]
I for my part rather bring in a fine sentence by head and shoulders
to fit my purpose, than divert my designs to hunt after a sentence. On
the contrary, words are to serve, and to follow a man's purpose; and let
Gascon come in play where French will not do. I would have things so
excelling, and so wholly possessing the imagination of him that hears,
that he should have something else to do, than to think of words. The
way of speaking that I love, is natural and plain, the same in writing
as in speaking, and a sinewy and muscular way of expressing a man's
self, short and pithy, not so elegant and artificial as prompt and
vehement;
"Haec demum sapiet dictio, qux feriet;"
["That has most weight and wisdom which pierces the ear." ("That
utterance indeed will have a taste which shall strike the ear.")
—Epitaph on Lucan, in Fabricius, Biblioth. Lat., ii. 10.]
rather hard than wearisome; free from affectation; irregular,
incontinuous, and bold; where every piece makes up an entire body; not
like a pedant, a preacher, or a pleader, but rather a soldier-like
style, as Suetonius calls that of Julius Caesar; and yet I see no reason
why he should call it so. I have ever been ready to imitate the
negligent garb, which is yet observable amongst the young men of our
time, to wear my cloak on one shoulder, my cap on one side, a stocking
in disorder, which seems to express a kind of haughty disdain of these
exotic ornaments, and a contempt of the artificial; but I find this
negligence of much better use in the form of speaking. All affectation,
particularly in the French gaiety and freedom, is ungraceful in a
courtier, and in a monarchy every gentleman ought to be fashioned
according to the court model; for which reason, an easy and natural
negligence does well. I no more like a web where the knots and seams are
to be seen, than a fine figure, so delicate, that a man may tell all the
bones and veins:
"Quae veritati operam dat oratio, incomposita sit et simplex."
["Let the language that is dedicated to truth be plain and
unaffected.—Seneca, Ep. 40.]
"Quis accurat loquitur, nisi qui vult putide loqui?"
["For who studies to speak accurately, that does not at the same
time wish to perplex his auditory?"—Idem, Ep., 75.]
That eloquence prejudices the subject it would advance, that wholly
attracts us to itself. And as in our outward habit, 'tis a ridiculous
effeminacy to distinguish ourselves by a particular and unusual garb or
fashion; so in language, to study new phrases, and to affect words that
are not of current use, proceeds from a puerile and scholastic ambition.
May I be bound to speak no other language than what is spoken in the
market-places of Paris! Aristophanes the grammarian was quite out, when
he reprehended Epicurus for his plain way of delivering himself, and the
design of his oratory, which was only perspicuity of speech. The
imitation of words, by its own facility, immediately disperses itself
through a whole people; but the imitation of inventing and fitly
applying those words is of a slower progress. The generality of readers,
for having found a like robe, very mistakingly imagine they have the
same body and inside too, whereas force and sinews are never to be
borrowed; the gloss, and outward ornament, that is, words and elocution,
may. Most of those I converse with, speak the same language I here
write; but whether they think the same thoughts I cannot say. The
Athenians, says Plato, study fulness and elegancy of speaking; the
Lacedaemonians affect brevity, and those of Crete to aim more at the
fecundity of conception than the fertility of speech; and these are the
best. Zeno used to say that he had two sorts of disciples, one that he
called cy——-ous, curious to learn things, and these were his favourites;
the other, aoy—-ous, that cared for nothing but words. Not that fine
speaking is not a very good and commendable quality; but not so
excellent and so necessary as some would make it; and I am scandalised
that our whole life should be spent in nothing else. I would first
understand my own language, and that of my neighbours, with whom most of
my business and conversation lies.
No doubt but Greek and Latin are very great ornaments, and of very
great use, but we buy them too dear. I will here discover one way, which
has been experimented in my own person, by which they are to be had
better cheap, and such may make use of it as will. My late father having
made the most precise inquiry that any man could possibly make amongst
men of the greatest learning and judgment, of an exact method of
education, was by them cautioned of this inconvenience then in use, and
made to believe, that the tedious time we applied to the learning of the
tongues of them who had them for nothing, was the sole cause we could
not arrive to the grandeur of soul and perfection of knowledge, of the
ancient Greeks and Romans. I do not, however, believe that to be the
only cause. So it is, that the expedient my father found out for this
was, that in my infancy, and before I began to speak, he committed me to
the care of a German, who since died a famous physician in France,
totally ignorant of our language, and very fluent and a great critic in
Latin. This man, whom he had fetched out of his own country, and whom he
entertained with a great salary for this only one end, had me
continually with him; he had with him also joined two others, of
inferior learning, to attend me, and to relieve him; these spoke to me
in no other language but Latin. As to the rest of his household, it was
an inviolable rule, that neither himself, nor my mother, nor valet, nor
chambermaid, should speak anything in my company, but such Latin words
as each one had learned to gabble with me. —[These passages are, the
basis of a small volume by the Abbe Mangin: "Education de Montaigne; ou,
L'Art d'enseigner le Latin a l'instar des meres latines."]—It is not to
be imagined how great an advantage this proved to the whole family; my
father and my mother by this means learned Latin enough to understand it
perfectly well, and to speak it to such a degree as was sufficient for
any necessary use; as also those of the servants did who were most
frequently with me. In short, we Latined it at such a rate, that it
overflowed to all the neighbouring villages, where there yet remain,
that have established themselves by custom, several Latin appellations
of artisans and their tools. As for what concerns myself, I was above
six years of age before I understood either French or Perigordin, any
more than Arabic; and without art, book, grammar, or precept, whipping,
or the expense of a tear, I had, by that time, learned to speak as pure
Latin as my master himself, for I had no means of mixing it up with any
other. If, for example, they were to give me a theme after the college
fashion, they gave it to others in French; but to me they were to give
it in bad Latin, to turn it into that which was good. And Nicolas
Grouchy, who wrote a book De Comitiis Romanorum; Guillaume Guerente, who
wrote a comment upon Aristotle: George Buchanan, that great Scottish
poet: and Marc Antoine Muret (whom both France and Italy have
acknowledged for the best orator of his time), my domestic tutors, have
all of them often told me that I had in my infancy that language so very
fluent and ready, that they were afraid to enter into discourse with me.
And particularly Buchanan, whom I since saw attending the late Mareschal
de Brissac, then told me, that he was about to write a treatise of
education, the example of which he intended to take from mine; for he
was then tutor to that Comte de Brissac who afterward proved so valiant
and so brave a gentleman.
As to Greek, of which I have but a mere smattering, my father also
designed to have it taught me by a device, but a new one, and by way of
sport; tossing our declensions to and fro, after the manner of those
who, by certain games of tables, learn geometry and arithmetic. For he,
amongst other rules, had been advised to make me relish science and duty
by an unforced will, and of my own voluntary motion, and to educate my
soul in all liberty and delight, without any severity or constraint;
which he was an observer of to such a degree, even of superstition, if I
may say so, that some being of opinion that it troubles and disturbs the
brains of children suddenly to wake them in the morning, and to snatch
them violently—and over-hastily from sleep (wherein they are much more
profoundly involved than we), he caused me to be wakened by the sound of
some musical instrument, and was never unprovided of a musician for that
purpose. By this example you may judge of the rest, this alone being
sufficient to recommend both the prudence and the affection of so good a
father, who is not to be blamed if he did not reap fruits answerable to
so exquisite a culture. Of this, two things were the cause: first, a
sterile and improper soil; for, though I was of a strong and healthful
constitution, and of a disposition tolerably sweet and tractable, yet I
was, withal, so heavy, idle, and indisposed, that they could not rouse
me from my sloth, not even to get me out to play. What I saw, I saw
clearly enough, and under this heavy complexion nourished a bold
imagination and opinions above my age. I had a slow wit that would go no
faster than it was led; a tardy understanding, a languishing invention,
and above all, incredible defect of memory; so that, it is no wonder, if
from all these nothing considerable could be extracted. Secondly, like
those who, impatient of along and steady cure, submit to all sorts of
prescriptions and recipes, the good man being extremely timorous of any
way failing in a thing he had so wholly set his heart upon, suffered
himself at last to be overruled by the common opinions, which always
follow their leader as a flight of cranes, and complying with the method
of the time, having no more those persons he had brought out of Italy,
and who had given him the first model of education, about him, he sent
me at six years of age to the College of Guienne, at that time the best
and most flourishing in France. And there it was not possible to add
anything to the care he had to provide me the most able tutors, with all
other circumstances of education, reserving also several particular
rules contrary to the college practice; but so it was, that with all
these precautions, it was a college still. My Latin immediately grew
corrupt, of which also by discontinuance I have since lost all manner of
use; so that this new way of education served me to no other end, than
only at my first coming to prefer me to the first forms; for at thirteen
years old, that I came out of the college, I had run through my whole
course (as they call it), and, in truth, without any manner of
advantage, that I can honestly brag of, in all this time.
The first taste which I had for books came to me from the pleasure in
reading the fables of Ovid's Metamorphoses; for, being about seven or
eight years old, I gave up all other diversions to read them, both by
reason that this was my own natural language, the easiest book that I
was acquainted with, and for the subject, the most accommodated to the
capacity of my age: for as for the Lancelot of the Lake, the Amadis of
Gaul, the Huon of Bordeaux, and such farragos, by which children are
most delighted with, I had never so much as heard their names, no more
than I yet know what they contain; so exact was the discipline wherein I
was brought up. But this was enough to make me neglect the other lessons
that were prescribed me; and here it was infinitely to my advantage, to
have to do with an understanding tutor, who very well knew discreetly to
connive at this and other truantries of the same nature; for by this
means I ran through Virgil's AEneid, and then Terence, and then Plautus,
and then some Italian comedies, allured by the sweetness of the subject;
whereas had he been so foolish as to have taken me off this diversion, I
do really believe, I had brought away nothing from the college but a
hatred of books, as almost all our young gentlemen do. But he carried
himself very discreetly in that business, seeming to take no notice, and
allowing me only such time as I could steal from my other regular
studies, which whetted my appetite to devour those books. For the chief
things my father expected from their endeavours to whom he had delivered
me for education, were affability and good-humour; and, to say the
truth, my manners had no other vice but sloth and want of metal. The
fear was not that I should do ill, but that I should do nothing; nobody
prognosticated that I should be wicked, but only useless; they foresaw
idleness, but no malice; and I find it falls out accordingly: The
complaints I hear of myself are these: "He is idle, cold in the offices
of friendship and relation, and in those of the public, too particular,
too disdainful." But the most injurious do not say, "Why has he taken
such a thing? Why has he not paid such an one?" but, "Why does he part
with nothing? Why does he not give?" And I should take it for a favour
that men would expect from me no greater effects of supererogation than
these. But they are unjust to exact from me what I do not owe, far more
rigorously than they require from others that which they do owe. In
condemning me to it, they efface the gratification of the action, and
deprive me of the gratitude that would be my due for it; whereas the
active well-doing ought to be of so much the greater value from my
hands, by how much I have never been passive that way at all. I can the
more freely dispose of my fortune the more it is mine, and of myself the
more I am my own. Nevertheless, if I were good at setting out my own
actions, I could, peradventure, very well repel these reproaches, and
could give some to understand, that they are not so much offended, that
I do not enough, as that I am able to do a great deal more than I do.
Yet for all this heavy disposition of mine, my mind, when retired
into itself, was not altogether without strong movements, solid and
clear judgments about those objects it could comprehend, and could also,
without any helps, digest them; but, amongst other things, I do really
believe, it had been totally impossible to have made it to submit by
violence and force. Shall I here acquaint you with one faculty of my
youth? I had great assurance of countenance, and flexibility of voice
and gesture, in applying myself to any part I undertook to act: for
before—
"Alter ab undecimo tum me vix ceperat annus,"
["I had just entered my twelfth year."—Virgil, Bucol., 39.]
I played the chief parts in the Latin tragedies of Buchanan,
Guerente, and Muret, that were presented in our College of Guienne with
great dignity: now Andreas Goveanus, our principal, as in all other
parts of his charge, was, without comparison, the best of that
employment in France; and I was looked upon as one of the best actors.
'Tis an exercise that I do not disapprove in young people of condition;
and I have since seen our princes, after the example of some of the
ancients, in person handsomely and commendably perform these exercises;
it was even allowed to persons of quality to make a profession of it in
Greece.
"Aristoni tragico actori rem aperit: huic et genus et
fortuna honesta erant: nec ars, quia nihil tale apud
Graecos pudori est, ea deformabat."
["He imparted this matter to Aristo the tragedian; a man of good
family and fortune, which neither of them receive any blemish by
that profession; nothing of this kind being reputed a disparagement
in Greece."—Livy, xxiv. 24.]
Nay, I have always taxed those with impertinence who condemn these
entertainments, and with injustice those who refuse to admit such
comedians as are worth seeing into our good towns, and grudge the people
that public diversion. Well-governed corporations take care to assemble
their citizens, not only to the solemn duties of devotion, but also to
sports and spectacles. They find society and friendship augmented by it;
and besides, can there possibly be allowed a more orderly and regular
diversion than what is performed m the sight of every one, and very
often in the presence of the supreme magistrate himself? And I, for my
part, should think it reasonable, that the prince should sometimes
gratify his people at his own expense, out of paternal goodness and
affection; and that in populous cities there should be theatres erected
for such entertainments, if but to divert them from worse and private
actions.
To return to my subject, there is nothing like alluring the appetite
and affections; otherwise you make nothing but so many asses laden with
books; by dint of the lash, you give them their pocketful of learning to
keep; whereas, to do well you should not only lodge it with them, but
make them espouse it.
CHAPTER XXVI——THAT IT IS FOLLY TO MEASURE TRUTH AND ERROR BY OUR OWN
CAPACITY
'Tis not, perhaps, without reason, that we attribute facility of
belief and easiness of persuasion to simplicity and ignorance: for I
fancy I have heard belief compared to the impression of a seal upon the
soul, which by how much softer and of less resistance it is, is the more
easy to be impressed upon.
"Ut necesse est, lancem in Libra, ponderibus impositis,
deprimi, sic animum perspicuis cedere."
["As the scale of the balance must give way to the weight that
presses it down, so the mind yields to demonstration."
—Cicero, Acad., ii. 12.]
By how much the soul is more empty and without counterpoise, with so
much greater facility it yields under the weight of the first
persuasion. And this is the reason that children, the common people,
women, and sick folks, are most apt to be led by the ears. But then, on
the other hand, 'tis a foolish presumption to slight and condemn all
things for false that do not appear to us probable; which is the
ordinary vice of such as fancy themselves wiser than their neighbours. I
was myself once one of those; and if I heard talk of dead folks walking,
of prophecies, enchantments, witchcrafts, or any other story I had no
mind to believe:
"Somnia, terrores magicos, miracula, sagas,
Nocturnos lemures, portentaque Thessala,"
["Dreams, magic terrors, marvels, sorceries, Thessalian prodigies."
—Horace. Ep. ii. 3, 208.]
I presently pitied the poor people that were abused by these follies.
Whereas I now find, that I myself was to be pitied as much, at least, as
they; not that experience has taught me anything to alter my former
opinions, though my curiosity has endeavoured that way; but reason has
instructed me, that thus resolutely to condemn anything for false and
impossible, is arrogantly and impiously to circumscribe and limit the
will of God, and the power of our mother nature, within the bounds of my
own capacity, than which no folly can be greater. If we give the names
of monster and miracle to everything our reason cannot comprehend, how
many are continually presented before our eyes? Let us but consider
through what clouds, and as it were groping in the dark, our teachers
lead us to the knowledge of most of the things about us; assuredly we
shall find that it is rather custom than knowledge that takes away their
strangeness—
"Jam nemo, fessus saturusque videndi,
Suspicere in coeli dignatur lucida templa;"
["Weary of the sight, now no one deigns to look up to heaven's lucid
temples."—Lucretius, ii. 1037. The text has 'statiate videnai']
and that if those things were now newly presented to us, we should
think them as incredible, if not more, than any others.
"Si nunc primum mortalibus adsint
Ex improviso, si sint objecta repente,
Nil magis his rebus poterat mirabile dici,
Aute minus ante quod auderent fore credere gentes."
[Lucretius, ii. 1032. The sense of the passage is in the preceding
sentence.]
He that had never seen a river, imagined the first he met with to be
the sea; and the greatest things that have fallen within our knowledge,
we conclude the extremes that nature makes of the kind.
"Scilicet et fluvius qui non est maximus, ei'st
Qui non ante aliquem majorem vidit; et ingens
Arbor, homoque videtur, et omnia de genere omni
Maxima quae vidit quisque, haec ingentia fingit."
["A little river seems to him, who has never seen a larger river, a
mighty stream; and so with other things—a tree, a man—anything
appears greatest to him that never knew a greater."—Idem, vi. 674.]
"Consuetudine oculorum assuescunt animi, neque admirantur,
neque requirunt rationes earum rerum, quas semper vident."
["Things grow familiar to men's minds by being often seen; so that
they neither admire nor are they inquisitive about things they daily
see."—Cicero, De Natura Deor., lib. ii. 38.]
The novelty, rather than the greatness of things, tempts us to
inquire into their causes. We are to judge with more reverence, and with
greater acknowledgment of our own ignorance and infirmity, of the
infinite power of nature. How many unlikely things are there testified
by people worthy of faith, which, if we cannot persuade ourselves
absolutely to believe, we ought at least to leave them in suspense; for,
to condemn them as impossible, is by a temerarious presumption to
pretend to know the utmost bounds of possibility. Did we rightly
understand the difference betwixt the impossible and the unusual, and
betwixt that which is contrary to the order and course of nature and
contrary to the common opinion of men, in not believing rashly, and on
the other hand, in not being too incredulous, we should observe the rule
of 'Ne quid nimis' enjoined by Chilo.
When we find in Froissart, that the Comte de Foix knew in Bearn the
defeat of John, king of Castile, at Jubera the next day after it
happened, and the means by which he tells us he came to do so, we may be
allowed to be a little merry at it, as also at what our annals report,
that Pope Honorius, the same day that King Philip Augustus died at
Mantes, performed his public obsequies at Rome, and commanded the like
throughout Italy, the testimony of these authors not being, perhaps, of
authority enough to restrain us. But what if Plutarch, besides several
examples that he produces out of antiquity, tells us, he knows of
certain knowledge, that in the time of Domitian, the news of the battle
lost by Antony in Germany was published at Rome, many days' journey from
thence, and dispersed throughout the whole world, the same day it was
fought; and if Caesar was of opinion, that it has often happened, that
the report has preceded the incident, shall we not say, that these
simple people have suffered themselves to be deceived with the vulgar,
for not having been so clear-sighted as we? Is there anything more
delicate, more clear, more sprightly; than Pliny's judgment, when he is
pleased to set it to work? Anything more remote from vanity? Setting
aside his learning, of which I make less account, in which of these
excellences do any of us excel him? And yet there is scarce a young
schoolboy that does not convict him of untruth, and that pretends not to
instruct him in the progress of the works of nature. When we read in
Bouchet the miracles of St. Hilary's relics, away with them: his
authority is not sufficient to deprive us of the liberty of
contradicting him; but generally and offhand to condemn all suchlike
stories, seems to me a singular impudence. That great St. Augustin'
testifies to have seen a blind child recover sight upon the relics of
St. Gervasius and St. Protasius at Milan; a woman at Carthage cured of a
cancer, by the sign of the cross made upon her by a woman newly
baptized; Hesperius, a familiar friend of his, to have driven away the
spirits that haunted his house, with a little earth of the sepulchre of
our Lord; which earth, being also transported thence into the church, a
paralytic to have there been suddenly cured by it; a woman in a
procession, having touched St. Stephen's shrine with a nosegay, and
rubbing her eyes with it, to have recovered her sight, lost many years
before; with several other miracles of which he professes himself to
have been an eyewitness: of what shall we excuse him and the two holy
bishops, Aurelius and Maximinus, both of whom he attests to the truth of
these things? Shall it be of ignorance, simplicity, and facility; or of
malice and imposture? Is any man now living so impudent as to think
himself comparable to them in virtue, piety, learning, judgment, or any
kind of perfection?
"Qui, ut rationem nullam afferrent,
ipsa auctoritate me frangerent."
["Who, though they should adduce no reason, would convince me with
their authority alone."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes, i. 21.]
'Tis a presumption of great danger and consequence, besides the
absurd temerity it draws after it, to contemn what we do not comprehend.
For after, according to your fine understanding, you have established
the limits of truth and error, and that, afterwards, there appears a
necessity upon you of believing stranger things than those you have
contradicted, you are already obliged to quit your limits. Now, that
which seems to me so much to disorder our consciences in the commotions
we are now in concerning religion, is the Catholics dispensing so much
with their belief. They fancy they appear moderate, and wise, when they
grant to their opponents some of the articles in question; but, besides
that they do not discern what advantage it is to those with whom we
contend, to begin to give ground and to retire, and how much this
animates our enemy to follow his blow: these articles which they select
as things indifferent, are sometimes of very great importance. We are
either wholly and absolutely to submit ourselves to the authority of our
ecclesiastical polity, or totally throw off all obedience to it: 'tis
not for us to determine what and how much obedience we owe to it. And
this I can say, as having myself made trial of it, that having formerly
taken the liberty of my own swing and fancy, and omitted or neglected
certain rules of the discipline of our Church, which seemed to me vain
and strange coming afterwards to discourse of it with learned men, I
have found those same things to be built upon very good and solid ground
and strong foundation; and that nothing but stupidity and ignorance
makes us receive them with less reverence than the rest. Why do we not
consider what contradictions we find in our own judgments; how many
things were yesterday articles of our faith, that to-day appear no other
than fables? Glory and curiosity are the scourges of the soul; the last
prompts us to thrust our noses into everything, the other forbids us to
leave anything doubtful and undecided.
CHAPTER XXVII——OF FRIENDSHIP
Having considered the proceedings of a painter that serves me, I had
a mind to imitate his way. He chooses the fairest place and middle of
any wall, or panel, wherein to draw a picture, which he finishes with
his utmost care and art, and the vacuity about it he fills with
grotesques, which are odd fantastic figures without any grace but what
they derive from their variety, and the extravagance of their shapes.
And in truth, what are these things I scribble, other than grotesques
and monstrous bodies, made of various parts, without any certain figure,
or any other than accidental order, coherence, or proportion?
"Desinit in piscem mulier formosa superne."
["A fair woman in her upper form terminates in a fish."
—Horace, De Arte Poetica, v. 4.]
In this second part I go hand in hand with my painter; but fall very
short of him in the first and the better, my power of handling not being
such, that I dare to offer at a rich piece, finely polished, and set off
according to art. I have therefore thought fit to borrow one of Estienne
de la Boetie, and such a one as shall honour and adorn all the rest of
my work—namely, a discourse that he called 'Voluntary Servitude'; but,
since, those who did not know him have properly enough called it "Le
contr Un." He wrote in his youth,—["Not being as yet eighteen years
old."—Edition of 1588.] by way of essay, in honour of liberty against
tyrants; and it has since run through the hands of men of great learning
and judgment, not without singular and merited commendation; for it is
finely written, and as full as anything can possibly be. And yet one may
confidently say it is far short of what he was able to do; and if in
that more mature age, wherein I had the happiness to know him, he had
taken a design like this of mine, to commit his thoughts to writing, we
should have seen a great many rare things, and such as would have gone
very near to have rivalled the best writings of antiquity: for in
natural parts especially, I know no man comparable to him. But he has
left nothing behind him, save this treatise only (and that too by
chance, for I believe he never saw it after it first went out of his
hands), and some observations upon that edict of January—[1562, which
granted to the Huguenots the public exercise of their religion.]—made
famous by our civil-wars, which also shall elsewhere, peradventure, find
a place. These were all I could recover of his remains, I to whom with
so affectionate a remembrance, upon his death-bed, he by his last will
bequeathed his library and papers, the little book of his works only
excepted, which I committed to the press. And this particular obligation
I have to this treatise of his, that it was the occasion of my first
coming acquainted with him; for it was showed to me long before I had
the good fortune to know him; and the first knowledge of his name,
proving the first cause and foundation of a friendship, which we
afterwards improved and maintained, so long as God was pleased to
continue us together, so perfect, inviolate, and entire, that certainly
the like is hardly to be found in story, and amongst the men of this
age, there is no sign nor trace of any such thing in use; so much
concurrence is required to the building of such a one, that 'tis much,
if fortune bring it but once to pass in three ages.
There is nothing to which nature seems so much to have inclined us,
as to society; and Aristotle , says that the good legislators had more
respect to friendship than to justice. Now the most supreme point of its
perfection is this: for, generally, all those that pleasure, profit,
public or private interest create and nourish, are so much the less
beautiful and generous, and so much the less friendships, by how much
they mix another cause, and design, and fruit in friendship, than
itself. Neither do the four ancient kinds, natural, social, hospitable,
venereal, either separately or jointly, make up a true and perfect
friendship.
That of children to parents is rather respect: friendship is
nourished by communication, which cannot by reason of the great
disparity, be betwixt these, but would rather perhaps offend the duties
of nature; for neither are all the secret thoughts of fathers fit to be
communicated to children, lest it beget an indecent familiarity betwixt
them; nor can the advices and reproofs, which is one of the principal
offices of friendship, be properly performed by the son to the father.
There are some countries where 'twas the custom for children to kill
their fathers; and others, where the fathers killed their children, to
avoid their being an impediment one to another in life; and naturally
the expectations of the one depend upon the ruin of the other. There
have been great philosophers who have made nothing of this tie of
nature, as Aristippus for one, who being pressed home about the
affection he owed to his children, as being come out of him, presently
fell to spit, saying, that this also came out of him, and that we also
breed worms and lice; and that other, that Plutarch endeavoured to
reconcile to his brother: "I make never the more account of him," said
he, "for coming out of the same hole." This name of brother does indeed
carry with it a fine and delectable sound, and for that reason, he and I
called one another brothers but the complication of interests, the
division of estates, and that the wealth of the one should be the
property of the other, strangely relax and weaken the fraternal tie:
brothers pursuing their fortune and advancement by the same path, 'tis
hardly possible but they must of necessity often jostle and hinder one
another. Besides, why is it necessary that the correspondence of
manners, parts, and inclinations, which begets the true and perfect
friendships, should always meet in these relations? The father and the
son may be of quite contrary humours, and so of brothers: he is my son,
he is my brother; but he is passionate, ill-natured, or a fool. And
moreover, by how much these are friendships that the law and natural
obligation impose upon us, so much less is there of our own choice and
voluntary freedom; whereas that voluntary liberty of ours has no
production more promptly and; properly its own than affection and
friendship. Not that I have not in my own person experimented all that
can possibly be expected of that kind, having had the best and most
indulgent father, even to his extreme old age, that ever was, and who
was himself descended from a family for many generations famous and
exemplary for brotherly concord:
"Et ipse
Notus in fratres animi paterni."
["And I myself, known for paternal love toward my brothers."
—Horace, Ode, ii. 2, 6.]
We are not here to bring the love we bear to women, though it be an
act of our own choice, into comparison, nor rank it with the others. The
fire of this, I confess,
"Neque enim est dea nescia nostri
Qux dulcem curis miscet amaritiem,"
["Nor is the goddess unknown to me who mixes a sweet bitterness
with my love."—-Catullus, lxviii. 17.]
is more active, more eager, and more sharp: but withal, 'tis more
precipitant, fickle, moving, and inconstant; a fever subject to
intermissions and paroxysms, that has seized but on one part of us.
Whereas in friendship, 'tis a general and universal fire, but temperate
and equal, a constant established heat, all gentle and smooth, without
poignancy or roughness. Moreover, in love, 'tis no other than frantic
desire for that which flies from us:
"Come segue la lepre il cacciatore
Al freddo, al caldo, alla montagna, al lito;
Ne piu l'estima poi the presa vede;
E sol dietro a chi fugge affretta il piede"
["As the hunter pursues the hare, in cold and heat, to the mountain,
to the shore, nor cares for it farther when he sees it taken, and
only delights in chasing that which flees from him."—Aristo, x. 7.]
so soon as it enters unto the terms of friendship, that is to say,
into a concurrence of desires, it vanishes and is gone, fruition
destroys it, as having only a fleshly end, and such a one as is subject
to satiety. Friendship, on the contrary, is enjoyed proportionably as it
is desired; and only grows up, is nourished and improved by enjoyment,
as being of itself spiritual, and the soul growing still more refined by
practice. Under this perfect friendship, the other fleeting affections
have in my younger years found some place in me, to say nothing of him,
who himself so confesses but too much in his verses; so that I had both
these passions, but always so, that I could myself well enough
distinguish them, and never in any degree of comparison with one
another; the first maintaining its flight in so lofty and so brave a
place, as with disdain to look down, and see the other flying at a far
humbler pitch below.
As concerning marriage, besides that it is a covenant, the entrance
into which only is free, but the continuance in it forced and
compulsory, having another dependence than that of our own free will,
and a bargain commonly contracted to other ends, there almost always
happens a thousand intricacies in it to unravel, enough to break the
thread and to divert the current of a lively affection: whereas
friendship has no manner of business or traffic with aught but itself.
Moreover, to say truth, the ordinary talent of women is not such as is
sufficient to maintain the conference and communication required to the
support of this sacred tie; nor do they appear to be endued with
constancy of mind, to sustain the pinch of so hard and durable a knot.
And doubtless, if without this, there could be such a free and voluntary
familiarity contracted, where not only the souls might have this entire
fruition, but the bodies also might share in the alliance, and a man be
engaged throughout, the friendship would certainly be more full and
perfect; but it is without example that this sex has ever yet arrived at
such perfection; and, by the common consent of the ancient schools, it
is wholly rejected from it.
That other Grecian licence is justly abhorred by our manners, which
also, from having, according to their practice, a so necessary disparity
of age and difference of offices betwixt the lovers, answered no more to
the perfect union and harmony that we here require than the other:
"Quis est enim iste amor amicitiae? cur neque deformem
adolescentem quisquam amat, neque formosum senem?"
["For what is that friendly love? why does no one love a deformed
youth or a comely old man?"—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., iv. 33.]
Neither will that very picture that the Academy presents of it, as I
conceive, contradict me, when I say, that this first fury inspired by
the son of Venus into the heart of the lover, upon sight of the flower
and prime of a springing and blossoming youth, to which they allow all
the insolent and passionate efforts that an immoderate ardour can
produce, was simply founded upon external beauty, the false image of
corporal generation; for it could not ground this love upon the soul,
the sight of which as yet lay concealed, was but now springing, and not
of maturity to blossom; that this fury, if it seized upon a low spirit,
the means by which it preferred its suit were rich presents, favour in
advancement to dignities, and such trumpery, which they by no means
approve; if on a more generous soul, the pursuit was suitably generous,
by philosophical instructions, precepts to revere religion, to obey the
laws, to die for the good of one's country; by examples of valour,
prudence, and justice, the lover studying to render himself acceptable
by the grace and beauty of the soul, that of his body being long since
faded and decayed, hoping by this mental society to establish a more
firm and lasting contract. When this courtship came to effect in due
season (for that which they do not require in the lover, namely, leisure
and discretion in his pursuit, they strictly require in the person
loved, forasmuch as he is to judge of an internal beauty, of difficult
knowledge and abstruse discovery), then there sprung in the person loved
the desire of a spiritual conception; by the mediation of a spiritual
beauty. This was the principal; the corporeal, an accidental and
secondary matter; quite the contrary as to the lover. For this reason
they prefer the person beloved, maintaining that the gods in like manner
preferred him too, and very much blame the poet AEschylus for having, in
the loves of Achilles and Patroclus, given the lover's part to Achilles,
who was in the first and beardless flower of his adolescence, and the
handsomest of all the Greeks. After this general community, the
sovereign, and most worthy part presiding and governing, and performing
its proper offices, they say, that thence great utility was derived,
both by private and public concerns; that it constituted the force and
power of the countries where it prevailed, and the chiefest security of
liberty and justice. Of which the healthy loves of Harmodius and
Aristogiton are instances. And therefore it is that they called it
sacred and divine, and conceive that nothing but the violence of tyrants
and the baseness of the common people are inimical to it. Finally, all
that can be said in favour of the Academy is, that it was a love which
ended in friendship, which well enough agrees with the Stoical
definition of love:
"Amorem conatum esse amicitiae faciendae
ex pulchritudinis specie."
["Love is a desire of contracting friendship arising from the beauty
of the object."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., vi. 34.]
I return to my own more just and true description:
"Omnino amicitiae, corroboratis jam confirmatisque,
et ingeniis, et aetatibus, judicandae sunt."
["Those are only to be reputed friendships that are fortified and
confirmed by judgement and the length of time."
—Cicero, De Amicit., c. 20.]
For the rest, what we commonly call friends and friendships, are
nothing but acquaintance and familiarities, either occasionally
contracted, or upon some design, by means of which there happens some
little intercourse betwixt our souls. But in the friendship I speak of,
they mix and work themselves into one piece, with so universal a
mixture, that there is no more sign of the seam by which they were first
conjoined. If a man should importune me to give a reason why I loved
him, I find it could no otherwise be expressed, than by making answer:
because it was he, because it was I. There is, beyond all that I am able
to say, I know not what inexplicable and fated power that brought on
this union. We sought one another long before we met, and by the
characters we heard of one another, which wrought upon our affections
more than, in reason, mere reports should do; I think 'twas by some
secret appointment of heaven. We embraced in our names; and at our first
meeting, which was accidentally at a great city entertainment, we found
ourselves so mutually taken with one another, so acquainted, and so
endeared betwixt ourselves, that from thenceforward nothing was so near
to us as one another. He wrote an excellent Latin satire, since printed,
wherein he excuses the precipitation of our intelligence, so suddenly
come to perfection, saying, that destined to have so short a
continuance, as begun so late (for we were both full-grown men, and he
some years the older), there was no time to lose, nor were we tied to
conform to the example of those slow and regular friendships, that
require so many precautions of long preliminary conversation: This has
no other idea than that of itself, and can only refer to itself: this is
no one special consideration, nor two, nor three, nor four, nor a
thousand; 'tis I know not what quintessence of all this mixture, which,
seizing my whole will, carried it to plunge and lose itself in his, and
that having seized his whole will, brought it back with equal
concurrence and appetite to plunge and lose itself in mine. I may truly
say lose, reserving nothing to ourselves that was either his or
mine.—[All this relates to Estienne de la Boetie.]
When Laelius,—[Cicero, De Amicit., c. II.]—in the presence of the
Roman consuls, who after thay had sentenced Tiberius Gracchus,
prosecuted all those who had had any familiarity with him also; came to
ask Caius Blosius, who was his chiefest friend, how much he would have
done for him, and that he made answer: "All things."—"How! All things!"
said Laelius. "And what if he had commanded you to fire our
temples?"—"He would never have commanded me that," replied Blosius.—"But
what if he had?" said Laelius.—"I would have obeyed him," said the
other. If he was so perfect a friend to Gracchus as the histories report
him to have been, there was yet no necessity of offending the consuls by
such a bold confession, though he might still have retained the
assurance he had of Gracchus' disposition. However, those who accuse
this answer as seditious, do not well understand the mystery; nor
presuppose, as it was true, that he had Gracchus' will in his sleeve,
both by the power of a friend, and the perfect knowledge he had of the
man: they were more friends than citizens, more friends to one another
than either enemies or friends to their country, or than friends to
ambition and innovation; having absolutely given up themselves to one
another, either held absolutely the reins of the other's inclination;
and suppose all this guided by virtue, and all this by the conduct of
reason, which also without these it had not been possible to do,
Blosius' answer was such as it ought to be. If any of their actions flew
out of the handle, they were neither (according to my measure of
friendship) friends to one another, nor to themselves. As to the rest,
this answer carries no worse sound, than mine would do to one that
should ask me: "If your will should command you to kill your daughter,
would you do it?" and that I should make answer, that I would; for this
expresses no consent to such an act, forasmuch as I do not in the least
suspect my own will, and as little that of such a friend. 'Tis not in
the power of all the eloquence in the world, to dispossess me of the
certainty I have of the intentions and resolutions of my friend; nay, no
one action of his, what face soever it might bear, could be presented to
me, of which I could not presently, and at first sight, find out the
moving cause. Our souls had drawn so unanimously together, they had
considered each other with so ardent an affection, and with the like
affection laid open the very bottom of our hearts to one another's view,
that I not only knew his as well as my own; but should certainly in any
concern of mine have trusted my interest much more willingly with him,
than with myself.
Let no one, therefore, rank other common friendships with such a one
as this. I have had as much experience of these as another, and of the
most perfect of their kind: but I do not advise that any should confound
the rules of the one and the other, for they would find themselves much
deceived. In those other ordinary friendships, you are to walk with
bridle in your hand, with prudence and circumspection, for in them the
knot is not so sure that a man may not half suspect it will slip. "Love
him," said Chilo,—[Aulus Gellius, i. 3.]—"so as if you were one day to
hate him; and hate him so as you were one day to love him." This
precept, though abominable in the sovereign and perfect friendship I
speak of, is nevertheless very sound as to the practice of the ordinary
and customary ones, and to which the saying that Aristotle had so
frequent in his mouth, "O my friends, there is no friend," may very
fitly be applied. In this noble commerce, good offices, presents, and
benefits, by which other friendships are supported and maintained, do
not deserve so much as to be mentioned; and the reason is the
concurrence of our wills; for, as the kindness I have for myself
receives no increase, for anything I relieve myself withal in time of
need (whatever the Stoics say), and as I do not find myself obliged to
myself for any service I do myself: so the union of such friends, being
truly perfect, deprives them of all idea of such duties, and makes them
loathe and banish from their conversation these words of division and
distinction, benefits, obligation, acknowledgment, entreaty, thanks, and
the like. All things, wills, thoughts, opinions, goods, wives, children,
honours, and lives, being in effect common betwixt them, and that
absolute concurrence of affections being no other than one soul in two
bodies (according to that very proper definition of Aristotle), they can
neither lend nor give anything to one another. This is the reason why
the lawgivers, to honour marriage with some resemblance of this divine
alliance, interdict all gifts betwixt man and wife; inferring by that,
that all should belong to each of them, and that they have nothing to
divide or to give to each other.
If, in the friendship of which I speak, one could give to the other,
the receiver of the benefit would be the man that obliged his friend;
for each of them contending and above all things studying how to be
useful to the other, he that administers the occasion is the liberal
man, in giving his friend the satisfaction of doing that towards him
which above all things he most desires. When the philosopher Diogenes
wanted money, he used to say, that he redemanded it of his friends, not
that he demanded it. And to let you see the practical working of this, I
will here produce an ancient and singular example. Eudamidas, a
Corinthian, had two friends, Charixenus a Sicyonian and Areteus a
Corinthian; this man coming to die, being poor, and his two friends
rich, he made his will after this manner. "I bequeath to Areteus the
maintenance of my mother, to support and provide for her in her old age;
and to Charixenus I bequeath the care of marrying my daughter, and to
give her as good a portion as he is able; and in case one of these
chance to die, I hereby substitute the survivor in his place." They who
first saw this will made themselves very merry at the contents: but the
legatees, being made acquainted with it, accepted it with very great
content; and one of them, Charixenus, dying within five days after, and
by that means the charge of both duties devolving solely on him, Areteus
nurtured the old woman with very great care and tenderness, and of five
talents he had in estate, he gave two and a half in marriage with an
only daughter he had of his own, and two and a half in marriage with the
daughter of Eudamidas, and on one and the same day solemnised both their
nuptials.
This example is very full, if one thing were not to be objected,
namely the multitude of friends for the perfect friendship I speak of is
indivisible; each one gives himself so entirely to his friend, that he
has nothing left to distribute to others: on the contrary, is sorry that
he is not double, treble, or quadruple, and that he has not many souls
and many wills, to confer them all upon this one object. Common
friendships will admit of division; one may love the beauty of this
person, the good-humour of that, the liberality of a third, the paternal
affection of a fourth, the fraternal love of a fifth, and so of the
rest: but this friendship that possesses the whole soul, and there rules
and sways with an absolute sovereignty, cannot possibly admit of a
rival. If two at the same time should call to you for succour, to which
of them would you run? Should they require of you contrary offices, how
could you serve them both? Should one commit a thing to your silence
that it were of importance to the other to know, how would you disengage
yourself? A unique and particular friendship dissolves all other
obligations whatsoever: the secret I have sworn not to reveal to any
other, I may without perjury communicate to him who is not another, but
myself. 'Tis miracle enough certainly, for a man to double himself, and
those that talk of tripling, talk they know not of what. Nothing is
extreme, that has its like; and he who shall suppose, that of two, I
love one as much as the other, that they mutually love one another too,
and love me as much as I love them, multiplies into a confraternity the
most single of units, and whereof, moreover, one alone is the hardest
thing in the world to find. The rest of this story suits very well with
what I was saying; for Eudamidas, as a bounty and favour, bequeaths to
his friends a legacy of employing themselves in his necessity; he leaves
them heirs to this liberality of his, which consists in giving them the
opportunity of conferring a benefit upon him; and doubtless, the force
of friendship is more eminently apparent in this act of his, than in
that of Areteus. In short, these are effects not to be imagined nor
comprehended by such as have not experience of them, and which make me
infinitely honour and admire the answer of that young soldier to Cyrus,
by whom being asked how much he would take for a horse, with which he
had won the prize of a race, and whether he would exchange him for a
kingdom? —"No, truly, sir," said he, "but I would give him with all my
heart, to get thereby a true friend, could I find out any man worthy of
that alliance."—[Xenophon, Cyropadia, viii. 3.]—He did not say ill in
saying, "could I find": for though one may almost everywhere meet with
men sufficiently qualified for a superficial acquaintance, yet in this,
where a man is to deal from the very bottom of his heart, without any
manner of reservation, it will be requisite that all the wards and
springs be truly wrought and perfectly sure.
In confederations that hold but by one end, we are only to provide
against the imperfections that particularly concern that end. It can be
of no importance to me of what religion my physician or my lawyer is;
this consideration has nothing in common with the offices of friendship
which they owe me; and I am of the same indifference in the domestic
acquaintance my servants must necessarily contract with me. I never
inquire, when I am to take a footman, if he be chaste, but if he be
diligent; and am not solicitous if my muleteer be given to gaming, as if
he be strong and able; or if my cook be a swearer, if he be a good cook.
I do not take upon me to direct what other men should do in the
government of their families, there are plenty that meddle enough with
that, but only give an account of my method in my own:
"Mihi sic usus est: tibi, ut opus est facto, face."
["This has been my way; as for you, do as you find needful.
—"Terence, Heaut., i. I., 28.]
For table-talk, I prefer the pleasant and witty before the learned
and the grave; in bed, beauty before goodness; in common discourse the
ablest speaker, whether or no there be sincerity in the case. And, as he
that was found astride upon a hobby-horse, playing with his children,
entreated the person who had surprised him in that posture to say
nothing of it till himself came to be a father,—[Plutarch, Life of
Agesilaus, c. 9.]—supposing that the fondness that would then possess
his own soul, would render him a fairer judge of such an action; so I,
also, could wish to speak to such as have had experience of what I say:
though, knowing how remote a thing such a friendship is from the common
practice, and how rarely it is to be found, I despair of meeting with
any such judge. For even these discourses left us by antiquity upon this
subject, seem to me flat and poor, in comparison of the sense I have of
it, and in this particular, the effects surpass even the precepts of
philosophy.
"Nil ego contulerim jucundo sanus amico."
["While I have sense left to me, there will never be anything more
acceptable to me than an agreeable friend."
—Horace, Sat., i. 5, 44.]
The ancient Menander declared him to be happy that had had the good
fortune to meet with but the shadow of a friend: and doubtless he had
good reason to say so, especially if he spoke by experience: for in good
earnest, if I compare all the rest of my life, though, thanks be to God,
I have passed my time pleasantly enough, and at my ease, and the loss of
such a friend excepted, free from any grievous affliction, and in great
tranquillity of mind, having been contented with my natural and original
commodities, without being solicitous after others; if I should compare
it all, I say, with the four years I had the happiness to enjoy the
sweet society of this excellent man, 'tis nothing but smoke, an obscure
and tedious night. From the day that I lost him:
"Quern semper acerbum,
Semper honoratum (sic, di, voluistis) habebo,"
["A day for me ever sad, for ever sacred, so have you willed ye
gods."—AEneid, v. 49.]
I have only led a languishing life; and the very pleasures that
present themselves to me, instead of administering anything of
consolation, double my affliction for his loss. We were halves
throughout, and to that degree, that methinks, by outliving him, I
defraud him of his part.
"Nec fas esse ulla me voluptate hic frui
Decrevi, tantisper dum ille abest meus particeps."
["I have determined that it will never be right for me to enjoy any
pleasure, so long as he, with whom I shared all pleasures is away."
—Terence, Heaut., i. I. 97.]
I was so grown and accustomed to be always his double in all places
and in all things, that methinks I am no more than half of myself:
"Illam meae si partem anima tulit
Maturior vis, quid moror altera?
Nec carus aeque, nec superstes
Integer? Ille dies utramque
Duxit ruinam."
["If that half of my soul were snatch away from me by an untimely
stroke, why should the other stay? That which remains will not be
equally dear, will not be whole: the same day will involve the
destruction of both."]
or:
["If a superior force has taken that part of my soul, why do I, the
remaining one, linger behind? What is left is not so dear, nor an
entire thing: this day has wrought the destruction of both."
—Horace, Ode, ii. 17, 5.]
There is no action or imagination of mine wherein I do not miss him;
as I know that he would have missed me: for as he surpassed me by
infinite degrees in virtue and all other accomplishments, so he also did
in the duties of friendship:
"Quis desiderio sit pudor, aut modus
Tam cari capitis?"
["What shame can there, or measure, in lamenting so dear a friend?"
—Horace, Ode, i. 24, I.]
"O misero frater adempte mihi!
Omnia tecum una perierunt gaudia nostra,
Quae tuus in vita dulcis alebat amor.
Tu mea, tu moriens fregisti commoda, frater;
Tecum una tota est nostra sepulta anima
Cujus ego interitu tota de menthe fugavi
Haec studia, atque omnes delicias animi.
Alloquar? audiero nunquam tua verba loquentem?
Nunquam ego te, vita frater amabilior
Aspiciam posthac; at certe semper amabo;"
["O brother, taken from me miserable! with thee, all our joys have
vanished, those joys which, in thy life, thy dear love nourished.
Dying, thou, my brother, hast destroyed all my happiness. My whole
soul is buried with thee. Through whose death I have banished from
my mind these studies, and all the delights of the mind. Shall I
address thee? I shall never hear thy voice. Never shall I behold
thee hereafter. O brother, dearer to me than life. Nought remains,
but assuredly I shall ever love thee."—Catullus, lxviii. 20; lxv.]
But let us hear a boy of sixteen speak:
—[In Cotton's translation the work referred to is "those Memoirs
upon the famous edict of January," of which mention has already been
made in the present edition. The edition of 1580, however, and the
Variorum edition of 1872-1900, indicate no particular work; but the
edition of 1580 has it "this boy of eighteen years" (which was the
age at which La Boetie wrote his "Servitude Volontaire"), speaks of
"a boy of sixteen" as occurring only in the common editions, and it
would seem tolerably clear that this more important work was, in
fact, the production to which Montaigne refers, and that the proper
reading of the text should be "sixteen years." What "this boy
spoke" is not given by Montaigne, for the reason stated in the next
following paragraph.]
"Because I have found that that work has been since brought out, and
with a mischievous design, by those who aim at disturbing and changing
the condition of our government, without troubling themselves to think
whether they are likely to improve it: and because they have mixed up
his work with some of their own performance, I have refrained from
inserting it here. But that the memory of the author may not be injured,
nor suffer with such as could not come near-hand to be acquainted with
his principles, I here give them to understand, that it was written by
him in his boyhood, and that by way of exercise only, as a common theme
that has been hackneyed by a thousand writers. I make no question but
that he himself believed what he wrote, being so conscientious that he
would not so much as lie in jest: and I moreover know, that could it
have been in his own choice, he had rather have been born at Venice,
than at Sarlac; and with reason. But he had another maxim sovereignty
imprinted in his soul, very religiously to obey and submit to the laws
under which he was born. There never was a better citizen, more
affectionate to his country; nor a greater enemy to all the commotions
and innovations of his time: so that he would much rather have employed
his talent to the extinguishing of those civil flames, than have added
any fuel to them; he had a mind fashioned to the model of better ages.
Now, in exchange of this serious piece, I will present you with another
of a more gay and frolic air, from the same hand, and written at the
same age."
CHAPTER XXVIII——NINE AND TWENTY SONNETS OF ESTIENNE DE LA BOITIE
TO MADAME DE GRAMMONT, COMTESSE DE GUISSEN.
[They scarce contain anything but amorous complaints, expressed in a
very rough style, discovering the follies and outrages of a restless
passion, overgorged, as it were, with jealousies, fears and
suspicions.—Coste.]
[These....contained in the edition of 1588 nine-and-twenty sonnets
of La Boetie, accompanied by a dedicatory epistle to Madame de
Grammont. The former, which are referred to at the end of Chap.
XXVIL, do not really belong to the book, and are of very slight
interest at this time; the epistle is transferred to the
Correspondence. The sonnets, with the letter, were presumably sent
some time after Letters V. et seq. Montaigne seems to have had
several copies written out to forward to friends or acquaintances.]
CHAPTER XXIX——OF MODERATION
As if we had an infectious touch, we, by our manner of handling,
corrupt things that in themselves are laudable and good: we may grasp
virtue so that it becomes vicious, if we embrace it too stringently and
with too violent a desire. Those who say, there is never any excess in
virtue, forasmuch as it is not virtue when it once becomes excess, only
play upon words:
"Insani sapiens nomen ferat, aequus iniqui,
Ultra quam satis est, virtutem si petat ipsam."
["Let the wise man bear the name of a madman, the just one of an
unjust, if he seek wisdom more than is sufficient."
—Horace, Ep., i. 6, 15.]
["The wise man is no longer wise, the just man no longer just, if he
seek to carry his love for wisdom or virtue beyond that which is
necessary."]
This is a subtle consideration of philosophy. A man may both be too
much in love with virtue, and be excessive in a just action. Holy Writ
agrees with this, Be not wiser than you should, but be soberly
wise.—[St. Paul, Epistle to the Romans, xii. 3.]—I have known a great
man,
—["It is likely that Montaigne meant Henry III., king of France.
The Cardinal d'Ossat, writing to Louise, the queen-dowager, told
her, in his frank manner, that he had lived as much or more like a
monk than a monarch (Letter XXIII.) And Pope Sextus V., speaking of
that prince one day to the Cardinal de Joyeuse, protector of the
affairs of France, said to him pleasantly, 'There is nothing that
your king hath not done, and does not do so still, to be a monk, nor
anything that I have not done, not to be a monk.'"—Coste.]
prejudice the opinion men had of his devotion, by pretending to be
devout beyond all examples of others of his condition. I love temperate
and moderate natures. An immoderate zeal, even to that which is good,
even though it does not offend, astonishes me, and puts me to study what
name to give it. Neither the mother of Pausanias,
—["Montaigne would here give us to understand, upon the authority of
Diodorus Siculus, that Pausanias' mother gave the first hint of the
punishment that was to be inflicted on her son. 'Pausanias,' says
this historian, 'perceiving that the ephori, and some other
Lacedoemonians, aimed at apprehending him, got the start of them,
and went and took sanctuary m Minerva's temple: and the
Lacedaemonians, being doubtful whether they ought to take him from
thence in violation of the franchise there, it is said that his own
mother came herself to the temple but spoke nothing nor did anything
more than lay a piece of brick, which she brought with her, on the
threshold of the temple, which, when she had done, she returned
home. The Lacedaemonians, taking the hint from the mother, caused
the gate of the temple to be walled up, and by this means starved
Pausanias, so that he died with hunger, &c. (lib. xi. cap. 10., of
Amyot's translation). The name of Pausanias' mother was Alcithea,
as we are informed by Thucydides' scholiast, who only says that it
was reported, that when they set about walling up the gates of the
chapel in which Pausanias had taken refuge, his mother Alcithea laid
the first stone."—Coste.]
who was the first instructor of her son's process, and threw the
first stone towards his death, nor Posthumius the dictator, who put his
son to death, whom the ardour of youth had successfully pushed upon the
enemy a little more advanced than the rest of his squadron, do appear to
me so much just as strange; and I should neither advise nor like to
follow so savage a virtue, and that costs so dear.
—["Opinions differ as to the truth of this fact. Livy thinks he
has good authority for rejecting it because it does not appear in
history that Posthumious was branded with it, as Titus Manlius was,
about 100 years after his time; for Manlius, having put his son to
death for the like cause, obtained the odious name of Imperiosus,
and since that time Manliana imperia has been used as a term to
signify orders that are too severe; Manliana Imperia, says Livy,
were not only horrible for the time present, but of a bad example to
posterity. And this historian makes no doubt but such commands
would have been actually styled Posthumiana Imperia, if Posthumius
had been the first who set so barbarous an example (Livy, lib. iv.
cap. 29, and lib. viii. cap. 7). But, however, Montaigne has Valer.
Maximus on his side, who says expressly, that Posthumius caused his
son to be put to death, and Diodorus of Sicily (lib. xii. cap.
19)."—Coste.]
The archer that shoots over, misses as much as he that falls short,
and 'tis equally troublesome to my sight, to look up at a great light,
and to look down into a dark abyss. Callicles in Plato says, that the
extremity of philosophy is hurtful, and advises not to dive into it
beyond the limits of profit; that, taken moderately, it is pleasant and
useful; but that in the end it renders a man brutish and vicious, a
contemner of religion and the common laws, an enemy to civil
conversation, and all human pleasures, incapable of all public
administration, unfit either to assist others or to relieve himself, and
a fit object for all sorts of injuries and affronts. He says true; for
in its excess, it enslaves our natural freedom, and by an impertinent
subtlety, leads us out of the fair and beaten way that nature has traced
for us.
The love we bear to our wives is very lawful, and yet theology thinks
fit to curb and restrain it. As I remember, I have read in one place of
St. Thomas Aquinas,—[Secunda Secundx, Quaest. 154, art. 9.]—where he
condemns marriages within any of the forbidden degrees, for this reason,
amongst others, that there is some danger, lest the friendship a man
bears to such a woman, should be immoderate; for if the conjugal
affection be full and perfect betwixt them, as it ought to be, and that
it be over and above surcharged with that of kindred too, there is no
doubt, but such an addition will carry the husband beyond the bounds of
reason.
Those sciences that regulate the manners of men, divinity and
philosophy, will have their say in everything; there is no action so
private and secret that can escape their inspection and jurisdiction.
They are best taught who are best able to control and curb their own
liberty; women expose their nudities as much as you will upon the
account of pleasure, though in the necessities of physic they are
altogether as shy. I will, therefore, in their behalf:
—[Coste translates this: "on the part of philosophy and theology,"
observing that but few wives would think themselves obliged to
Montaigne for any such lesson to their husbands.]—
teach the husbands, that is, such as are too vehement in the exercise
of the matrimonial duty—if such there still be—this lesson, that the
very pleasures they enjoy in the society of their wives are reproachable
if immoderate, and that a licentious and riotous abuse of them is a
fault as reprovable here as in illicit connections. Those immodest and
debauched tricks and postures, that the first ardour suggests to us in
this affair, are not only indecently but detrimentally practised upon
our wives. Let them at least learn impudence from another hand; they are
ever ready enough for our business, and I for my part always went the
plain way to work.
Marriage is a solemn and religious tie, and therefore the pleasure we
extract from it should be a sober and serious delight, and mixed with a
certain kind of gravity; it should be a sort of discreet and
conscientious pleasure. And seeing that the chief end of it is
generation, some make a question, whether when men are out of hopes as
when they are superannuated or already with child, it be lawful to
embrace our wives. 'Tis homicide, according to Plato.—[Laws, 8.]—
Certain nations (the Mohammedan, amongst others) abominate all
conjunction with women with child, others also, with those who are in
their courses. Zenobia would never admit her husband for more than one
encounter, after which she left him to his own swing for the whole time
of her conception, and not till after that would again receive
him:—[Trebellius Pollio, Triginta Tyran., c. 30.]—a brave and generous
example of conjugal continence. It was doubtless from some lascivious
poet,—[The lascivious poet is Homer; see his Iliad, xiv. 294.]—and one
that himself was in great distress for a little of this sport, that
Plato borrowed this story; that Jupiter was one day so hot upon his
wife, that not having so much patience as till she could get to the
couch, he threw her upon the floor, where the vehemence of pleasure made
him forget the great and important resolutions he had but newly taken
with the rest of the gods in his celestial council, and to brag that he
had had as good a bout, as when he got her maidenhead, unknown to their
parents.
The kings of Persia were wont to invite their wives to the beginning
of their festivals; but when the wine began to work in good earnest, and
that they were to give the reins to pleasure, they sent them back to
their private apartments, that they might not participate in their
immoderate lust, sending for other women in their stead, with whom they
were not obliged to so great a decorum of respect.—[Plutarch, Precepts
of Marriage, c. 14.]—All pleasures and all sorts of gratifications are
not properly and fitly conferred upon all sorts of persons. Epaminondas
had committed to prison a young man for certain debauches; for whom
Pelopidas mediated, that at his request he might be set at liberty,
which Epaminondas denied to him, but granted it at the first word to a
wench of his, that made the same intercession; saying, that it was a
gratification fit for such a one as she, but not for a captain.
Sophocles being joint praetor with Pericles, seeing accidentally a fine
boy pass by: "O what a charming boy is that!" said he. "That might be
very well," answered Pericles, "for any other than a praetor, who ought
not only to have his hands, but his eyes, too, chaste."—[Cicero, De
Offic., i. 40.] AElius Verus, the emperor, answered his wife, who
reproached him with his love to other women, that he did it upon a
conscientious account, forasmuch as marriage was a name of honour and
dignity, not of wanton and lascivious desire; and our ecclesiastical
history preserves the memory of that woman in great veneration, who
parted from her husband because she would not comply with his indecent
and inordinate desires. In fine, there is no pleasure so just and
lawful, where intemperance and excess are not to be condemned.
But, to speak the truth, is not man a most miserable creature the
while? It is scarce, by his natural condition, in his power to taste one
pleasure pure and entire; and yet must he be contriving doctrines and
precepts to curtail that little he has; he is not yet wretched enough,
unless by art and study he augment his own misery:
"Fortunae miseras auximus arte vias."
["We artificially augment the wretchedness of fortune."
—Properitius, lib. iii. 7, 44.]
Human wisdom makes as ill use of her talent, when she exercises it in
rescinding from the number and sweetness of those pleasures that are
naturally our due, as she employs it favourably and well in artificially
disguising and tricking out the ills of life, to alleviate the sense of
them. Had I ruled the roast, I should have taken another and more
natural course, which, to say the truth, is both commodious and holy,
and should, peradventure, have been able to have limited it too;
notwithstanding that both our spiritual and corporal physicians, as by
compact betwixt themselves, can find no other way to cure, nor other
remedy for the infirmities of the body and the soul, than by misery and
pain. To this end, watchings, fastings, hair-shirts, remote and solitary
banishments, perpetual imprisonments, whips and other afflictions, have
been introduced amongst men: but so, that they should carry a sting with
them, and be real afflictions indeed; and not fall out as it once did to
one Gallio, who having been sent an exile into the isle of Lesbos, news
was not long after brought to Rome, that he there lived as merry as the
day was long; and that what had been enjoined him for a penance, turned
to his pleasure and satisfaction: whereupon the Senate thought fit to
recall him home to his wife and family, and confine him to his own
house, to accommodate their punishment to his feeling and apprehension.
For to him whom fasting would make more healthful and more sprightly,
and to him to whose palate fish were more acceptable than flesh, the
prescription of these would have no curative effect; no more than in the
other sort of physic, where drugs have no effect upon him who swallows
them with appetite and pleasure: the bitterness of the potion and the
abhorrence of the patient are necessary circumstances to the operation.
The nature that would eat rhubarb like buttered turnips, would frustrate
the use and virtue of it; it must be something to trouble and disturb
the stomach, that must purge and cure it; and here the common rule, that
things are cured by their contraries, fails; for in this one ill is
cured by another.
This belief a little resembles that other so ancient one, of thinking
to gratify the gods and nature by massacre and murder: an opinion
universally once received in all religions. And still, in these later
times wherein our fathers lived, Amurath at the taking of the Isthmus,
immolated six hundred young Greeks to his father's soul, in the nature
of a propitiatory sacrifice for his sins. And in those new countries
discovered in this age of ours, which are pure and virgin yet, in
comparison of ours, this practice is in some measure everywhere
received: all their idols reek with human blood, not without various
examples of horrid cruelty: some they burn alive, and take, half
broiled, off the coals to tear out their hearts and entrails; some, even
women, they flay alive, and with their bloody skins clothe and disguise
others. Neither are we without great examples of constancy and
resolution in this affair the poor souls that are to be sacrificed, old
men, women, and children, themselves going about some days before to beg
alms for the offering of their sacrifice, presenting themselves to the
slaughter, singing and dancing with the spectators.
The ambassadors of the king of Mexico, setting out to Fernando Cortez
the power and greatness of their master, after having told him, that he
had thirty vassals, of whom each was able to raise an hundred thousand
fighting men, and that he kept his court in the fairest and best
fortified city under the sun, added at last, that he was obliged yearly
to offer to the gods fifty thousand men. And it is affirmed, that he
maintained a continual war, with some potent neighbouring nations, not
only to keep the young men in exercise, but principally to have
wherewithal to furnish his sacrifices with his prisoners of war. At a
certain town in another place, for the welcome of the said Cortez, they
sacrificed fifty men at once. I will tell you this one tale more, and I
have done; some of these people being beaten by him, sent to acknowledge
him, and to treat with him of a peace, whose messengers carried him
three sorts of gifts, which they presented in these terms: "Behold,
lord, here are five slaves: if thou art a furious god that feedeth upon
flesh and blood, eat these, and we will bring thee more; if thou art an
affable god, behold here incense and feathers; but if thou art a man,
take these fowls and these fruits that we have brought thee."
CHAPTER XXX——OF CANNIBALS
When King Pyrrhus invaded Italy, having viewed and considered the
order of the army the Romans sent out to meet him; "I know not," said
he, "what kind of barbarians" (for so the Greeks called all other
nations) "these may be; but the disposition of this army that I see has
nothing of barbarism in it."—[Plutarch, Life of Pyrrhus, c. 8.]—As much
said the Greeks of that which Flaminius brought into their country; and
Philip, beholding from an eminence the order and distribution of the
Roman camp formed in his kingdom by Publius Sulpicius Galba, spake to
the same effect. By which it appears how cautious men ought to be of
taking things upon trust from vulgar opinion, and that we are to judge
by the eye of reason, and not from common report.
I long had a man in my house that lived ten or twelve years in the
New World, discovered in these latter days, and in that part of it where
Villegaignon landed,—[At Brazil, in 1557.]—which he called Antarctic
France. This discovery of so vast a country seems to be of very great
consideration. I cannot be sure, that hereafter there may not be
another, so many wiser men than we having been deceived in this. I am
afraid our eyes are bigger than our bellies, and that we have more
curiosity than capacity; for we grasp at all, but catch nothing but
wind.
Plato brings in Solon,—[In Timaeus.]—telling a story that he had
heard from the priests of Sais in Egypt, that of old, and before the
Deluge, there was a great island called Atlantis, situate directly at
the mouth of the straits of Gibraltar, which contained more countries
than both Africa and Asia put together; and that the kings of that
country, who not only possessed that Isle, but extended their dominion
so far into the continent that they had a country of Africa as far as
Egypt, and extending in Europe to Tuscany, attempted to encroach even
upon Asia, and to subjugate all the nations that border upon the
Mediterranean Sea, as far as the Black Sea; and to that effect overran
all Spain, the Gauls, and Italy, so far as to penetrate into Greece,
where the Athenians stopped them: but that some time after, both the
Athenians, and they and their island, were swallowed by the Flood.
It is very likely that this extreme irruption and inundation of water
made wonderful changes and alterations in the habitations of the earth,
as 'tis said that the sea then divided Sicily from Italy—
"Haec loca, vi quondam et vasta convulsa ruina,
Dissiluisse ferunt, quum protenus utraque tellus
Una foret"
["These lands, they say, formerly with violence and vast desolation
convulsed, burst asunder, where erewhile were."—AEneid, iii. 414.]
Cyprus from Syria, the isle of Negropont from the continent of
Beeotia, and elsewhere united lands that were separate before, by
filling up the channel betwixt them with sand and mud:
"Sterilisque diu palus, aptaque remis,
Vicinas urbes alit, et grave sentit aratrum."
["That which was once a sterile marsh, and bore vessels on its
bosom, now feeds neighbouring cities, and admits the plough."
—Horace, De Arte Poetica, v. 65.]
But there is no great appearance that this isle was this New World so
lately discovered: for that almost touched upon Spain, and it were an
incredible effect of an inundation, to have tumbled back so prodigious a
mass, above twelve hundred leagues: besides that our modern navigators
have already almost discovered it to be no island, but terra firma, and
continent with the East Indies on the one side, and with the lands under
the two poles on the other side; or, if it be separate from them, it is
by so narrow a strait and channel, that it none the more deserves the
name of an island for that.
It should seem, that in this great body, there are two sorts of
motions, the one natural and the other febrific, as there are in ours.
When I consider the impression that our river of Dordogne has made in my
time on the right bank of its descent, and that in twenty years it has
gained so much, and undermined the foundations of so many houses, I
perceive it to be an extraordinary agitation: for had it always followed
this course, or were hereafter to do it, the aspect of the world would
be totally changed. But rivers alter their course, sometimes beating
against the one side, and sometimes the other, and some times quietly
keeping the channel. I do not speak of sudden inundations, the causes of
which everybody understands. In Medoc, by the seashore, the Sieur
d'Arsac, my brother, sees an estate he had there, buried under the sands
which the sea vomits before it: where the tops of some houses are yet to
be seen, and where his rents and domains are converted into pitiful
barren pasturage. The inhabitants of this place affirm, that of late
years the sea has driven so vehemently upon them, that they have lost
above four leagues of land. These sands are her harbingers: and we now
see great heaps of moving sand, that march half a league before her, and
occupy the land.
The other testimony from antiquity, to which some would apply this
discovery of the New World, is in Aristotle; at least, if that little
book of Unheard of Miracles be his—[one of the spurious publications
brought out under his name—D.W.]. He there tells us, that certain
Carthaginians, having crossed the Atlantic Sea without the Straits of
Gibraltar, and sailed a very long time, discovered at last a great and
fruitful island, all covered over with wood, and watered with several
broad and deep rivers, far remote from all terra firma; and that they,
and others after them, allured by the goodness and fertility of the
soil, went thither with their wives and children, and began to plant a
colony. But the senate of Carthage perceiving their people by little and
little to diminish, issued out an express prohibition, that none, upon
pain of death, should transport themselves thither; and also drove out
these new inhabitants; fearing, 'tis said, lest' in process of time they
should so multiply as to supplant themselves and ruin their state. But
this relation of Aristotle no more agrees with our new-found lands than
the other.
This man that I had was a plain ignorant fellow, and therefore the
more likely to tell truth: for your better-bred sort of men are much
more curious in their observation, 'tis true, and discover a great deal
more; but then they gloss upon it, and to give the greater weight to
what they deliver, and allure your belief, they cannot forbear a little
to alter the story; they never represent things to you simply as they
are, but rather as they appeared to them, or as they would have them
appear to you, and to gain the reputation of men of judgment, and the
better to induce your faith, are willing to help out the business with
something more than is really true, of their own invention. Now in this
case, we should either have a man of irreproachable veracity, or so
simple that he has not wherewithal to contrive, and to give a colour of
truth to false relations, and who can have no ends in forging an
untruth. Such a one was mine; and besides, he has at divers times
brought to me several seamen and merchants who at the same time went the
same voyage. I shall therefore content myself with his information,
without inquiring what the cosmographers say to the business. We should
have topographers to trace out to us the particular places where they
have been; but for having had this advantage over us, to have seen the
Holy Land, they would have the privilege, forsooth, to tell us stories
of all the other parts of the world beside. I would have every one write
what he knows, and as much as he knows, but no more; and that not in
this only but in all other subjects; for such a person may have some
particular knowledge and experience of the nature of such a river, or
such a fountain, who, as to other things, knows no more than what
everybody does, and yet to give a currency to his little pittance of
learning, will undertake to write the whole body of physics: a vice from
which great inconveniences derive their original.
Now, to return to my subject, I find that there is nothing barbarous
and savage in this nation, by anything that I can gather, excepting,
that every one gives the title of barbarism to everything that is not in
use in his own country. As, indeed, we have no other level of truth and
reason than the example and idea of the opinions and customs of the
place wherein we live: there is always the perfect religion, there the
perfect government, there the most exact and accomplished usage of all
things. They are savages at the same rate that we say fruits are wild,
which nature produces of herself and by her own ordinary progress;
whereas, in truth, we ought rather to call those wild whose natures we
have changed by our artifice and diverted from the common order. In
those, the genuine, most useful, and natural virtues and properties are
vigorous and sprightly, which we have helped to degenerate in these, by
accommodating them to the pleasure of our own corrupted palate. And yet
for all this, our taste confesses a flavour and delicacy excellent even
to emulation of the best of ours, in several fruits wherein those
countries abound without art or culture. Neither is it reasonable that
art should gain the pre-eminence of our great and powerful mother
nature. We have so surcharged her with the additional ornaments and
graces we have added to the beauty and riches of her own works by our
inventions, that we have almost smothered her; yet in other places,
where she shines in her own purity and proper lustre, she marvellously
baffles and disgraces all our vain and frivolous attempts:
"Et veniunt hederae sponte sua melius;
Surgit et in solis formosior arbutus antris;
Et volucres nulls dulcius arte canunt."
["The ivy grows best spontaneously, the arbutus best in shady caves;
and the wild notes of birds are sweeter than art can teach.
—"Propertius, i. 2, 10.]
Our utmost endeavours cannot arrive at so much as to imitate the nest
of the least of birds, its contexture, beauty, and convenience: not so
much as the web of a poor spider.
All things, says Plato,—[Laws, 10.]—are produced either by nature, by
fortune, or by art; the greatest and most beautiful by the one or the
other of the former, the least and the most imperfect by the last.
These nations then seem to me to be so far barbarous, as having
received but very little form and fashion from art and human invention,
and consequently to be not much remote from their original simplicity.
The laws of nature, however, govern them still, not as yet much vitiated
with any mixture of ours: but 'tis in such purity, that I am sometimes
troubled we were not sooner acquainted with these people, and that they
were not discovered in those better times, when there were men much more
able to judge of them than we are. I am sorry that Lycurgus and Plato
had no knowledge of them; for to my apprehension, what we now see in
those nations, does not only surpass all the pictures with which the
poets have adorned the golden age, and all their inventions in feigning
a happy state of man, but, moreover, the fancy and even the wish and
desire of philosophy itself; so native and so pure a simplicity, as we
by experience see to be in them, could never enter into their
imagination, nor could they ever believe that human society could have
been maintained with so little artifice and human patchwork. I should
tell Plato that it is a nation wherein there is no manner of traffic, no
knowledge of letters, no science of numbers, no name of magistrate or
political superiority; no use of service, riches or poverty, no
contracts, no successions, no dividends, no properties, no employments,
but those of leisure, no respect of kindred, but common, no clothing, no
agriculture, no metal, no use of corn or wine; the very words that
signify lying, treachery, dissimulation, avarice, envy, detraction,
pardon, never heard of.
—[This is the famous passage which Shakespeare, through Florio's
version, 1603, or ed. 1613, p. 102, has employed in the "Tempest,"
ii. 1.]
How much would he find his imaginary Republic short of his
perfection?
"Viri a diis recentes."
["Men fresh from the gods."—Seneca, Ep., 90.]
"Hos natura modos primum dedit."
["These were the manners first taught by nature."
—Virgil, Georgics, ii. 20.]
As to the rest, they live in a country very pleasant and temperate,
so that, as my witnesses inform me, 'tis rare to hear of a sick person,
and they moreover assure me, that they never saw any of the natives,
either paralytic, bleareyed, toothless, or crooked with age. The
situation of their country is along the sea-shore, enclosed on the other
side towards the land, with great and high mountains, having about a
hundred leagues in breadth between. They have great store of fish and
flesh, that have no resemblance to those of ours: which they eat without
any other cookery, than plain boiling, roasting, and broiling. The first
that rode a horse thither, though in several other voyages he had
contracted an acquaintance and familiarity with them, put them into so
terrible a fright, with his centaur appearance, that they killed him
with their arrows before they could come to discover who he was. Their
buildings are very long, and of capacity to hold two or three hundred
people, made of the barks of tall trees, reared with one end upon the
ground, and leaning to and supporting one another at the top, like some
of our barns, of which the covering hangs down to the very ground, and
serves for the side walls. They have wood so hard, that they cut with
it, and make their swords of it, and their grills of it to broil their
meat. Their beds are of cotton, hung swinging from the roof, like our
seamen's hammocks, every man his own, for the wives lie apart from their
husbands. They rise with the sun, and so soon as they are up, eat for
all day, for they have no more meals but that; they do not then drink,
as Suidas reports of some other people of the East that never drank at
their meals; but drink very often all day after, and sometimes to a
rousing pitch. Their drink is made of a certain root, and is of the
colour of our claret, and they never drink it but lukewarm. It will not
keep above two or three days; it has a somewhat sharp, brisk taste, is
nothing heady, but very comfortable to the stomach; laxative to
strangers, but a very pleasant beverage to such as are accustomed to it.
They make use, instead of bread, of a certain white compound, like
coriander seeds; I have tasted of it; the taste is sweet and a little
flat. The whole day is spent in dancing. Their young men go a-hunting
after wild beasts with bows and arrows; one part of their women are
employed in preparing their drink the while, which is their chief
employment. One of their old men, in the morning before they fall to
eating, preaches to the whole family, walking from the one end of the
house to the other, and several times repeating the same sentence, till
he has finished the round, for their houses are at least a hundred yards
long. Valour towards their enemies and love towards their wives, are the
two heads of his discourse, never failing in the close, to put them in
mind, that 'tis their wives who provide them their drink warm and well
seasoned. The fashion of their beds, ropes, swords, and of the wooden
bracelets they tie about their wrists, when they go to fight, and of the
great canes, bored hollow at one end, by the sound of which they keep
the cadence of their dances, are to be seen in several places, and
amongst others, at my house. They shave all over, and much more neatly
than we, without other razor than one of wood or stone. They believe in
the immortality of the soul, and that those who have merited well of the
gods are lodged in that part of heaven where the sun rises, and the
accursed in the west.
They have I know not what kind of priests and prophets, who very
rarely present themselves to the people, having their abode in the
mountains. At their arrival, there is a great feast, and solemn assembly
of many villages: each house, as I have described, makes a village, and
they are about a French league distant from one another. This prophet
declaims to them in public, exhorting them to virtue and their duty: but
all their ethics are comprised in these two articles, resolution in war,
and affection to their wives. He also prophesies to them events to come,
and the issues they are to expect from their enterprises, and prompts
them to or diverts them from war: but let him look to't; for if he fail
in his divination, and anything happen otherwise than he has foretold,
he is cut into a thousand pieces, if he be caught, and condemned for a
false prophet: for that reason, if any of them has been mistaken, he is
no more heard of.
Divination is a gift of God, and therefore to abuse it, ought to be a
punishable imposture. Amongst the Scythians, where their diviners failed
in the promised effect, they were laid, bound hand and foot, upon carts
loaded with firs and bavins, and drawn by oxen, on which they were
burned to death.—[Herodotus, iv. 69.]—Such as only meddle with things
subject to the conduct of human capacity, are excusable in doing the
best they can: but those other fellows that come to delude us with
assurances of an extraordinary faculty, beyond our understanding, ought
they not to be punished, when they do not make good the effect of their
promise, and for the temerity of their imposture?
They have continual war with the nations that live further within the
mainland, beyond their mountains, to which they go naked, and without
other arms than their bows and wooden swords, fashioned at one end like
the head of our javelins. The obstinacy of their battles is wonderful,
and they never end without great effusion of blood: for as to running
away, they know not what it is. Every one for a trophy brings home the
head of an enemy he has killed, which he fixes over the door of his
house. After having a long time treated their prisoners very well, and
given them all the regales they can think of, he to whom the prisoner
belongs, invites a great assembly of his friends. They being come, he
ties a rope to one of the arms of the prisoner, of which, at a distance,
out of his reach, he holds the one end himself, and gives to the friend
he loves best the other arm to hold after the same manner; which being.
done, they two, in the presence of all the assembly, despatch him with
their swords. After that, they roast him, eat him amongst them, and send
some chops to their absent friends. They do not do this, as some think,
for nourishment, as the Scythians anciently did, but as a representation
of an extreme revenge; as will appear by this: that having observed the
Portuguese, who were in league with their enemies, to inflict another
sort of death upon any of them they took prisoners, which was to set
them up to the girdle in the earth, to shoot at the remaining part till
it was stuck full of arrows, and then to hang them, they thought those
people of the other world (as being men who had sown the knowledge of a
great many vices amongst their neighbours, and who were much greater
masters in all sorts of mischief than they) did not exercise this sort
of revenge without a meaning, and that it must needs be more painful
than theirs, they began to leave their old way, and to follow this. I am
not sorry that we should here take notice of the barbarous horror of so
cruel an action, but that, seeing so clearly into their faults, we
should be so blind to our own. I conceive there is more barbarity in
eating a man alive, than when he is dead; in tearing a body limb from
limb by racks and torments, that is yet in perfect sense; in roasting it
by degrees; in causing it to be bitten and worried by dogs and swine (as
we have not only read, but lately seen, not amongst inveterate and
mortal enemies, but among neighbours and fellow-citizens, and, which is
worse, under colour of piety and religion), than to roast and eat him
after he is dead.
Chrysippus and Zeno, the two heads of the Stoic sect, were of opinion
that there was no hurt in making use of our dead carcasses, in what way
soever for our necessity, and in feeding upon them too;—[Diogenes
Laertius, vii. 188.]—as our own ancestors, who being besieged by Caesar
in the city Alexia, resolved to sustain the famine of the siege with the
bodies of their old men, women, and other persons who were incapable of
bearing arms.
"Vascones, ut fama est, alimentis talibus usi
Produxere animas."
["'Tis said the Gascons with such meats appeased their hunger."
—Juvenal, Sat., xv. 93.]
And the physicians make no bones of employing it to all sorts of use,
either to apply it outwardly; or to give it inwardly for the health of
the patient. But there never was any opinion so irregular, as to excuse
treachery, disloyalty, tyranny, and cruelty, which are our familiar
vices. We may then call these people barbarous, in respect to the rules
of reason: but not in respect to ourselves, who in all sorts of
barbarity exceed them. Their wars are throughout noble and generous, and
carry as much excuse and fair pretence, as that human malady is capable
of; having with them no other foundation than the sole jealousy of
valour. Their disputes are not for the conquest of new lands, for these
they already possess are so fruitful by nature, as to supply them
without labour or concern, with all things necessary, in such abundance
that they have no need to enlarge their borders. And they are, moreover,
happy in this, that they only covet so much as their natural necessities
require: all beyond that is superfluous to them: men of the same age
call one another generally brothers, those who are younger, children;
and the old men are fathers to all. These leave to their heirs in common
the full possession of goods, without any manner of division, or other
title than what nature bestows upon her creatures, in bringing them into
the world. If their neighbours pass over the mountains to assault them,
and obtain a victory, all the victors gain by it is glory only, and the
advantage of having proved themselves the better in valour and virtue:
for they never meddle with the goods of the conquered, but presently
return into their own country, where they have no want of anything
necessary, nor of this greatest of all goods, to know happily how to
enjoy their condition and to be content. And those in turn do the same;
they demand of their prisoners no other ransom, than acknowledgment that
they are overcome: but there is not one found in an age, who will not
rather choose to die than make such a confession, or either by word or
look recede from the entire grandeur of an invincible courage. There is
not a man amongst them who had not rather be killed and eaten, than so
much as to open his mouth to entreat he may not. They use them with all
liberality and freedom, to the end their lives may be so much the dearer
to them; but frequently entertain them with menaces of their approaching
death, of the torments they are to suffer, of the preparations making in
order to it, of the mangling their limbs, and of the feast that is to be
made, where their carcass is to be the only dish. All which they do, to
no other end, but only to extort some gentle or submissive word from
them, or to frighten them so as to make them run away, to obtain this
advantage that they were terrified, and that their constancy was shaken;
and indeed, if rightly taken, it is in this point only that a true
victory consists:
"Victoria nulla est,
Quam quae confessor animo quoque subjugat hostes."
["No victory is complete, which the conquered do not admit to be
so.—"Claudius, De Sexto Consulatu Honorii, v. 248.]
The Hungarians, a very warlike people, never pretend further than to
reduce the enemy to their discretion; for having forced this confession
from them, they let them go without injury or ransom, excepting, at the
most, to make them engage their word never to bear arms against them
again. We have sufficient advantages over our enemies that are borrowed
and not truly our own; it is the quality of a porter, and no effect of
virtue, to have stronger arms and legs; it is a dead and corporeal
quality to set in array; 'tis a turn of fortune to make our enemy
stumble, or to dazzle him with the light of the sun; 'tis a trick of
science and art, and that may happen in a mean base fellow, to be a good
fencer. The estimate and value of a man consist in the heart and in the
will: there his true honour lies. Valour is stability, not of legs and
arms, but of the courage and the soul; it does not lie in the goodness
of our horse or our arms but in our own. He that falls obstinate in his
courage—
"Si succiderit, de genu pugnat"
["If his legs fail him, he fights on his knees."
—Seneca, De Providentia, c. 2.]
—he who, for any danger of imminent death, abates nothing of his
assurance; who, dying, yet darts at his enemy a fierce and disdainful
look, is overcome not by us, but by fortune; he is killed, not
conquered; the most valiant are sometimes the most unfortunate. There
are defeats more triumphant than victories. Never could those four
sister victories, the fairest the sun ever be held, of Salamis, Plataea,
Mycale, and Sicily, venture to oppose all their united glories, to the
single glory of the discomfiture of King Leonidas and his men, at the
pass of Thermopylae. Who ever ran with a more glorious desire and
greater ambition, to the winning, than Captain Iscolas to the certain
loss of a battle?—[Diodorus Siculus, xv. 64.]—Who could have found out a
more subtle invention to secure his safety, than he did to assure his
destruction? He was set to defend a certain pass of Peloponnesus against
the Arcadians, which, considering the nature of the place and the
inequality of forces, finding it utterly impossible for him to do, and
seeing that all who were presented to the enemy, must certainly be left
upon the place; and on the other side, reputing it unworthy of his own
virtue and magnanimity and of the Lacedaemonian name to fail in any part
of his duty, he chose a mean betwixt these two extremes after this
manner; the youngest and most active of his men, he preserved for the
service and defence of their country, and sent them back; and with the
rest, whose loss would be of less consideration, he resolved to make
good the pass, and with the death of them, to make the enemy buy their
entry as dear as possibly he could; as it fell out, for being presently
environed on all sides by the Arcadians, after having made a great
slaughter of the enemy, he and his were all cut in pieces. Is there any
trophy dedicated to the conquerors which was not much more due to these
who were overcome? The part that true conquering is to play, lies in the
encounter, not in the coming off; and the honour of valour consists in
fighting, not in subduing.
But to return to my story: these prisoners are so far from
discovering the least weakness, for all the terrors that can be
represented to them, that, on the contrary, during the two or three
months they are kept, they always appear with a cheerful countenance;
importune their masters to make haste to bring them to the test, defy,
rail at them, and reproach them with cowardice, and the number of
battles they have lost against those of their country. I have a song
made by one of these prisoners, wherein he bids them "come all, and dine
upon him, and welcome, for they shall withal eat their own fathers and
grandfathers, whose flesh has served to feed and nourish him. These
muscles," says he, "this flesh and these veins, are your own: poor silly
souls as you are, you little think that the substance of your ancestors'
limbs is here yet; notice what you eat, and you will find in it the
taste of your own flesh:" in which song there is to be observed an
invention that nothing relishes of the barbarian. Those that paint these
people dying after this manner, represent the prisoner spitting in the
faces of his executioners and making wry mouths at them. And 'tis most
certain, that to the very last gasp, they never cease to brave and defy
them both in word and gesture. In plain truth, these men are very savage
in comparison of us; of necessity, they must either be absolutely so or
else we are savages; for there is a vast difference betwixt their
manners and ours.
The men there have several wives, and so much the greater number, by
how much they have the greater reputation for valour. And it is one very
remarkable feature in their marriages, that the same jealousy our wives
have to hinder and divert us from the friendship and familiarity of
other women, those employ to promote their husbands' desires, and to
procure them many spouses; for being above all things solicitous of
their husbands' honour, 'tis their chiefest care to seek out, and to
bring in the most companions they can, forasmuch as it is a testimony of
the husband's virtue. Most of our ladies will cry out, that 'tis
monstrous; whereas in truth it is not so, but a truly matrimonial
virtue, and of the highest form. In the Bible, Sarah, with Leah and
Rachel, the two wives of Jacob, gave the most beautiful of their
handmaids to their husbands; Livia preferred the passions of Augustus to
her own interest; —[Suetonius, Life of Augustus, c. 71.]—and the wife of
King Deiotarus, Stratonice, did not only give up a fair young maid that
served her to her husband's embraces, but moreover carefully brought up
the children he had by her, and assisted them in the succession to their
father's crown.
And that it may not be supposed, that all this is done by a simple
and servile obligation to their common practice, or by any authoritative
impression of their ancient custom, without judgment or reasoning, and
from having a soul so stupid that it cannot contrive what else to do, I
must here give you some touches of their sufficiency in point of
understanding. Besides what I repeated to you before, which was one of
their songs of war, I have another, a love-song, that begins thus:
"Stay, adder, stay, that by thy pattern my sister may draw the
fashion and work of a rich ribbon, that I may present to my beloved,
by which means thy beauty and the excellent order of thy scales
shall for ever be preferred before all other serpents."
Wherein the first couplet, "Stay, adder," &c., makes the burden of
the song. Now I have conversed enough with poetry to judge thus much
that not only there is nothing barbarous in this invention, but,
moreover, that it is perfectly Anacreontic. To which it may be added,
that their language is soft, of a pleasing accent, and something
bordering upon the Greek termination.
Three of these people, not foreseeing how dear their knowledge of the
corruptions of this part of the world will one day cost their happiness
and repose, and that the effect of this commerce will be their ruin, as
I presuppose it is in a very fair way (miserable men to suffer
themselves to be deluded with desire of novelty and to have left the
serenity of their own heaven to come so far to gaze at ours!), were at
Rouen at the time that the late King Charles IX. was there. The king
himself talked to them a good while, and they were made to see our
fashions, our pomp, and the form of a great city. After which, some one
asked their opinion, and would know of them, what of all the things they
had seen, they found most to be admired? To which they made answer,
three things, of which I have forgotten the third, and am troubled at
it, but two I yet remember. They said, that in the first place they
thought it very strange that so many tall men, wearing beards, strong,
and well armed, who were about the king ('tis like they meant the Swiss
of the guard), should submit to obey a child, and that they did not
rather choose out one amongst themselves to command. Secondly (they have
a way of speaking in their language to call men the half of one
another), that they had observed that there were amongst us men full and
crammed with all manner of commodities, whilst, in the meantime, their
halves were begging at their doors, lean and half-starved with hunger
and poverty; and they thought it strange that these necessitous halves
were able to suffer so great an inequality and injustice, and that they
did not take the others by the throats, or set fire to their houses.
I talked to one of them a great while together, but I had so ill an
interpreter, and one who was so perplexed by his own ignorance to
apprehend my meaning, that I could get nothing out of him of any moment:
Asking him what advantage he reaped from the superiority he had amongst
his own people (for he was a captain, and our mariners called him king),
he told me, to march at the head of them to war. Demanding of him
further how many men he had to follow him, he showed me a space of
ground, to signify as many as could march in such a compass, which might
be four or five thousand men; and putting the question to him whether or
no his authority expired with the war, he told me this remained: that
when he went to visit the villages of his dependence, they planed him
paths through the thick of their woods, by which he might pass at his
ease. All this does not sound very ill, and the last was not at all
amiss, for they wear no breeches.
CHAPTER XXXI——THAT A MAN IS SOBERLY TO JUDGE OF THE DIVINE
ORDINANCES
The true field and subject of imposture are things unknown, forasmuch
as, in the first place, their very strangeness lends them credit, and
moreover, by not being subjected to our ordinary reasons, they deprive
us of the means to question and dispute them: For which reason, says
Plato, —[In Critias.]—it is much more easy to satisfy the hearers, when
speaking of the nature of the gods than of the nature of men, because
the ignorance of the auditory affords a fair and large career and all
manner of liberty in the handling of abstruse things. Thence it comes to
pass, that nothing is so firmly believed, as what we least know; nor any
people so confident, as those who entertain us with fables, such as your
alchemists, judicial astrologers, fortune-tellers, and physicians,
"Id genus omne."
["All that sort of people."—Horace, Sat., i. 2, 2.]
To which I would willingly, if I durst, join a pack of people that
take upon them to interpret and control the designs of God Himself,
pretending to find out the cause of every accident, and to pry into the
secrets of the divine will, there to discover the incomprehensible
motive, of His works; and although the variety, and the continual
discordance of events, throw them from corner to corner, and toss them
from east to west, yet do they still persist in their vain inquisition,
and with the same pencil to paint black and white.
In a nation of the Indies, there is this commendable custom, that
when anything befalls them amiss in any encounter or battle, they
publicly ask pardon of the sun, who is their god, as having committed an
unjust action, always imputing their good or evil fortune to the divine
justice, and to that submitting their own judgment and reason. 'Tis
enough for a Christian to believe that all things come from God, to
receive them with acknowledgment of His divine and inscrutable wisdom,
and also thankfully to accept and receive them, with what face soever
they may present themselves. But I do not approve of what I see in use,
that is, to seek to affirm and support our religion by the prosperity of
our enterprises. Our belief has other foundation enough, without going
about to authorise it by events: for the people being accustomed to such
plausible arguments as these and so proper to their taste, it is to be
feared, lest when they fail of success they should also stagger in their
faith: as in the war wherein we are now engaged upon the account of
religion, those who had the better in the business of
Rochelabeille,—[May 1569.]—making great brags of that success as an
infallible approbation of their cause, when they came afterwards to
excuse their misfortunes of Moncontour and Jarnac, by saying they were
fatherly scourges and corrections that they had not a people wholly at
their mercy, they make it manifestly enough appear, what it is to take
two sorts of grist out of the same sack, and with the same mouth to blow
hot and cold. It were better to possess the vulgar with the solid and
real foundations of truth. 'Twas a fine naval battle that was gained
under the command of Don John of Austria a few months since—[That of
Lepanto, October 7, 1571.]—against the Turks; but it has also pleased
God at other times to let us see as great victories at our own expense.
In fine, 'tis a hard matter to reduce divine things to our balance,
without waste and losing a great deal of the weight. And who would take
upon him to give a reason that Arius and his Pope Leo, the principal
heads of the Arian heresy, should die, at several times, of so like and
strange deaths (for being withdrawn from the disputation by a griping in
the bowels, they both of them suddenly gave up the ghost upon the
stool), and would aggravate this divine vengeance by the circumstances
of the place, might as well add the death of Heliogabalus, who was also
slain in a house of office. And, indeed, Irenaeus was involved in the
same fortune. God, being pleased to show us, that the good have
something else to hope for and the wicked something else to fear, than
the fortunes or misfortunes of this world, manages and applies these
according to His own occult will and pleasure, and deprives us of the
means foolishly to make thereof our own profit. And those people abuse
themselves who will pretend to dive into these mysteries by the strength
of human reason. They never give one hit that they do not receive two
for it; of which St. Augustine makes out a great proof upon his
adversaries. 'Tis a conflict that is more decided by strength of memory
than by the force of reason. We are to content ourselves with the light
it pleases the sun to communicate to us, by virtue of his rays; and who
will lift up his eyes to take in a greater, let him not think it
strange, if for the reward of his presumption, he there lose his sight.
"Quis hominum potest scire consilium Dei?
Aut quis poterit cogitare quid velit Dominus?"
["Who of men can know the counsel of God? or who can think what the
will of the Lord is."—Book of Wisdom, ix. 13.]
CHAPTER XXXII——THAT WE ARE TO AVOID PLEASURES, EVEN AT THE EXPENSE
OF LIFE
I had long ago observed most of the opinions of the ancients to
concur in this, that it is high time to die when there is more ill than
good in living, and that to preserve life to our own torment and
inconvenience is contrary to the very rules of nature, as these old laws
instruct us.
["Either tranquil life, or happy death. It is well to die when life
is wearisome. It is better to die than to live miserable."
—Stobaeus, Serm. xx.]
But to push this contempt of death so far as to employ it to the
removing our thoughts from the honours, riches, dignities, and other
favours and goods, as we call them, of fortune, as if reason were not
sufficient to persuade us to avoid them, without adding this new
injunction, I had never seen it either commanded or practised, till this
passage of Seneca fell into my hands; who advising Lucilius, a man of
great power and authority about the emperor, to alter his voluptuous and
magnificent way of living, and to retire himself from this worldly
vanity and ambition, to some solitary, quiet, and philosophical life,
and the other alleging some difficulties: "I am of opinion," says he,
"either that thou leave that life of thine, or life itself; I would,
indeed, advise thee to the gentle way, and to untie, rather than to
break, the knot thou hast indiscreetly knit, provided, that if it be not
otherwise to be untied, thou resolutely break it. There is no man so
great a coward, that had not rather once fall than to be always
falling." I should have found this counsel conformable enough to the
Stoical roughness: but it appears the more strange, for being borrowed
from Epicurus, who writes the same thing upon the like occasion to
Idomeneus. And I think I have observed something like it, but with
Christian moderation, amongst our own people.
St. Hilary, Bishop of Poictiers, that famous enemy of the Arian
heresy, being in Syria, had intelligence thither sent him, that Abra,
his only daughter, whom he left at home under the eye and tuition of her
mother, was sought in marriage by the greatest noblemen of the country,
as being a virgin virtuously brought up, fair, rich, and in the flower
of her age; whereupon he wrote to her (as appears upon record), that she
should remove her affection from all the pleasures and advantages
proposed to her; for that he had in his travels found out a much greater
and more worthy fortune for her, a husband of much greater power and
magnificence, who would present her with robes and jewels of inestimable
value; wherein his design was to dispossess her of the appetite and use
of worldly delights, to join her wholly to God; but the nearest and most
certain way to this, being, as he conceived, the death of his daughter;
he never ceased, by vows, prayers, and orisons, to beg of the Almighty,
that He would please to call her out of this world, and to take her to
Himself; as accordingly it came to pass; for soon after his return, she
died, at which he expressed a singular joy. This seems to outdo the
other, forasmuch as he applies himself to this means at the outset,
which they only take subsidiarily; and, besides, it was towards his only
daughter. But I will not omit the latter end of this story, though it be
for my purpose; St. Hilary's wife, having understood from him how the
death of their daughter was brought about by his desire and design, and
how much happier she was to be removed out of this world than to have
stayed in it, conceived so vivid an apprehension of the eternal and
heavenly beatitude, that she begged of her husband, with the extremest
importunity, to do as much for her; and God, at their joint request,
shortly after calling her to Him, it was a death embraced with singular
and mutual content.
CHAPTER XXXIII——THAT FORTUNE IS OFTEN-TIMES OBSERVED TO ACT BY THE
RULE OF REASON
The inconstancy and various motions of Fortune
[The term Fortune, so often employed by Montaigne, and in passages
where he might have used Providence, was censured by the doctors who
examined his Essays when he was at Rome in 1581. See his Travels,
i. 35 and 76.]
may reasonably make us expect she should present us with all sorts of
faces. Can there be a more express act of justice than this? The Duc de
Valentinois,—[Caesar Borgia.]—having resolved to poison Adrian, Cardinal
of Corneto, with whom Pope Alexander VI., his father and himself, were
to sup in the Vatican, he sent before a bottle of poisoned wine, and
withal, strict order to the butler to keep it very safe. The Pope being
come before his son, and calling for drink, the butler supposing this
wine had not been so strictly recommended to his care, but only upon the
account of its excellency, presented it forthwith to the Pope, and the
duke himself coming in presently after, and being confident they had not
meddled with his bottle, took also his cup; so that the father died
immediately upon the spot—[Other historians assign the Pope several days
of misery prior to death. D.W.]—, and the son, after having been long
tormented with sickness, was reserved to another and a worse fortune.
Sometimes she seems to play upon us, just in the nick of an affair;
Monsieur d'Estrees, at that time ensign to Monsieur de Vendome, and
Monsieur de Licques, lieutenant in the company of the Duc d'Ascot, being
both pretenders to the Sieur de Fougueselles' sister, though of several
parties (as it oft falls out amongst frontier neighbours), the Sieur de
Licques carried her; but on the same day he was married, and which was
worse, before he went to bed to his wife, the bridegroom having a mind
to break a lance in honour of his new bride, went out to skirmish near
St. Omer, where the Sieur d'Estrees proving the stronger, took him
prisoner, and the more to illustrate his victory, the lady was fain—
"Conjugis ante coacta novi dimittere collum,
Quam veniens una atque altera rursus hyems
Noctibus in longis avidum saturasset amorem,"
["Compelled to abstain from embracing her new spouse in her arms
before two winters pass in succession, during their long nights had
satiated her eager love."—Catullus, lxviii. 81.]
—to request him of courtesy, to deliver up his prisoner to her, as he
accordingly did, the gentlemen of France never denying anything to
ladies.
Does she not seem to be an artist here? Constantine, son of Helena,
founded the empire of Constantinople, and so many ages after,
Constantine, the son of Helen, put an end to it. Sometimes she is
pleased to emulate our miracles we are told, that King Clovis besieging
Angouleme, the walls fell down of themselves by divine favour and
Bouchet has it from some author, that King Robert having sat down before
a city, and being stolen away from the siege to go keep the feast of St.
Aignan at Orleans, as he was in devotion at a certain part of the Mass,
the walls of the beleaguered city, without any manner of violence, fell
down with a sudden ruin. But she did quite contrary in our Milan wars;
for, le Capitaine Rense laying siege for us to the city Arona, and
having carried a mine under a great part of the wall, the mine being
sprung, the wall was lifted from its base, but dropped down again
nevertheless, whole and entire, and so exactly upon its foundation, that
the besieged suffered no inconvenience by that attempt.
Sometimes she plays the physician. Jason of Pheres being given over
by the physicians, by reason of an imposthume in his breast, having a
mind to rid himself of his pain, by death at least, threw himself in a
battle desperately into the thickest of the enemy, where he was so
fortunately wounded quite through the body, that the imposthume broke,
and he was perfectly cured. Did she not also excel the painter
Protogenes in his art? who having finished the picture of a dog quite
tired and out of breath, in all the other parts excellently well to his
own liking, but not being able to express, as he would, the slaver and
foam that should come out of its mouth, vexed and angry at his work, he
took his sponge, which by cleaning his pencils had imbibed several sorts
of colours, and threw it in a rage against the picture, with an intent
utterly to deface it; when fortune guiding the sponge to hit just upon
the mouth of the dog, it there performed what all his art was not able
to do. Does she not sometimes direct our counsels and correct them?
Isabel, Queen of England, having to sail from Zealand into her own
kingdom,—[in 1326]— with an army, in favour of her son against her
husband, had been lost, had she come into the port she intended, being
there laid wait for by the enemy; but fortune, against her will, threw
her into another haven, where she landed in safety. And that man of old
who, throwing a stone at a dog, hit and killed his mother-in-law, had he
not reason to pronounce this verse:
["Fortune has more judgement than we."—Menander]
Icetes had contracted with two soldiers to kill Timoleon at Adrana in
Sicily.—[Plutarch, Life of Timoleon, c. 7.]—They took their time to do
it when he was assisting at a sacrifice, and thrusting into the crowd,
as they were making signs to one another, that now was a fit time to do
their business, in steps a third, who, with a sword takes one of them
full drive over the pate, lays him dead upon the place and runs away,
which the others see, and concluding himself discovered and lost, runs
to the altar and begs for mercy, promising to discover the whole truth,
which as he was doing, and laying open the full conspiracy, behold the
third man, who being apprehended, was, as a murderer, thrust and hauled
by the people through the press, towards Timoleon, and the other most
eminent persons of the assembly, before whom being brought, he cries out
for pardon, pleading that he had justly slain his father's murderer;
which he, also, proving upon the spot, by sufficient witnesses, whom his
good fortune very opportunely supplied him withal, that his father was
really killed in the city of Leontini, by that very man on whom he had
taken his revenge, he was presently awarded ten Attic minae, for having
had the good fortune, by designing to revenge the death of his father,
to preserve the life of the common father of Sicily. Fortune, truly, in
her conduct surpasses all the rules of human prudence.
But to conclude: is there not a direct application of her favour,
bounty, and piety manifestly discovered in this action? Ignatius the
father and Ignatius the son being proscribed by the triumvirs of Rome,
resolved upon this generous act of mutual kindness, to fall by the hands
of one another, and by that means to frustrate and defeat the cruelty of
the tyrants; and accordingly with their swords drawn, ran full drive
upon one another, where fortune so guided the points, that they made two
equally mortal wounds, affording withal so much honour to so brave a
friendship, as to leave them just strength enough to draw out their
bloody swords, that they might have liberty to embrace one another in
this dying condition, with so close and hearty an embrace, that the
executioner cut off both their heads at once, leaving the bodies still
fast linked together in this noble bond, and their wounds joined mouth
to mouth, affectionately sucking in the last blood and remainder of the
lives of each other.
CHAPTER XXXIV——OF ONE DEFECT IN OUR GOVERNMENT
My late father, a man that had no other advantages than experience
and his own natural parts, was nevertheless of a very clear judgment,
formerly told me that he once had thoughts of endeavouring to introduce
this practice; that there might be in every city a certain place
assigned to which such as stood in need of anything might repair, and
have their business entered by an officer appointed for that purpose. As
for example: I want a chapman to buy my pearls; I want one that has
pearls to sell; such a one wants company to go to Paris; such a one
seeks a servant of such a quality; such a one a master; such a one such
an artificer; some inquiring for one thing, some for another, every one
according to what he wants. And doubtless, these mutual advertisements
would be of no contemptible advantage to the public correspondence and
intelligence: for there are evermore conditions that hunt after one
another, and for want of knowing one another's occasions leave men in
very great necessity.
I have heard, to the great shame of the age we live in, that in our
very sight two most excellent men for learning died so poor that they
had scarce bread to put in their mouths: Lilius Gregorius Giraldus in
Italy and Sebastianus Castalio in Germany: and I believe there are a
thousand men would have invited them into their families, with very
advantageous conditions, or have relieved them where they were, had they
known their wants. The world is not so generally corrupted, but that I
know a man that would heartily wish the estate his ancestors have left
him might be employed, so long as it shall please fortune to give him
leave to enjoy it, to secure rare and remarkable persons of any kind,
whom misfortune sometimes persecutes to the last degree, from the
dangers of necessity; and at least place them in such a condition that
they must be very hard to please, if they are not contented.
My father in his domestic economy had this rule (which I know how to
commend, but by no means to imitate), namely, that besides the day-book
or memorial of household affairs, where the small accounts, payments,
and disbursements, which do not require a secretary's hand, were
entered, and which a steward always had in custody, he ordered him whom
he employed to write for him, to keep a journal, and in it to set down
all the remarkable occurrences, and daily memorials of the history of
his house: very pleasant to look over, when time begins to wear things
out of memory, and very useful sometimes to put us out of doubt when
such a thing was begun, when ended; what visitors came, and when they
went; our travels, absences, marriages, and deaths; the reception of
good or ill news; the change of principal servants, and the like. An
ancient custom, which I think it would not be amiss for every one to
revive in his own house; and I find I did very foolishly in neglecting
it.
CHAPTER XXXV——OF THE CUSTOM OF WEARING CLOTHES
Whatever I shall say upon this subject, I am of necessity to invade
some of the bounds of custom, so careful has she been to shut up all the
avenues. I was disputing with myself in this shivering season, whether
the fashion of going naked in those nations lately discovered is imposed
upon them by the hot temperature of the air, as we say of the Indians
and Moors, or whether it be the original fashion of mankind. Men of
understanding, forasmuch as all things under the sun, as the Holy Writ
declares, are subject to the same laws, were wont in such considerations
as these, where we are to distinguish the natural laws from those which
have been imposed by man's invention, to have recourse to the general
polity of the world, where there can be nothing counterfeit. Now, all
other creatures being sufficiently furnished with all things necessary
for the support of their being—[Montaigne's expression is, "with needle
and thread."—W.C.H.]—it is not to be imagined that we only are brought
into the world in a defective and indigent condition, and in such a
state as cannot subsist without external aid. Therefore it is that I
believe, that as plants, trees, and animals, and all things that have
life, are seen to be by nature sufficiently clothed and covered, to
defend them from the injuries of weather:
"Proptereaque fere res omnes ant corio sunt,
Aut seta, ant conchis, ant callo, ant cortice tectae,"
["And that for this reason nearly all things are clothed with skin,
or hair, or shells, or bark, or some such thing."
—Lucretius, iv. 936.]
so were we: but as those who by artificial light put out that of day,
so we by borrowed forms and fashions have destroyed our own. And 'tis
plain enough to be seen, that 'tis custom only which renders that
impossible that otherwise is nothing so; for of those nations who have
no manner of knowledge of clothing, some are situated under the same
temperature that we are, and some in much colder climates. And besides,
our most tender parts are always exposed to the air, as the eyes, mouth,
nose, and ears; and our country labourers, like our ancestors in former
times, go with their breasts and bellies open. Had we been born with a
necessity upon us of wearing petticoats and breeches, there is no doubt
but nature would have fortified those parts she intended should be
exposed to the fury of the seasons with a thicker skin, as she has done
the finger-ends and the soles of the feet. And why should this seem hard
to believe? I observe much greater distance betwixt my habit and that of
one of our country boors, than betwixt his and that of a man who has no
other covering but his skin. How many men, especially in Turkey, go
naked upon the account of devotion? Some one asked a beggar, whom he saw
in his shirt in the depth of winter, as brisk and frolic as he who goes
muffled up to the ears in furs, how he was able to endure to go so?
"Why, sir," he answered, "you go with your face bare: I am all face."
The Italians have a story of the Duke of Florence's fool, whom his
master asking how, being so thinly clad, he was able to support the
cold, when he himself, warmly wrapped up as he was, was hardly able to
do it? "Why," replied the fool, "use my receipt to put on all your
clothes you have at once, and you'll feel no more cold than I." King
Massinissa, to an extreme old age, could never be prevailed upon to go
with his head covered, how cold, stormy, or rainy soever the weather
might be; which also is reported of the Emperor Severus. Herodotus tells
us, that in the battles fought betwixt the Egyptians and the Persians,
it was observed both by himself and by others, that of those who were
left dead upon the field, the heads of the Egyptians were without
comparison harder than those of the Persians, by reason that the last
had gone with their heads always covered from their infancy, first with
biggins, and then with turbans, and the others always shaved and bare.
King Agesilaus continued to a decrepit age to wear always the same
clothes in winter that he did in summer. Caesar, says Suetonius, marched
always at the head of his army, for the most part on foot, with his head
bare, whether it was rain or sunshine, and as much is said of Hannibal:
"Tum vertice nudo,
Excipere insanos imbres, coelique ruinam."
["Bareheaded he marched in snow, exposed to pouring rain and the
utmost rigour of the weather."—Silius Italicus, i. 250.]
A Venetian who has long lived in Pegu, and has lately returned
thence, writes that the men and women of that kingdom, though they cover
all their other parts, go always barefoot and ride so too; and Plato
very earnestly advises for the health of the whole body, to give the
head and the feet no other clothing than what nature has bestowed. He
whom the Poles have elected for their king,—[Stephen Bathory]—since ours
came thence, who is, indeed, one of the greatest princes of this age,
never wears any gloves, and in winter or whatever weather can come,
never wears other cap abroad than that he wears at home. Whereas I
cannot endure to go unbuttoned or untied; my neighbouring labourers
would think themselves in chains, if they were so braced. Varro is of
opinion, that when it was ordained we should be bare in the presence of
the gods and before the magistrate, it was so ordered rather upon the
score of health, and to inure us to the injuries of weather, than upon
the account of reverence; and since we are now talking of cold, and
Frenchmen used to wear variety of colours (not I myself, for I seldom
wear other than black or white, in imitation of my father), let us add
another story out of Le Capitaine Martin du Bellay, who affirms, that in
the march to Luxembourg he saw so great frost, that the munition-wine
was cut with hatchets and wedges, and delivered out to the soldiers by
weight, and that they carried it away in baskets: and Ovid,
"Nudaque consistunt, formam servantia testae,
Vina; nec hausta meri, sed data frusta, bibunt."
["The wine when out of the cask retains the form of the cask;
and is given out not in cups, but in bits."
—Ovid, Trist., iii. 10, 23.]
At the mouth of Lake Maeotis the frosts are so very sharp, that in
the very same place where Mithridates' lieutenant had fought the enemy
dryfoot and given them a notable defeat, the summer following he
obtained over them a naval victory. The Romans fought at a very great
disadvantage, in the engagement they had with the Carthaginians near
Piacenza, by reason that they went to the charge with their blood
congealed and their limbs numbed with cold, whereas Hannibal had caused
great fires to be dispersed quite through his camp to warm his soldiers,
and oil to be distributed amongst them, to the end that anointing
themselves, they might render their nerves more supple and active, and
fortify the pores against the violence of the air and freezing wind,
which raged in that season.
The retreat the Greeks made from Babylon into their own country is
famous for the difficulties and calamities they had to overcome; of
which this was one, that being encountered in the mountains of Armenia
with a horrible storm of snow, they lost all knowledge of the country
and of the ways, and being driven up, were a day and a night without
eating or drinking; most of their cattle died, many of themselves were
starved to death, several struck blind with the force of the hail and
the glare of the snow, many of them maimed in their fingers and toes,
and many stiff and motionless with the extremity of the cold, who had
yet their understanding entire.
Alexander saw a nation, where they bury their fruit-trees in winter
to protect them from being destroyed by the frost, and we also may see
the same.
But, so far as clothes go, the King of Mexico changed four times a
day his apparel, and never put it on again, employing that he left off
in his continual liberalities and rewards; and neither pot, dish, nor
other utensil of his kitchen or table was ever served twice.
CHAPTER XXXVI——OF CATO THE YOUNGER
["I am not possessed with this common errour, to judge of others
according to what I am my selfe. I am easie to beleeve things
differing from my selfe. Though I be engaged to one forme, I do not
tie the world unto it, as every man doth. And I beleeve and
conceive a thousand manners of life, contrary to the common sorte."
—Florio, ed. 1613, p. 113.]
I am not guilty of the common error of judging another by myself. I
easily believe that in another's humour which is contrary to my own; and
though I find myself engaged to one certain form, I do not oblige others
to it, as many do; but believe and apprehend a thousand ways of living;
and, contrary to most men, more easily admit of difference than
uniformity amongst us. I as frankly as any one would have me, discharge
a man from my humours and principles, and consider him according to his
own particular model. Though I am not continent myself, I nevertheless
sincerely approve the continence of the Feuillans and Capuchins, and
highly commend their way of living. I insinuate myself by imagination
into their place, and love and honour them the more for being other than
I am. I very much desire that we may be judged every man by himself, and
would not be drawn into the consequence of common examples. My own
weakness nothing alters the esteem I ought to have for the force and
vigour of those who deserve it:
"Sunt qui nihil suadent, quam quod se imitari posse confidunt."
["There are who persuade nothing but what they believe they can
imitate themselves."—Cicero, De Orator., c. 7.]
Crawling upon the slime of the earth, I do not for all that cease to
observe up in the clouds the inimitable height of some heroic souls.
'Tis a great deal for me to have my judgment regular and just, if the
effects cannot be so, and to maintain this sovereign part, at least,
free from corruption; 'tis something to have my will right and good
where my legs fail me. This age wherein we live, in our part of the
world at least, is grown so stupid, that not only the exercise, but the
very imagination of virtue is defective, and seems to be no other but
college jargon:
"Virtutem verba putant, ut
Lucum ligna:"
["They think words virtue, as they think mere wood a sacred grove."
—Horace, Ep., i. 6, 31.]
"Quam vereri deberent, etiam si percipere non possent."
["Which they ought to reverence, though they cannot comprehend."
—Cicero, Tusc. Quas., v. 2.]
'Tis a gewgaw to hang in a cabinet or at the end of the tongue, as on
the tip of the ear, for ornament only. There are no longer virtuous
actions extant; those actions that carry a show of virtue have yet
nothing of its essence; by reason that profit, glory, fear, custom, and
other suchlike foreign causes, put us on the way to produce them. Our
justice also, valour, courtesy, may be called so too, in respect to
others and according to the face they appear with to the public; but in
the doer it can by no means be virtue, because there is another end
proposed, another moving cause. Now virtue owns nothing to be hers, but
what is done by herself and for herself alone.
In that great battle of Plataea, that the Greeks under the command of
Pausanias gained against Mardonius and the Persians, the conquerors,
according to their custom, coming to divide amongst them the glory of
the exploit, attributed to the Spartan nation the pre-eminence of valour
in the engagement. The Spartans, great judges of virtue, when they came
to determine to what particular man of their nation the honour was due
of having the best behaved himself upon this occasion, found that
Aristodemus had of all others hazarded his person with the greatest
bravery; but did not, however, allow him any prize, by reason that his
virtue had been incited by a desire to clear his reputation from the
reproach of his miscarriage at the business of Thermopylae, and to die
bravely to wipe off that former blemish.
Our judgments are yet sick, and obey the humour of our depraved
manners. I observe most of the wits of these times pretend to ingenuity,
by endeavouring to blemish and darken the glory of the bravest and most
generous actions of former ages, putting one vile interpretation or
another upon them, and forging and supposing vain causes and motives for
the noble things they did: a mighty subtlety indeed! Give me the
greatest and most unblemished action that ever the day beheld, and I
will contrive a hundred plausible drifts and ends to obscure it. God
knows, whoever will stretch them out to the full, what diversity of
images our internal wills suffer under. They do not so maliciously play
the censurers, as they do it ignorantly and rudely in all their
detractions.
The same pains and licence that others take to blemish and bespatter
these illustrious names, I would willingly undergo to lend them a
shoulder to raise them higher. These rare forms, that are culled out by
the consent of the wisest men of all ages, for the world's example, I
should not stick to augment in honour, as far as my invention would
permit, in all the circumstances of favourable interpretation; and we
may well believe that the force of our invention is infinitely short of
their merit. 'Tis the duty of good men to portray virtue as beautiful as
they can, and there would be nothing wrong should our passion a little
transport us in favour of so sacred a form. What these people do, on the
contrary, they either do out of malice, or by the vice of confining
their belief to their own capacity; or, which I am more inclined to
think, for not having their sight strong, clear, and elevated enough to
conceive the splendour of virtue in her native purity: as Plutarch
complains, that in his time some attributed the cause of the younger
Cato's death to his fear of Caesar, at which he seems very angry, and
with good reason; and by this a man may guess how much more he would
have been offended with those who have attributed it to ambition.
Senseless people! He would rather have performed a noble, just, and
generous action, and to have had ignominy for his reward, than for
glory. That man was in truth a pattern that nature chose out to show to
what height human virtue and constancy could arrive.
But I am not capable of handling so rich an argument, and shall
therefore only set five Latin poets together, contending in the praise
of Cato; and, incidentally, for their own too. Now, a well-educated
child will judge the two first, in comparison of the others, a little
flat and languid; the third more vigorous, but overthrown by the
extravagance of his own force; he will then think that there will be
room for one or two gradations of invention to come to the fourth, and,
mounting to the pitch of that, he will lift up his hands in admiration;
coming to the last, the first by some space' (but a space that he will
swear is not to be filled up by any human wit), he will be astounded, he
will not know where he is.
And here is a wonder: we have far more poets than judges and
interpreters of poetry; it is easier to write it than to understand it.
There is, indeed, a certain low and moderate sort of poetry, that a man
may well enough judge by certain rules of art; but the true, supreme,
and divine poesy is above all rules and reason. And whoever discerns the
beauty of it with the most assured and most steady sight, sees no more
than the quick reflection of a flash of lightning: it does not exercise,
but ravishes and overwhelms our judgment. The fury that possesses him
who is able to penetrate into it wounds yet a third man by hearing him
repeat it; like a loadstone that not only attracts the needle, but also
infuses into it the virtue to attract others. And it is more evidently
manifest in our theatres, that the sacred inspiration of the Muses,
having first stirred up the poet to anger, sorrow, hatred, and out of
himself, to whatever they will, does moreover by the poet possess the
actor, and by the actor consecutively all the spectators. So much do our
passions hang and depend upon one another.
Poetry has ever had that power over me from a child to transpierce
and transport me; but this vivid sentiment that is natural to me has
been variously handled by variety of forms, not so much higher or lower
(for they were ever the highest of every kind), as differing in colour.
First, a gay and sprightly fluency; afterwards, a lofty and penetrating
subtlety; and lastly, a mature and constant vigour. Their names will
better express them: Ovid, Lucan, Virgil.
But our poets are beginning their career:
"Sit Cato, dum vivit, sane vel Caesare major,"
["Let Cato, whilst he live, be greater than Caesar."
—Martial, vi. 32]
says one.
"Et invictum, devicta morte, Catonem,"
["And Cato invincible, death being overcome."
—Manilius, Astron., iv. 87.]
says the second. And the third, speaking of the civil wars betwixt
Caesar and Pompey,
"Victrix causa diis placuit, set victa Catoni."
["The victorious cause blessed the gods, the defeated one Cato.
—"Lucan, i. 128.]
And the fourth, upon the praises of Caesar:
"Et cuncta terrarum subacta,
Praeter atrocem animum Catonis."
["And conquered all but the indomitable mind of Cato."
—Horace, Od., ii. 1, 23.]
And the master of the choir, after having set forth all the great
names of the greatest Romans, ends thus:
"His dantem jura Catonem."
["Cato giving laws to all the rest."—AEneid, viii. 670.]
CHAPTER XXXVII——THAT WE LAUGH AND CRY FOR THE SAME THING
When we read in history that Antigonus was very much displeased with
his son for presenting him the head of King Pyrrhus his enemy, but newly
slain fighting against him, and that seeing it, he wept; and that Rene,
Duke of Lorraine, also lamented the death of Charles, Duke of Burgundy,
whom he had himself defeated, and appeared in mourning at his funeral;
and that in the battle of D'Auray (which Count Montfort obtained over
Charles de Blois, his competitor for the duchy of Brittany), the
conqueror meeting the dead body of his enemy, was very much afflicted at
his death, we must not presently cry out:
"E cosi avven, the l'animo ciascuna
Sua passion sotto 'l contrario manto,
Ricopre, con la vista or'chiara, or'bruna."
["And thus it happens that the mind of each veils its passion under
a different appearance, and beneath a smiling visage, gay beneath a
sombre air."—Petrarch.]
When Pompey's head was presented to Caesar, the histories tell us
that he turned away his face, as from a sad and unpleasing object. There
had been so long an intelligence and society betwixt them in the
management of the public affairs, so great a community of fortunes, so
many mutual offices, and so near an alliance, that this countenance of
his ought not to suffer under any misinterpretation, or to be suspected
for either false or counterfeit, as this other seems to believe:
"Tutumque putavit
Jam bonus esse socer; lacrymae non sponte cadentes,
Effudit, gemitusque expressit pectore laeto;"
["And now he thought it safe to play the kind father-in-law,
shedding forced tears, and from a joyful breast discharging sighs
and groans."—Lucan, ix. 1037.]
for though it be true that the greatest part of our actions are no
other than visor and disguise, and that it may sometimes be true that
"Haeredis fletus sub persona rises est,"
["The heir's tears behind the mask are smiles."
—Publius Syrus, apud Gellium, xvii. 14.]
yet, in judging of these accidents, we are to consider how much our
souls are oftentimes agitated with divers passions. And as they say that
in our bodies there is a congregation of divers humours, of which that
is the sovereign which, according to the complexion we are of, is
commonly most predominant in us: so, though the soul have in it divers
motions to give it agitation, yet must there of necessity be one to
overrule all the rest, though not with so necessary and absolute a
dominion but that through the flexibility and inconstancy of the soul,
those of less authority may upon occasion reassume their place and make
a little sally in turn. Thence it is, that we see not only children, who
innocently obey and follow nature, often laugh and cry at the same
thing, but not one of us can boast, what journey soever he may have in
hand that he has the most set his heart upon, but when he comes to part
with his family and friends, he will find something that troubles him
within; and though he refrain his tears yet he puts foot in the stirrup
with a sad and cloudy countenance. And what gentle flame soever may warm
the heart of modest and wellborn virgins, yet are they fain to be forced
from about their mothers' necks to be put to bed to their husbands,
whatever this boon companion is pleased to say:
"Estne novis nuptis odio Venus? anne parentum
Frustrantur falsis gaudia lachrymulis,
Ubertim thalami quasi intra limina fundunt?
Non, ita me divi, vera gemunt, juverint."
["Is Venus really so alarming to the new-made bride, or does she
honestly oppose her parent's rejoicing the tears she so abundantly
sheds on entering the nuptial chamber? No, by the Gods, these are
no true tears."—Catullus, lxvi. 15.]
["Is Venus really so repugnant to newly-married maids? Do they meet
the smiles of parents with feigned tears? They weep copiously
within the very threshold of the nuptial chamber. No, so the gods
help me, they do not truly grieve."—Catullus, lxvi. 15.]—
[A more literal translation. D.W.]
Neither is it strange to lament a person dead whom a man would by no
means should be alive. When I rattle my man, I do it with all the mettle
I have, and load him with no feigned, but downright real curses; but the
heat being over, if he should stand in need of me, I should be very
ready to do him good: for I instantly turn the leaf. When I call him
calf and coxcomb, I do not pretend to entail those titles upon him for
ever; neither do I think I give myself the lie in calling him an honest
fellow presently after. No one quality engrosses us purely and
universally. Were it not the sign of a fool to talk to one's self, there
would hardly be a day or hour wherein I might not be heard to grumble
and mutter to myself and against myself, "Confound the fool!" and yet I
do not think that to be my definition. Who for seeing me one while cold
and presently very fond towards my wife, believes the one or the other
to be counterfeited, is an ass. Nero, taking leave of his mother whom he
was sending to be drowned, was nevertheless sensible of some emotion at
this farewell, and was struck with horror and pity. 'Tis said, that the
light of the sun is not one continuous thing, but that he darts new rays
so thick one upon another that we cannot perceive the intermission:
"Largus enim liquidi fons luminis, aetherius sol,
Irrigat assidue coelum candore recenti,
Suppeditatque novo confestim lumine lumen."
["So the wide fountain of liquid light, the ethereal sun, steadily
fertilises the heavens with new heat, and supplies a continuous
store of fresh light."—Lucretius, v. 282.]
Just so the soul variously and imperceptibly darts out her passions.
Artabanus coming by surprise once upon his nephew Xerxes, chid him
for the sudden alteration of his countenance. He was considering the
immeasurable greatness of his forces passing over the Hellespont for the
Grecian expedition: he was first seized with a palpitation of joy, to
see so many millions of men under his command, and this appeared in the
gaiety of his looks: but his thoughts at the same instant suggesting to
him that of so many lives, within a century at most, there would not be
one left, he presently knit his brows and grew sad, even to tears.
We have resolutely pursued the revenge of an injury received, and
been sensible of a singular contentment for the victory; but we shall
weep notwithstanding. 'Tis not for the victory, though, that we shall
weep: there is nothing altered in that but the soul looks upon things
with another eye and represents them to itself with another kind of
face; for everything has many faces and several aspects.
Relations, old acquaintances, and friendships, possess our
imaginations and make them tender for the time, according to their
condition; but the turn is so quick, that 'tis gone in a moment:
"Nil adeo fieri celeri ratione videtur,
Quam si mens fieri proponit, et inchoat ipsa,
Ocius ergo animus, quam res se perciet ulla,
Ante oculos quorum in promptu natura videtur;"
["Nothing therefore seems to be done in so swift a manner than if
the mind proposes it to be done, and itself begins. It is more
active than anything which we see in nature."—Lucretius, iii. 183.]
and therefore, if we would make one continued thing of all this
succession of passions, we deceive ourselves. When Timoleon laments the
murder he had committed upon so mature and generous deliberation, he
does not lament the liberty restored to his country, he does not lament
the tyrant; but he laments his brother: one part of his duty is
performed; let us give him leave to perform the other.
CHAPTER XXXVIII——OF SOLITUDE
Let us pretermit that long comparison betwixt the active and the
solitary life; and as for the fine sayings with which ambition and
avarice palliate their vices, that we are not born for ourselves but for
the public,—[This is the eulogium passed by Lucan on Cato of Utica, ii.
383.]—let us boldly appeal to those who are in public affairs; let them
lay their hands upon their hearts, and then say whether, on the
contrary, they do not rather aspire to titles and offices and that
tumult of the world to make their private advantage at the public
expense. The corrupt ways by which in this our time they arrive at the
height to which their ambitions aspire, manifestly enough declares that
their ends cannot be very good. Let us tell ambition that it is she
herself who gives us a taste of solitude; for what does she so much
avoid as society? What does she so much seek as elbowroom? A man many do
well or ill everywhere; but if what Bias says be true, that the greatest
part is the worse part, or what the Preacher says: there is not one good
of a thousand:
"Rari quippe boni: numero vix sunt totidem quot
Thebarum portae, vel divitis ostia Nili,"
["Good men forsooth are scarce: there are hardly as many as there
are gates of Thebes or mouths of the rich Nile."
—Juvenal, Sat., xiii. 26.]
the contagion is very dangerous in the crowd. A man must either
imitate the vicious or hate them both are dangerous things, either to
resemble them because they are many or to hate many because they are
unresembling to ourselves. Merchants who go to sea are in the right when
they are cautious that those who embark with them in the same bottom be
neither dissolute blasphemers nor vicious other ways, looking upon such
society as unfortunate. And therefore it was that Bias pleasantly said
to some, who being with him in a dangerous storm implored the assistance
of the gods: "Peace, speak softly," said he, "that they may not know you
are here in my company."—[Diogenes Laertius]—And of more pressing
example, Albuquerque, viceroy in the Indies for Emmanuel, king of
Portugal, in an extreme peril of shipwreck, took a young boy upon his
shoulders, for this only end that, in the society of their common danger
his innocence might serve to protect him, and to recommend him to the
divine favour, that they might get safe to shore. 'Tis not that a wise
man may not live everywhere content, and be alone in the very crowd of a
palace; but if it be left to his own choice, the schoolman will tell you
that he should fly the very sight of the crowd: he will endure it if
need be; but if it be referred to him, he will choose to be alone. He
cannot think himself sufficiently rid of vice, if he must yet contend
with it in other men. Charondas punished those as evil men who were
convicted of keeping ill company. There is nothing so unsociable and
sociable as man, the one by his vice, the other by his nature. And
Antisthenes, in my opinion, did not give him a satisfactory answer, who
reproached him with frequenting ill company, by saying that the
physicians lived well enough amongst the sick, for if they contribute to
the health of the sick, no doubt but by the contagion, continual sight
of, and familiarity with diseases, they must of necessity impair their
own.
Now the end, I take it, is all one, to live at more leisure and at
one's ease: but men do not always take the right way. They often think
they have totally taken leave of all business, when they have only
exchanged one employment for another: there is little less trouble in
governing a private family than a whole kingdom. Wherever the mind is
perplexed, it is in an entire disorder, and domestic employments are not
less troublesome for being less important. Moreover, for having shaken
off the court and the exchange, we have not taken leave of the principal
vexations of life:
"Ratio et prudentia curas,
Non locus effusi late maris arbiter, aufert;"
["Reason and prudence, not a place with a commanding view of the
great ocean, banish care."—Horace, Ep., i. 2.]
ambition, avarice, irresolution, fear, and inordinate desires, do not
leave us because we forsake our native country:
"Et
Post equitem sedet atra cura;"
["Black care sits behind the horse man."
—Horace, Od., iii. 1, 40].
they often follow us even to cloisters and philosophical schools; nor
deserts, nor caves, hair-shirts, nor fasts, can disengage us from them:
"Haeret lateri lethalis arundo."
["The fatal shaft adheres to the side."—AEneid, iv. 73.]
One telling Socrates that such a one was nothing improved by his
travels: "I very well believe it," said he, "for he took himself along
with him"
"Quid terras alio calentes
Sole mutamus? patriae quis exsul
Se quoque fugit?"
["Why do we seek climates warmed by another sun? Who is the man
that by fleeing from his country, can also flee from himself?"
—Horace, Od., ii. 16, 18.]
If a man do not first discharge both himself and his mind of the
burden with which he finds himself oppressed, motion will but make it
press the harder and sit the heavier, as the lading of a ship is of less
encumbrance when fast and bestowed in a settled posture. You do a sick
man more harm than good in removing him from place to place; you fix and
establish the disease by motion, as stakes sink deeper and more firmly
into the earth by being moved up and down in the place where they are
designed to stand. Therefore, it is not enough to get remote from the
public; 'tis not enough to shift the soil only; a man must flee from the
popular conditions that have taken possession of his soul, he must
sequester and come again to himself:
"Rupi jam vincula, dicas
Nam luctata canis nodum arripit; attamen illi,
Quum fugit, a collo trahitur pars longa catenae."
["You say, perhaps, you have broken your chains: the dog who after
long efforts has broken his chain, still in his flight drags a heavy
portion of it after him."—Persius, Sat., v. 158.]
We still carry our fetters along with us. 'Tis not an absolute
liberty; we yet cast back a look upon what we have left behind us; the
fancy is still full of it:
"Nisi purgatum est pectus, quae praelia nobis
Atque pericula tunc ingratis insinuandum?
Quantae connscindunt hominem cupedinis acres
Sollicitum curae? quantique perinde timores?
Quidve superbia, spurcitia, ac petulantia, quantas
Efficiunt clades? quid luxus desidiesque?"
["But unless the mind is purified, what internal combats and dangers
must we incur in spite of all our efforts! How many bitter
anxieties, how many terrors, follow upon unregulated passion!
What destruction befalls us from pride, lust, petulant anger!
What evils arise from luxury and sloth!"—Lucretius, v. 4.]
Our disease lies in the mind, which cannot escape from itself;
"In culpa est animus, qui se non effugit unquam,"
—Horace, Ep., i. 14, 13.
and therefore is to be called home and confined within itself: that
is the true solitude, and that may be enjoyed even in populous cities
and the courts of kings, though more commodiously apart.
Now, since we will attempt to live alone, and to waive all manner of
conversation amongst them, let us so order it that our content may
depend wholly upon ourselves; let us dissolve all obligations that ally
us to others; let us obtain this from ourselves, that we may live alone
in good earnest, and live at our ease too.
Stilpo having escaped from the burning of his town, where he lost
wife, children, and goods, Demetrius Poliorcetes seeing him, in so great
a ruin of his country, appear with an undisturbed countenance, asked him
if he had received no loss? To which he made answer, No; and that, thank
God, nothing was lost of his.—[Seneca, Ep. 7.]—This also was the meaning
of the philosopher Antisthenes, when he pleasantly said, that "men
should furnish themselves with such things as would float, and might
with the owner escape the storm";—[Diogenes Laertius, vi. 6.] and
certainly a wise man never loses anything if he have himself. When the
city of Nola was ruined by the barbarians, Paulinus, who was bishop of
that place, having there lost all he had, himself a prisoner, prayed
after this manner: "O Lord, defend me from being sensible of this loss;
for Thou knowest they have yet touched nothing of that which is
mine."—[St. Augustin, De Civit. Dei, i. 10.]—The riches that made him
rich and the goods that made him good, were still kept entire. This it
is to make choice of treasures that can secure themselves from plunder
and violence, and to hide them in such a place into which no one can
enter and that is not to be betrayed by any but ourselves. Wives,
children, and goods must be had, and especially health, by him that can
get it; but we are not so to set our hearts upon them that our happiness
must have its dependence upon them; we must reserve a backshop, wholly
our own and entirely free, wherein to settle our true liberty, our
principal solitude and retreat. And in this we must for the most part
entertain ourselves with ourselves, and so privately that no exotic
knowledge or communication be admitted there; there to laugh and to
talk, as if without wife, children, goods, train, or attendance, to the
end that when it shall so fall out that we must lose any or all of
these, it may be no new thing to be without them. We have a mind pliable
in itself, that will be company; that has wherewithal to attack and to
defend, to receive and to give: let us not then fear in this solitude to
languish under an uncomfortable vacuity.
"In solis sis tibi turba locis."
["In solitude, be company for thyself."—Tibullus, vi. 13. 12.]
Virtue is satisfied with herself, without discipline, without words,
without effects. In our ordinary actions there is not one of a thousand
that concerns ourselves. He that thou seest scrambling up the ruins of
that wall, furious and transported, against whom so many
harquebuss-shots are levelled; and that other all over scars, pale, and
fainting with hunger, and yet resolved rather to die than to open the
gates to him; dost thou think that these men are there upon their own
account? No; peradventure in the behalf of one whom they never saw and
who never concerns himself for their pains and danger, but lies
wallowing the while in sloth and pleasure: this other slavering,
blear-eyed, slovenly fellow, that thou seest come out of his study after
midnight, dost thou think he has been tumbling over books to learn how
to become a better man, wiser, and more content? No such matter; he will
there end his days, but he will teach posterity the measure of Plautus'
verses and the true orthography of a Latin word. Who is it that does not
voluntarily exchange his health, his repose, and his very life for
reputation and glory, the most useless, frivolous, and false coin that
passes current amongst us? Our own death does not sufficiently terrify
and trouble us; let us, moreover, charge ourselves with those of our
wives, children, and family: our own affairs do not afford us anxiety
enough; let us undertake those of our neighbours and friends, still more
to break our brains and torment us:
"Vah! quemquamne hominem in animum instituere, aut
Parare, quod sit carius, quam ipse est sibi?"
["Ah! can any man conceive in his mind or realise what is dearer
than he is to himself?"—Terence, Adelph., i. I, 13.]
Solitude seems to me to wear the best favour in such as have already
employed their most active and flourishing age in the world's service,
after the example of Thales. We have lived enough for others; let us at
least live out the small remnant of life for ourselves; let us now call
in our thoughts and intentions to ourselves, and to our own ease and
repose. 'Tis no light thing to make a sure retreat; it will be enough
for us to do without mixing other enterprises. Since God gives us
leisure to order our removal, let us make ready, truss our baggage, take
leave betimes of the company, and disentangle ourselves from those
violent importunities that engage us elsewhere and separate us from
ourselves.
We must break the knot of our obligations, how strong soever, and
hereafter love this or that, but espouse nothing but ourselves: that is
to say, let the remainder be our own, but not so joined and so close as
not to be forced away without flaying us or tearing out part of our
whole. The greatest thing in the world is for a man to know that he is
his own. 'Tis time to wean ourselves from society when we can no longer
add anything to it; he who is not in a condition to lend must forbid
himself to borrow. Our forces begin to fail us; let us call them in and
concentrate them in and for ourselves. He that can cast off within
himself and resolve the offices of friendship and company, let him do
it. In this decay of nature which renders him useless, burdensome, and
importunate to others, let him take care not to be useless, burdensome,
and importunate to himself. Let him soothe and caress himself, and above
all things be sure to govern himself with reverence to his reason and
conscience to that degree as to be ashamed to make a false step in their
presence:
"Rarum est enim, ut satis se quisque vereatur."
["For 'tis rarely seen that men have respect and reverence enough
for themselves."—Quintilian, x. 7.]
Socrates says that boys are to cause themselves to be instructed, men
to exercise themselves in well-doing, and old men to retire from all
civil and military employments, living at their own discretion, without
the obligation to any office. There are some complexions more proper for
these precepts of retirement than others. Such as are of a soft and dull
apprehension, and of a tender will and affection, not readily to be
subdued or employed, whereof I am one, both by natural condition and by
reflection, will sooner incline to this advice than active and busy
souls, which embrace: all, engage in all, are hot upon everything, which
offer, present, and give themselves up to every occasion. We are to use
these accidental and extraneous commodities, so far as they are pleasant
to us, but by no means to lay our principal foundation there; 'tis no
true one; neither nature nor reason allows it so to be. Why therefore
should we, contrary to their laws, enslave our own contentment to the
power of another? To anticipate also the accidents of fortune, to
deprive ourselves of the conveniences we have in our own power, as
several have done upon the account of devotion, and some philosophers by
reasoning; to be one's own servant, to lie hard, to put out our own
eyes, to throw our wealth into the river, to go in search of grief;
these, by the misery of this life, aiming at bliss in another; those by
laying themselves low to avoid the danger of falling: all such are acts
of an excessive virtue. The stoutest and most resolute natures render
even their seclusion glorious and exemplary:
"Tuta et parvula laudo,
Quum res deficiunt, satis inter vilia fortis
Verum, ubi quid melius contingit et unctius, idem
Hos sapere et solos aio bene vivere, quorum
Conspicitur nitidis fundata pecunia villis."
["When means are deficient, I laud a safe and humble condition,
content with little: but when things grow better and more easy, I
all the same say that you alone are wise and live well, whose
invested money is visible in beautiful villas."
—Horace, Ep., i. 15, 42.]
A great deal less would serve my turn well enough. 'Tis enough for
me, under fortune's favour, to prepare myself for her disgrace, and,
being at my ease, to represent to myself, as far as my imagination can
stretch, the ill to come; as we do at jousts and tiltings, where we
counterfeit war in the greatest calm of peace. I do not think Arcesilaus
the philosopher the less temperate and virtuous for knowing that he made
use of gold and silver vessels, when the condition of his fortune
allowed him so to do; I have indeed a better opinion of him than if he
had denied himself what he used with liberality and moderation. I see
the utmost limits of natural necessity: and considering a poor man
begging at my door, ofttimes more jocund and more healthy than I myself
am, I put myself into his place, and attempt to dress my mind after his
mode; and running, in like manner, over other examples, though I fancy
death, poverty, contempt, and sickness treading on my heels, I easily
resolve not to be affrighted, forasmuch as a less than I takes them with
so much patience; and am not willing to believe that a less
understanding can do more than a greater, or that the effects of precept
cannot arrive to as great a height as those of custom. And knowing of
how uncertain duration these accidental conveniences are, I never
forget, in the height of all my enjoyments, to make it my chiefest
prayer to Almighty God, that He will please to render me content with
myself and the condition wherein I am. I see young men very gay and
frolic, who nevertheless keep a mass of pills in their trunk at home, to
take when they've got a cold, which they fear so much the less, because
they think they have remedy at hand. Every one should do in like manner,
and, moreover, if they find themselves subject to some more violent
disease, should furnish themselves with such medicines as may numb and
stupefy the part.
The employment a man should choose for such a life ought neither to
be a laborious nor an unpleasing one; otherwise 'tis to no purpose at
all to be retired. And this depends upon every one's liking and humour.
Mine has no manner of complacency for husbandry, and such as love it
ought to apply themselves to it with moderation:
["Endeavour to make circumstances subject to me,
and not me subject to circumstances."
—Horace, Ep., i. i, 19.]
Husbandry is otherwise a very servile employment, as Sallust calls
it; though some parts of it are more excusable than the rest, as the
care of gardens, which Xenophon attributes to Cyrus; and a mean may be
found out betwixt the sordid and low application, so full of perpetual
solicitude, which is seen in men who make it their entire business and
study, and the stupid and extreme negligence, letting all things go at
random which we see in others
"Democriti pecus edit agellos
Cultaque, dum peregre est animus sine corpore velox."
["Democritus' cattle eat his corn and spoil his fields, whilst his
soaring mind ranges abroad without the body."
—Horace, Ep., i, 12, 12.]
But let us hear what advice the younger Pliny gives his friend
Caninius Rufus upon the subject of solitude: "I advise thee, in the full
and plentiful retirement wherein thou art, to leave to thy hinds the
care of thy husbandry, and to addict thyself to the study of letters, to
extract from thence something that may be entirely and absolutely thine
own." By which he means reputation; like Cicero, who says that he would
employ his solitude and retirement from public affairs to acquire by his
writings an immortal life.
"Usque adeone
Scire tuum, nihil est, nisi to scire hoc, sciat alter?"
["Is all that thy learning nothing, unless another knows
that thou knowest?"—Persius, Sat., i. 23.]
It appears to be reason, when a man talks of retiring from the world,
that he should look quite out of [for] himself. These do it but by
halves: they design well enough for themselves when they shall be no
more in it; but still they pretend to extract the fruits of that design
from the world, when absent from it, by a ridiculous contradiction.
The imagination of those who seek solitude upon the account of
devotion, filling their hopes and courage with certainty of divine
promises in the other life, is much more rationally founded. They
propose to themselves God, an infinite object in goodness and power; the
soul has there wherewithal, at full liberty, to satiate her desires:
afflictions and sufferings turn to their advantage, being undergone for
the acquisition of eternal health and joy; death is to be wished and
longed for, where it is the passage to so perfect a condition; the
asperity of the rules they impose upon themselves is immediately
softened by custom, and all their carnal appetites baffled and subdued,
by refusing to humour and feed them, these being only supported by use
and exercise. This sole end of another happily immortal life is that
which really merits that we should abandon the pleasures and
conveniences of this; and he who can really and constantly inflame his
soul with the ardour of this vivid faith and hope, erects for himself in
solitude a more voluptuous and delicious life than any other sort of
existence.
Neither the end, then, nor the means of this advice pleases me, for
we often fall out of the frying-pan into the fire.—[or: we always
relapse ill from fever into fever.]—This book-employment is as painful
as any other, and as great an enemy to health, which ought to be the
first thing considered; neither ought a man to be allured with the
pleasure of it, which is the same that destroys the frugal, the
avaricious, the voluptuous, and the ambitious man.
["This plodding occupation of bookes is as painfull as any other,
and as great an enemie vnto health, which ought principally to be
considered. And a man should not suffer him selfe to be inveagled
by the pleasure he takes in them."—Florio, edit. 1613, p. 122.]
The sages give us caution enough to beware the treachery of our
desires, and to distinguish true and entire pleasures from such as are
mixed and complicated with greater pain. For the most of our pleasures,
say they, wheedle and caress only to strangle us, like those thieves the
Egyptians called Philistae; if the headache should come before
drunkenness, we should have a care of drinking too much; but pleasure,
to deceive us, marches before and conceals her train. Books are
pleasant, but if, by being over-studious, we impair our health and spoil
our goodhumour, the best pieces we have, let us give it over; I, for my
part, am one of those who think, that no fruit derived from them can
recompense so great a loss. As men who have long felt themselves
weakened by indisposition, give themselves up at last to the mercy of
medicine and submit to certain rules of living, which they are for the
future never to transgress; so he who retires, weary of and disgusted
with the common way of living, ought to model this new one he enters
into by the rules of reason, and to institute and establish it by
premeditation and reflection. He ought to have taken leave of all sorts
of labour, what advantage soever it may promise, and generally to have
shaken off all those passions which disturb the tranquillity of body and
soul, and then choose the way that best suits with his own humour:
"Unusquisque sua noverit ire via."
In husbandry, study, hunting, and all other exercises, men are to
proceed to the utmost limits of pleasure, but must take heed of engaging
further, where trouble begins to mix with it. We are to reserve so much
employment only as is necessary to keep us in breath and to defend us
from the inconveniences that the other extreme of a dull and stupid
laziness brings along with it. There are sterile knotty sciences,
chiefly hammered out for the crowd; let such be left to them who are
engaged in the world's service. I for my part care for no other books,
but either such as are pleasant and easy, to amuse me, or those that
comfort and instruct me how to regulate my life and death:
"Tacitum sylvas inter reptare salubres,
Curantem, quidquid dignum sapienti bonoque est."
["Silently meditating in the healthy groves, whatever is worthy
of a wise and good man."—Horace, Ep., i. 4, 4.]
Wiser men, having great force and vigour of soul, may propose to
themselves a rest wholly spiritual but for me, who have a very ordinary
soul, it is very necessary to support myself with bodily conveniences;
and age having of late deprived me of those pleasures that were more
acceptable to me, I instruct and whet my appetite to those that remain,
more suitable to this other reason. We ought to hold with all our force,
both of hands and teeth, the use of the pleasures of life that our
years, one after another, snatch away from us:
"Carpamus dulcia; nostrum est,
Quod vivis; cinis, et manes, et fabula fies."
["Let us pluck life's sweets, 'tis for them we live: by and by we
shall be ashes, a ghost, a mere subject of talk."
—Persius, Sat., v. 151.]
Now, as to the end that Pliny and Cicero propose to us of glory, 'tis
infinitely wide of my account. Ambition is of all others the most
contrary humour to solitude; glory and repose are things that cannot
possibly inhabit in one and the same place. For so much as I understand,
these have only their arms and legs disengaged from the crowd; their
soul and intention remain confined behind more than ever:
"Tun', vetule, auriculis alienis colligis escas?"
["Dost thou, then, old man, collect food for others' ears?"
—Persius, Sat., i. 22.]
they have only retired to take a better leap, and by a stronger
motion to give a brisker charge into the crowd. Will you see how they
shoot short? Let us put into the counterpoise the advice of two
philosophers, of two very different sects, writing, the one to
Idomeneus, the other to Lucilius, their friends, to retire into solitude
from worldly honours and affairs. "You have," say they, "hitherto lived
swimming and floating; come now and die in the harbour: you have given
the first part of your life to the light, give what remains to the
shade. It is impossible to give over business, if you do not also quit
the fruit; therefore disengage yourselves from all concern of name and
glory; 'tis to be feared the lustre of your former actions will give you
but too much light, and follow you into your most private retreat. Quit
with other pleasures that which proceeds from the approbation of another
man: and as to your knowledge and parts, never concern yourselves; they
will not lose their effect if yourselves be the better for them.
Remember him, who being asked why he took so much pains in an art that
could come to the knowledge of but few persons? 'A few are enough for
me,' replied he; 'I have enough with one; I have enough with never an
one.'—[Seneca, Ep., 7.]—He said true; you and a companion are theatre
enough to one another, or you to yourself. Let the people be to you one,
and be you one to the whole people. 'Tis an unworthy ambition to think
to derive glory from a man's sloth and privacy: you are to do like the
beasts of chase, who efface the track at the entrance into their den.
You are no more to concern yourself how the world talks of you, but how
you are to talk to yourself. Retire yourself into yourself, but first
prepare yourself there to receive yourself: it were a folly to trust
yourself in your own hands, if you cannot govern yourself. A man may
miscarry alone as well as in company. Till you have rendered yourself
one before whom you dare not trip, and till you have a bashfulness and
respect for yourself,
"Obversentur species honestae animo;"
["Let honest things be ever present to the mind"
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 22.]
present continually to your imagination Cato, Phocion, and Aristides,
in whose presence the fools themselves will hide their faults, and make
them controllers of all your intentions; should these deviate from
virtue, your respect to those will set you right; they will keep you in
this way to be contented with yourself; to borrow nothing of any other
but yourself; to stay and fix your soul in certain and limited thoughts,
wherein she may please herself, and having understood the true and real
goods, which men the more enjoy the more they understand, to rest
satisfied, without desire of prolongation of life or name." This is the
precept of the true and natural philosophy, not of a boasting and
prating philosophy, such as that of the two former.
CHAPTER XXXIX——A CONSIDERATION UPON CICERO
One word more by way of comparison betwixt these two. There are to be
gathered out of the writings of Cicero and the younger Pliny (but
little, in my opinion, resembling his uncle in his humours) infinite
testimonies of a beyond measure ambitious nature; and amongst others,
this for one, that they both, in the sight of all the world, solicit the
historians of their time not to forget them in their memoirs; and
fortune, as if in spite, has made the vanity of those requests live upon
record down to this age of ours, while she has long since consigned the
histories themselves to oblivion. But this exceeds all meanness of
spirit in persons of such a quality as they were, to think to derive any
great renown from babbling and prating; even to the publishing of their
private letters to their friends, and so withal, that though some of
them were never sent, the opportunity being lost, they nevertheless
presented them to the light, with this worthy excuse that they were
unwilling to lose their labours and lucubrations. Was it not very well
becoming two consuls of Rome, sovereign magistrates of the republic that
commanded the world, to spend their leisure in contriving quaint and
elegant missives, thence to gain the reputation of being versed in their
own mother-tongues? What could a pitiful schoolmaster have done worse,
whose trade it was thereby to get his living? If the acts of Xenophon
and Caesar had not far transcended their eloquence, I scarce believe
they would ever have taken the pains to have written them; they made it
their business to recommend not their speaking, but their doing. And
could the perfection of eloquence have added a lustre suitable to a
great personage, certainly Scipio and Laelius had never resigned the
honour of their comedies, with all the luxuriances and elegances of the
Latin tongue, to an African slave; for that the work was theirs, its
beauty and excellence sufficiently declare; Terence himself confesses as
much, and I should take it ill from any one that would dispossess me of
that belief.
'Tis a kind of mockery and offence to extol a man for qualities
misbecoming his condition, though otherwise commendable in themselves,
but such as ought not, however, to be his chief talent; as if a man
should commend a king for being a good painter, a good architect, a good
marksman, or a good runner at the ring: commendations that add no
honour, unless mentioned altogether and in the train of those that are
properly applicable to him, namely, justice and the science of governing
and conducting his people both in peace and war. At this rate,
agriculture was an honour to Cyrus, and eloquence and the knowledge of
letters to Charlemagne. I have in my time known some, who by writing
acquired both their titles and fortune, disown their apprenticeship,
corrupt their style, and affect ignorance in so vulgar a quality (which
also our nation holds to be rarely seen in very learned hands), and to
seek a reputation by better qualities. Demosthenes' companions in the
embassy to Philip, extolling that prince as handsome, eloquent, and a
stout drinker, Demosthenes said that those were commendations more
proper for a woman, an advocate, or a sponge, than for a king':
"Imperet bellante prior, jacentem
Lenis in hostem."
["In the fight, overthrow your enemy, but be merciful to him when
fallen.—"Horace, Carm. Saec., v. 51.]
'Tis not his profession to know either how to hunt or to dance well;
"Orabunt causas alii, coelique meatus
Describent radio, et fulgentia sidera dicent;
Hic regere imperio populos sciat."
["Let others plead at the bar, or describe the spheres, and point
out the glittering stars; let this man learn to rule the nations."
—AEneid, vi. 849.]
Plutarch says, moreover, that to appear so excellent in these less
necessary qualities is to produce witness against a man's self, that he
has spent his time and applied his study ill, which ought to have been
employed in the acquisition of more necessary and more useful things. So
that Philip, king of Macedon, having heard that great Alexander his son
sing once at a feast to the wonder of the best musicians there: "Art
thou not ashamed," said he to him, "to sing so well?" And to the same
Philip a musician, with whom he was disputing about some things
concerning his art: "Heaven forbid, sir," said he, "that so great a
misfortune should ever befall you as to understand these things better
than I." A king should be able to answer as Iphicrates did the orator,
who pressed upon him in his invective after this manner: "And what art
thou that thou bravest it at this rate? art thou a man at arms, art thou
an archer, art thou a pikeman?"—"I am none of all this; but I know how
to command all these." And Antisthenes took it for an argument of little
value in Ismenias that he was commended for playing excellently well
upon a flute.
I know very well, that when I hear any one dwell upon the language of
my essays, I had rather a great deal he would say nothing: 'tis not so
much to elevate the style as to depress the sense, and so much the more
offensively as they do it obliquely; and yet I am much deceived if many
other writers deliver more worth noting as to the matter, and, how well
or ill soever, if any other writer has sown things much more materials
or at all events more downright, upon his paper than myself. To bring
the more in, I only muster up the heads; should I annex the sequel, I
should trebly multiply the volume. And how many stories have I scattered
up and down in this book that I only touch upon, which, should any one
more curiously search into, they would find matter enough to produce
infinite essays. Neither those stories nor my quotations always serve
simply for example, authority, or ornament; I do not only regard them
for the use I make of them: they carry sometimes besides what I apply
them to, the seed of a more rich and a bolder matter, and sometimes,
collaterally, a more delicate sound both to myself who will say no more
about it in this place, and to others who shall be of my humour.
But returning to the speaking virtue: I find no great choice betwixt
not knowing to speak anything but ill, and not knowing to speak anything
but well.
"Non est ornamentum virile concimitas."
["A carefully arranged dress is no manly ornament."
—Seneca, Ep., 115.]
The sages tell us that, as to what concerns knowledge, 'tis nothing
but philosophy; and as to what concerns effects, nothing but virtue,
which is generally proper to all degrees and to all orders.
There is something like this in these two other philosophers, for
they also promise eternity to the letters they write to their friends;
but 'tis after another manner, and by accommodating themselves, for a
good end, to the vanity of another; for they write to them that if the
concern of making themselves known to future ages, and the thirst of
glory, do yet detain them in the management of public affairs, and make
them fear the solitude and retirement to which they would persuade them,
let them never trouble themselves more about it, forasmuch as they shall
have credit enough with posterity to ensure them that were there nothing
else but the letters thus written to them, those letters will render
their names as known and famous as their own public actions could do.
And besides this difference, these are not idle and empty letters, that
contain nothing but a fine jingle of well-chosen words and delicate
couched phrases, but rather replete and abounding with grand discourses
of reason, by which a man may render himself not more eloquent, but more
wise, and that instruct us not to speak, but to do well. Away with that
eloquence that enchants us with itself, and not with actual things!
unless you will allow that of Cicero to be of so supreme a perfection as
to form a complete body of itself.
I shall farther add one story we read of him to this purpose, wherein
his nature will much more manifestly be laid open to us. He was to make
an oration in public, and found himself a little straitened for time to
make himself ready at his ease; when Eros, one of his slaves, brought
him word that the audience was deferred till the next day, at which he
was so ravished with joy that he enfranchised him for the good news.
Upon this subject of letters, I will add this more to what has been
already said, that it is a kind of writing wherein my friends think I
can do something; and I am willing to confess I should rather have
chosen to publish my whimsies that way than any other, had I had to whom
to write; but I wanted such a settled intercourse, as I once had, to
attract me to it, to raise my fancy, and to support me. For to traffic
with the wind, as some others have done, and to forge vain names to
direct my letters to, in a serious subject, I could never do it but in a
dream, being a sworn enemy to all manner of falsification. I should have
been more diligent and more confident had I had a judicious and
indulgent friend whom to address, than thus to expose myself to the
various judgments of a whole people, and I am deceived if I had not
succeeded better. I have naturally a humorous and familiar style; but it
is a style of my own, not proper for public business, but, like the
language I speak, too compact, irregular, abrupt, and singular; and as
to letters of ceremony that have no other substance than a fine
contexture of courteous words, I am wholly to seek. I have neither
faculty nor relish for those tedious tenders of service and affection; I
believe little in them from others, and I should not forgive myself
should I say to others more than I myself believe. 'Tis, doubtless, very
remote from the present practice; for there never was so abject and
servile prostitution of offers: life, soul, devotion, adoration, vassal,
slave, and I cannot tell what, as now; all which expressions are so
commonly and so indifferently posted to and fro by every one and to
every one, that when they would profess a greater and more respectful
inclination upon more just occasions, they have not wherewithal to
express it. I mortally hate all air of flattery, which is the cause that
I naturally fall into a shy, rough, and crude way of speaking, that, to
such as do not know me, may seem a little to relish of disdain. I honour
those most to whom I show the least honour, and where my soul moves with
the greatest cheerfulness, I easily forget the ceremonies of look and
gesture, and offer myself faintly and bluntly to them to whom I am the
most devoted: methinks they should read it in my heart, and that the
expression of my words does but injure the love I have conceived within.
To welcome, take leave, give thanks, accost, offer my service, and such
verbal formalities as the ceremonious laws of our modern civility
enjoin, I know no man so stupidly unprovided of language as myself; and
I have never been employed in writing letters of favour and
recommendation, that he, in whose behalf it was written, did not think
my mediation cold and imperfect. The Italians are great printers of
letters; I do believe I have at least an hundred several volumes of
them; of all which those of Annibale Caro seem to me to be the best. If
all the paper I have scribbled to the ladies at the time when my hand
was really prompted by my passion, were now in being, there might,
peradventure, be found a page worthy to be communicated to our young
inamoratos, that are besotted with that fury. I always write my letters
post-haste—so precipitately, that though I write intolerably ill, I
rather choose to do it myself, than to employ another; for I can find
none able to follow me: and I never transcribe any. I have accustomed
the great ones who know me to endure my blots and dashes, and upon paper
without fold or margin. Those that cost me the most pains, are the
worst; when I once begin to draw it in by head and shoulders, 'tis a
sign that I am not there. I fall too without premeditation or design;
the first word begets the second, and so to the end of the chapter. The
letters of this age consist more in fine edges and prefaces than in
matter. Just as I had rather write two letters than close and fold up
one, and always assign that employment to some other, so, when the real
business of my letter is dispatched, I would with all my heart transfer
it to another hand to add those long harangues, offers, and prayers,
that we place at the bottom, and should be glad that some new custom
would discharge us of that trouble; as also of superscribing them with a
long legend of qualities and titles, which for fear of mistakes, I have
often not written at all, and especially to men of the long robe and
finance; there are so many new offices, such a dispensation and ordering
of titles of honour, that 'tis hard to set them forth aright yet, being
so dearly bought, they are neither to be altered nor forgotten without
offence. I find it equally in bad taste to encumber the fronts and
inscriptions of the books we commit to the press with such.
CHAPTER XL——THAT THE RELISH FOR GOOD AND EVIL DEPENDS IN GREAT
MEASURE UPON THE OPINION WE HAVE OF THEM
Men (says an ancient Greek sentence)—[Manual of Epictetus, c. 10.]—
are tormented with the opinions they have of things and not by the
things themselves. It were a great victory obtained for the relief of
our miserable human condition, could this proposition be established for
certain and true throughout. For if evils have no admission into us but
by the judgment we ourselves make of them, it should seem that it is,
then, in our own power to despise them or to turn them to good. If
things surrender themselves to our mercy, why do we not convert and
accommodate them to our advantage? If what we call evil and torment is
neither evil nor torment of itself, but only that our fancy gives it
that quality, it is in us to change it, and it being in our own choice,
if there be no constraint upon us, we must certainly be very strange
fools to take arms for that side which is most offensive to us, and to
give sickness, want, and contempt a bitter and nauseous taste, if it be
in our power to give them a pleasant relish, and if, fortune simply
providing the matter, 'tis for us to give it the form. Now, that what we
call evil is not so of itself, or at least to that degree that we make
it, and that it depends upon us to give it another taste and complexion
(for all comes to one), let us examine how that can be maintained.
If the original being of those things we fear had power to lodge
itself in us by its own authority, it would then lodge itself alike, and
in like manner, in all; for men are all of the same kind, and saving in
greater and less proportions, are all provided with the same utensils
and instruments to conceive and to judge; but the diversity of opinions
we have of those things clearly evidences that they only enter us by
composition; one person, peradventure, admits them in their true being,
but a thousand others give them a new and contrary being in them. We
hold death, poverty, and pain for our principal enemies; now, this
death, which some repute the most dreadful of all dreadful things, who
does not know that others call it the only secure harbour from the
storms and tempests of life, the sovereign good of nature, the sole
support of liberty, and the common and prompt remedy of all evils? And
as the one expect it with fear and trembling, the others support it with
greater ease than life. That one complains of its facility:
"Mors! utinam pavidos vitae subducere nolles.
Sed virtus to sola daret!"
["O death! wouldst that thou might spare the coward, but that
valour alone should pay thee tribute."—Lucan, iv. 580.]
Now, let us leave these boastful courages. Theodorus answered
Lysimachus, who threatened to kill him, "Thou wilt do a brave feat,"
said he, "to attain the force of a cantharides." The majority of
philosophers are observed to have either purposely anticipated, or
hastened and assisted their own death. How many ordinary people do we
see led to execution, and that not to a simple death, but mixed with
shame and sometimes with grievous torments, appear with such assurance,
whether through firm courage or natural simplicity, that a man can
discover no change from their ordinary condition; settling their
domestic affairs, commending themselves to their friends, singing,
preaching, and addressing the people, nay, sometimes sallying into
jests, and drinking to their companions, quite as well as Socrates?
One that they were leading to the gallows told them they must not
take him through such a street, lest a merchant who lived there should
arrest him by the way for an old debt. Another told the hangman he must
not touch his neck for fear of making him laugh, he was so ticklish.
Another answered his confessor, who promised him he should that day sup
with our Lord, "Do you go then," said he, "in my room [place]; for I for
my part keep fast to-day." Another having called for drink, and the
hangman having drunk first, said he would not drink after him, for fear
of catching some evil disease. Everybody has heard the tale of the
Picard, to whom, being upon the ladder, they presented a common wench,
telling him (as our law does some times permit) that if he would marry
her they would save his life; he, having a while considered her and
perceiving that she halted: "Come, tie up, tie up," said he, "she
limps." And they tell another story of the same kind of a fellow in
Denmark, who being condemned to lose his head, and the like condition
being proposed to him upon the scaffold, refused it, by reason the girl
they offered him had hollow cheeks and too sharp a nose. A servant at
Toulouse being accused of heresy, for the sum of his belief referred
himself to that of his master, a young student, prisoner with him,
choosing rather to die than suffer himself to be persuaded that his
master could err. We read that of the inhabitants of Arras, when Louis
XI. took that city, a great many let themselves be hanged rather than
they would say, "God save the King." And amongst that mean-souled race
of men, the buffoons, there have been some who would not leave their
fooling at the very moment of death. One that the hang man was turning
off the ladder cried: "Launch the galley," an ordinary saying of his.
Another, whom at the point of death his friends had laid upon a bed of
straw before the fire, the physician asking him where his pain lay:
"Betwixt the bench and the fire," said he, and the priest, to give him
extreme unction, groping for his feet which his pain had made him pull
up to him: "You will find them," said he, "at the end of my legs." To
one who being present exhorted him to recommend himself to God: "Why,
who goes thither?" said he; and the other replying: "It will presently
be yourself, if it be His good pleasure." "Shall I be sure to be there
by to-morrow night?" said he. "Do, but recommend yourself to Him," said
the other, "and you will soon be there." "I were best then," said he,
"to carry my recommendations myself."
In the kingdom of Narsingah to this day the wives of their priests
are buried alive with the bodies of their husbands; all other wives are
burnt at their husbands' funerals, which they not only firmly but
cheerfully undergo. At the death of their king, his wives and
concubines, his favourites, all his officers, and domestic servants, who
make up a whole people, present themselves so gaily to the fire where
his body is burnt, that they seem to take it for a singular honour to
accompany their master in death. During our late wars of Milan, where
there happened so many takings and retakings of towns, the people,
impatient of so many changes of fortune, took such a resolution to die,
that I have heard my father say he there saw a list taken of
five-and-twenty masters of families who made themselves away in one
week's time: an incident somewhat resembling that of the Xanthians, who
being besieged by Brutus, fell—men, women, and children—into such a
furious appetite of dying, that nothing can be done to evade death which
they did not to avoid life; insomuch that Brutus had much difficulty in
saving a very small number.—["Only fifty were saved."—Plutarch, Life of
Brutus, c. 8.]
Every opinion is of force enough to cause itself to be espoused at
the expense of life. The first article of that valiant oath that Greece
took and observed in the Median war, was that every one should sooner
exchange life for death, than their own laws for those of Persia. What a
world of people do we see in the wars betwixt the Turks and the Greeks,
rather embrace a cruel death than uncircumcise themselves to admit of
baptism? An example of which no sort of religion is incapable.
The kings of Castile having banished the Jews out of their dominions,
John, King of Portugal, in consideration of eight crowns a head, sold
them a retreat into his for a certain limited time, upon condition that
the time fixed coming to expire they should begone, and he to furnish
them with shipping to transport them into Africa. The day comes, which
once lapsed they were given to understand that such as were afterward
found in the kingdom should remain slaves; vessels were very slenderly
provided; and those who embarked in them were rudely and villainously
used by the passengers, who, besides other indignities, kept them
cruising upon the sea, one while forwards and another backwards, till
they had spent all their provisions, and were constrained to buy of them
at so dear a rate and so long withal, that they set them not on shore
till they were all stripped to the very shirts. The news of this inhuman
usage being brought to those who remained behind, the greater part of
them resolved upon slavery and some made a show of changing religion.
Emmanuel, the successor of John, being come to the crown, first set them
at liberty, and afterwards altering his mind, ordered them to depart his
country, assigning three ports for their passage. He hoped, says Bishop
Osorius, no contemptible Latin historian of these later times, that the
favour of the liberty he had given them having failed of converting them
to Christianity, yet the difficulty of committing themselves to the
mercy of the mariners and of abandoning a country they were now
habituated to and were grown very rich in, to go and expose themselves
in strange and unknown regions, would certainly do it. But finding
himself deceived in his expectation, and that they were all resolved
upon the voyage, he cut off two of the three ports he had promised them,
to the end that the length and incommodity of the passage might reduce
some, or that he might have opportunity, by crowding them all into one
place, the more conveniently to execute what he had designed, which was
to force all the children under fourteen years of age from the arms of
their fathers and mothers, to transport them from their sight and
conversation, into a place where they might be instructed and brought up
in our religion. He says that this produced a most horrid spectacle the
natural affection betwixt the parents and their children, and moreover
their zeal to their ancient belief, contending against this violent
decree, fathers and mothers were commonly seen making themselves away,
and by a yet much more rigorous example, precipitating out of love and
compassion their young children into wells and pits, to avoid the
severity of this law. As to the remainder of them, the time that had
been prefixed being expired, for want of means to transport them they
again returned into slavery. Some also turned Christians, upon whose
faith, as also that of their posterity, even to this day, which is a
hundred years since, few Portuguese can yet rely; though custom and
length of time are much more powerful counsellors in such changes than
all other constraints whatever. In the town of Castelnaudari, fifty
heretic Albigeois at one time suffered themselves to be burned alive in
one fire rather than they would renounce their opinions.
"Quoties non modo ductores nostri, sed universi etiam exercitus,
ad non dubiam mortem concurrerunt?"
["How often have not only our leaders, but whole armies, run to a
certain and manifest death."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., i. 37.]
I have seen an intimate friend of mine run headlong upon death with a
real affection, and that was rooted in his heart by divers plausible
arguments which he would never permit me to dispossess him of, and upon
the first honourable occasion that offered itself to him, precipitate
himself into it, without any manner of visible reason, with an obstinate
and ardent desire of dying. We have several examples in our own times of
persons, even young children, who for fear of some little inconvenience
have despatched themselves. And what shall we not fear, says one of the
ancients—[Seneca, Ep., 70.]—to this purpose, if we dread that which
cowardice itself has chosen for its refuge?
Should I here produce a long catalogue of those, of all sexes and
conditions and sects, even in the most happy ages, who have either with
great constancy looked death in the face, or voluntarily sought it, and
sought it not only to avoid the evils of this life, but some purely to
avoid the satiety of living, and others for the hope of a better
condition elsewhere, I should never have done. Nay, the number is so
infinite that in truth I should have a better bargain on't to reckon up
those who have feared it. This one therefore shall serve for all: Pyrrho
the philosopher being one day in a boat in a very great tempest, shewed
to those he saw the most affrighted about him, and encouraged them, by
the example of a hog that was there, nothing at all concerned at the
storm. Shall we then dare to say that this advantage of reason, of which
we so much boast, and upon the account of which we think ourselves
masters and emperors over the rest of all creation, was given us for a
torment? To what end serves the knowledge of things if it renders us
more unmanly? if we thereby lose the tranquillity and repose we should
enjoy without it? and if it put us into a worse condition than Pyrrho's
hog? Shall we employ the understanding that was conferred upon us for
our greatest good to our own ruin; setting ourselves against the design
of nature and the universal order of things, which intend that every one
should make use of the faculties, members, and means he has to his own
best advantage?
But it may, peradventure, be objected against me: Your rule is true
enough as to what concerns death; but what will you say of indigence?
What will you, moreover, say of pain, which Aristippus, Hieronimus, and
most of the sages have reputed the worst of evils; and those who have
denied it by word of mouth have, however, confessed it in effect?
Posidonius being extremely tormented with a sharp and painful disease,
Pompeius came to visit him, excusing himself that he had taken so
unseasonable a time to come to hear him discourse of philosophy. "The
gods forbid," said Posidonius to him, "that pain should ever have the
power to hinder me from talking," and thereupon fell immediately upon a
discourse of the contempt of pain: but, in the meantime, his own
infirmity was playing his part, and plagued him to purpose; to which he
cried out, "Thou mayest work thy will, pain, and torment me with all the
power thou hast, but thou shalt never make me say that thou art an
evil." This story that they make such a clutter withal, what has it to
do, I fain would know, with the contempt of pain? He only fights it with
words, and in the meantime, if the shootings and dolours he felt did not
move him, why did he interrupt his discourse? Why did he fancy he did so
great a thing in forbearing to confess it an evil? All does not here
consist in the imagination; our fancies may work upon other things: but
here is the certain science that is playing its part, of which our
senses themselves are judges:
"Qui nisi sunt veri, ratio quoque falsa sit omnis."
["Which, if they be not true, all reasoning may also be false.
—"Lucretius, iv. 486.]
Shall we persuade our skins that the jerks of a whip agreeably tickle
us, or our taste that a potion of aloes is vin de Graves? Pyrrho's hog
is here in the same predicament with us; he is not afraid of death, 'tis
true, but if you beat him he will cry out to some purpose. Shall we
force the general law of nature, which in every living creature under
heaven is seen to tremble under pain? The very trees seem to groan under
the blows they receive. Death is only felt by reason, forasmuch as it is
the motion of an instant;
"Aut fuit, aut veniet; nihil est praesentis in illa."
["Death has been, or will come: there is nothing of the present in
it."—Estienne de la Boetie, Satires.]
"Morsque minus poenae, quam mora mortis, habet;"
["The delay of death is more painful than death itself."
—Ovid, Ep. Ariadne to Theseus, v. 42.]
a thousand beasts, a thousand men, are sooner dead than threatened.
That also which we principally pretend to fear in death is pain, its
ordinary forerunner: yet, if we may believe a holy father:
"Malam mortem non facit, nisi quod sequitur mortem."
["That which follows death makes death bad."
—St. Augustin, De Civit. Dei, i. ii.]
And I should yet say, more probably, that neither that which goes
before nor that which follows after is at all of the appurtenances of
death.
We excuse ourselves falsely: and I find by experience that it is
rather the impatience of the imagination of death that makes us
impatient of pain, and that we find it doubly grievous as it threatens
us with death. But reason accusing our cowardice for fearing a thing so
sudden, so inevitable, and so insensible, we take the other as the more
excusable pretence. All ills that carry no other danger along with them
but simply the evils themselves, we treat as things of no danger: the
toothache or the gout, painful as they are, yet being not reputed
mortal, who reckons them in the catalogue of diseases?
But let us presuppose that in death we principally regard the pain;
as also there is nothing to be feared in poverty but the miseries it
brings along with it of thirst, hunger, cold, heat, watching, and the
other inconveniences it makes us suffer, still we have nothing to do
with anything but pain. I will grant, and very willingly, that it is the
worst incident of our being (for I am the man upon earth who the most
hates and avoids it, considering that hitherto, I thank God, I have had
so little traffic with it), but still it is in us, if not to annihilate,
at least to lessen it by patience; and though the body and the reason
should mutiny, to maintain the soul, nevertheless, in good condition.
Were it not so, who had ever given reputation to virtue; valour, force,
magnanimity, and resolution? where were their parts to be played if
there were no pain to be defied?
"Avida est periculi virtus."
["Courage is greedy of danger."—Seneca, De Providentia, c. 4]
Were there no lying upon the hard ground, no enduring, armed at all
points, the meridional heats, no feeding upon the flesh of horses and
asses, no seeing a man's self hacked and hewed to pieces, no suffering a
bullet to be pulled out from amongst the shattered bones, no sewing up,
cauterising and searching of wounds, by what means were the advantage we
covet to have over the vulgar to be acquired? 'Tis far from flying evil
and pain, what the sages say, that of actions equally good, a man should
most covet to perform that wherein there is greater labour and pain.
"Non est enim hilaritate, nec lascivia, nec risu, aut joco
comite levitatis, sed saepe etiam tristes firmitate et
constantia sunt beati."
["For men are not only happy by mirth and wantonness, by laughter
and jesting, the companion of levity, but ofttimes the serious sort
reap felicity from their firmness and constancy."
—Cicero, De Finib. ii. 10.]
And for this reason it has ever been impossible to persuade our
forefathers but that the victories obtained by dint of force and the
hazard of war were not more honourable than those performed in great
security by stratagem or practice:
"Laetius est, quoties magno sibi constat honestum."
["A good deed is all the more a satisfaction by how much the more
it has cost us"—Lucan, ix. 404.]
Besides, this ought to be our comfort, that naturally, if the pain be
violent, 'tis but short; and if long, nothing violent:
"Si gravis, brevis;
Si longus, levis."
Thou wilt not feel it long if thou feelest it too much; it will
either put an end to itself or to thee; it comes to the same thing; if
thou canst not support it, it will export thee:
["Remember that the greatest pains are terminated by death; that
slighter pains have long intermissions of repose, and that we are
masters of the more moderate sort: so that, if they be tolerable,
we bear them; if not, we can go out of life, as from a theatre, when
it does not please us"—Cicero, De Finib. i. 15.]
That which makes us suffer pain with so much impatience is the not
being accustomed to repose our chiefest contentment in the soul; that we
do not enough rely upon her who is the sole and sovereign mistress of
our condition. The body, saving in the greater or less proportion, has
but one and the same bent and bias; whereas the soul is variable into
all sorts of forms; and subject to herself and to her own empire, all
things whatsoever, both the senses of the body and all other accidents:
and therefore it is that we ought to study her, to inquire into her, and
to rouse up all her powerful faculties. There is neither reason, force,
nor prescription that can anything prevail against her inclination and
choice. Of so many thousands of biases that she has at her disposal, let
us give her one proper to our repose and conversation, and then we shall
not only be sheltered and secured from all manner of injury and offence,
but moreover gratified and obliged, if she will, with evils and
offences. She makes her profit indifferently of all things; error,
dreams, serve her to good use, as loyal matter to lodge us in safety and
contentment. 'Tis plain enough to be seen that 'tis the sharpness of our
mind that gives the edge to our pains and pleasures: beasts that have no
such thing, leave to their bodies their own free and natural sentiments,
and consequently in every kind very near the same, as appears by the
resembling application of their motions. If we would not disturb in our
members the jurisdiction that appertains to them in this, 'tis to be
believed it would be the better for us, and that nature has given them a
just and moderate temper both to pleasure and pain; neither can it fail
of being just, being equal and common. But seeing we have enfranchised
ourselves from her rules to give ourselves up to the rambling liberty of
our own fancies, let us at least help to incline them to the most
agreeable side. Plato fears our too vehemently engaging ourselves with
pain and pleasure, forasmuch as these too much knit and ally the soul to
the body; whereas I rather, quite contrary, by reason it too much
separates and disunites them. As an enemy is made more fierce by our
flight, so pain grows proud to see us truckle under her. She will
surrender upon much better terms to them who make head against her: a
man must oppose and stoutly set himself against her. In retiring and
giving ground, we invite and pull upon ourselves the ruin that threatens
us. As the body is more firm in an encounter, the more stiffly and
obstinately it applies itself to it, so is it with the soul.
But let us come to examples, which are the proper game of folks of
such feeble force as myself; where we shall find that it is with pain as
with stones, that receive a brighter or a duller lustre according to the
foil they are set in, and that it has no more room in us than we are
pleased to allow it:
"Tantum doluerunt, quantum doloribus se inseruerunt."
["They suffered so much the more, by how much more they gave way to
suffering."—St. Augustin, De Civit. Dei, i. 10.]
We are more sensible of one little touch of a surgeon's lancet than
of twenty wounds with a sword in the heat of fight. The pains of
childbearing, said by the physicians and by God himself to be great, and
which we pass through with so many ceremonies—there are whole nations
that make nothing of them. I set aside the Lacedaemonian women, but what
else do you find in the Swiss among our foot-soldiers, if not that, as
they trot after their husbands, you see them to-day carry the child at
their necks that they carried yesterday in their bellies? The
counterfeit Egyptians we have amongst us go themselves to wash theirs,
so soon as they come into the world, and bathe in the first river they
meet. Besides so many wenches as daily drop their children by stealth,
as they conceived them, that fair and noble wife of Sabinus, a patrician
of Rome, for another's interest, endured alone, without help, without
crying out, or so much as a groan, the bearing of twins.—[Plutarch, On
Love, c. 34.]—A poor simple boy of Lacedaemon having stolen a fox (for
they more fear the shame of stupidity in stealing than we do the
punishment of the knavery), and having got it under his coat, rather
endured the tearing out of his bowels than he would discover his theft.
And another offering incense at a sacrifice, suffered himself to be
burned to the bone by a coal that fell into his sleeve, rather than
disturb the ceremony. And there have been a great number, for a sole
trial of virtue, following their institutions, who have at seven years
old endured to be whipped to death without changing their countenance.
And Cicero has seen them fight in parties, with fists, feet, and teeth,
till they have fainted and sunk down, rather than confess themselves
overcome:
["Custom could never conquer nature; she is ever invincible; but we
have infected the mind with shadows, delights, negligence, sloth;
we have grown effeminate through opinions and corrupt morality."
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., v. 27.]
Every one knows the story of Scaevola, that having slipped into the
enemy's camp to kill their general, and having missed his blow, to
repair his fault, by a more strange invention and to deliver his
country, he boldly confessed to Porsenna, who was the king he had a
purpose to kill, not only his design, but moreover added that there were
then in the camp a great number of Romans, his accomplices in the
enterprise, as good men as he; and to show what a one he himself was,
having caused a pan of burning coals to be brought, he saw and endured
his arm to broil and roast, till the king himself, conceiving horror at
the sight, commanded the pan to be taken away. What would you say of him
that would not vouchsafe to respite his reading in a book whilst he was
under incision? And of the other that persisted to mock and laugh in
contempt of the pains inflicted upon him; so that the provoked cruelty
of the executioners that had him in handling, and all the inventions of
tortures redoubled upon him, one after another, spent in vain, gave him
the bucklers? But he was a philosopher. But what! a gladiator of
Caesar's endured, laughing all the while, his wounds to be searched,
lanced, and laid open:
["What ordinary gladiator ever groaned? Which of them ever changed
countenance? Which of them not only stood or fell indecorously?
Which, when he had fallen and was commanded to receive the stroke of
the sword, contracted his neck."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 17.]
Let us bring in the women too. Who has not heard at Paris of her that
caused her face to be flayed only for the fresher complexion of a new
skin? There are who have drawn good and sound teeth to make their voices
more soft and sweet, or to place the other teeth in better order. How
many examples of the contempt of pain have we in that sex? What can they
not do, what do they fear to do, for never so little hope of an addition
to their beauty?
"Vallere queis cura est albos a stirpe capillos,
Et faciem, dempta pelle, referre novam."
["Who carefully pluck out their grey hairs by the roots, and renew
their faces by peeling off the old skin."—Tibullus, i. 8, 45.]
I have seen some of them swallow sand, ashes, and do their utmost to
destroy their stomachs to get pale complexions. To make a fine Spanish
body, what racks will they not endure of girding and bracing, till they
have notches in their sides cut into the very quick, and sometimes to
death?
It is an ordinary thing with several nations at this day to wound
themselves in good earnest to gain credit to what they profess; of which
our king, relates notable examples of what he has seen in Poland and
done towards himself.—[Henry III.]—But besides this, which I know to
have been imitated by some in France, when I came from that famous
assembly of the Estates at Blois, I had a little before seen a maid in
Picardy, who to manifest the ardour of her promises, as also her
constancy, give herself, with a bodkin she wore in her hair, four or
five good lusty stabs in the arm, till the blood gushed out to some
purpose. The Turks give themselves great scars in honour of their
mistresses, and to the end they may the longer remain, they presently
clap fire to the wound, where they hold it an incredible time to stop
the blood and form the cicatrice; people that have been eyewitnesses of
it have both written and sworn it to me. But for ten aspers—[A Turkish
coin worth about a penny]—there are there every day fellows to be found
that will give themselves a good deep slash in the arms or thighs. I am
willing, however, to have the testimonies nearest to us when we have
most need of them; for Christendom furnishes us with enough. After the
example of our blessed Guide there have been many who have crucified
themselves. We learn by testimony very worthy of belief, that King St.
Louis wore a hair-shirt till in his old age his confessor gave him a
dispensation to leave it off; and that every Friday he caused his
shoulders to be drubbed by his priest with five small chains of iron
which were always carried about amongst his night accoutrements for that
purpose.
William, our last Duke of Guienne, the father of that Eleanor who
transmitted that duchy to the houses of France and England, continually
for the last ten or twelve years of his life wore a suit of armour under
a religious habit by way of penance. Foulke, Count of Anjou, went as far
as Jerusalem, there to cause himself to be whipped by two of his
servants, with a rope about his neck, before the sepulchre of our Lord.
But do we not, moreover, every Good Friday, in various places, see great
numbers of men and women beat and whip themselves till they lacerate and
cut the flesh to the very bones? I have often seen it, and 'tis without
any enchantment; and it was said there were some amongst them (for they
go disguised) who for money undertook by this means to save harmless the
religion of others, by a contempt of pain, so much the greater, as the
incentives of devotion are more effectual than those of avarice. Q.
Maximus buried his son when he was a consul, and M. Cato his when
praetor elect, and L. Paulus both his, within a few days one after
another, with such a countenance as expressed no manner of grief. I said
once merrily of a certain person, that he had disappointed the divine
justice; for the violent death of three grown-up children of his being
one day sent him, for a severe scourge, as it is to be supposed, he was
so far from being afflicted at the accident, that he rather took it for
a particular grace and favour of heaven. I do not follow these monstrous
humours, though I lost two or three at nurse, if not without grief, at
least without repining, and yet there is hardly any accident that
pierces nearer to the quick. I see a great many other occasions of
sorrow, that should they happen to me I should hardly feel; and have
despised some, when they have befallen me, to which the world has given
so terrible a figure that I should blush to boast of my constancy:
"Ex quo intelligitur, non in natura, sed in opinione,
esse aegritudinem."
["By which one may understand that grief is not in nature, but in
opinion."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., iii. 28.]
Opinion is a powerful party, bold, and without measure. Who ever so
greedily hunted after security and repose as Alexander and Caesar did
after disturbance and difficulties? Teres, the father of Sitalces, was
wont to say that "when he had no wars, he fancied there was no
difference betwixt him and his groom." Cato the consul, to secure some
cities of Spain from revolt, only interdicting the inhabitants from
wearing arms, a great many killed themselves:
"Ferox gens, nullam vitam rati sine armis esse."
["A fierce people, who thought there was no life without war."
—Livy, xxxiv. 17.]
How many do we know who have forsaken the calm and sweetness of a
quiet life at home amongst their acquaintance, to seek out the horror of
unhabitable deserts; and having precipitated themselves into so abject a
condition as to become the scorn and contempt of the world, have hugged
themselves with the conceit, even to affectation. Cardinal Borromeo, who
died lately at Milan, amidst all the jollity that the air of Italy, his
youth, birth, and great riches, invited him to, kept himself in so
austere a way of living, that the same robe he wore in summer served him
for winter too; he had only straw for his bed, and his hours of leisure
from affairs he continually spent in study upon his knees, having a
little bread and a glass of water set by his book, which was all the
provision of his repast, and all the time he spent in eating.
I know some who consentingly have acquired both profit and
advancement from cuckoldom, of which the bare name only affrights so
many people.
If the sight be not the most necessary of all our senses, 'tis at
least the most pleasant; but the most pleasant and most useful of all
our members seem to be those of generation; and yet a great many have
conceived a mortal hatred against them only for this, that they were too
pleasant, and have deprived themselves of them only for their value: as
much thought he of his eyes that put them out. The generality and more
solid sort of men look upon abundance of children as a great blessing;
I, and some others, think it as great a benefit to be without them. And
when you ask Thales why he does not marry, he tells you, because he has
no mind to leave any posterity behind him.
That our opinion gives the value to things is very manifest in the
great number of those which we do, not so much prizing them, as
ourselves, and never considering either their virtues or their use, but
only how dear they cost us, as though that were a part of their
substance; and we only repute for value in them, not what they bring to
us, but what we add to them. By which I understand that we are great
economisers of our expense: as it weighs, it serves for so much as it
weighs. Our opinion will never suffer it to want of its value: the price
gives value to the diamond; difficulty to virtue; suffering to devotion;
and griping to physic. A certain person, to be poor, threw his crowns
into the same sea to which so many come, in all parts of the world, to
fish for riches. Epicurus says that to be rich is no relief, but only an
alteration, of affairs. In truth, it is not want, but rather abundance,
that creates avarice. I will deliver my own experience concerning this
affair.
I have since my emergence from childhood lived in three sorts of
conditions. The first, which continued for some twenty years, I passed
over without any other means but what were casual and depending upon the
allowance and assistance of others, without stint, but without certain
revenue. I then spent my money so much the more cheerfully, and with so
much the less care how it went, as it wholly depended upon my
overconfidence of fortune. I never lived more at my ease; I never had
the repulse of finding the purse of any of my friends shut against me,
having enjoined myself this necessity above all other necessities
whatever, by no means to fail of payment at the appointed time, which
also they have a thousand times respited, seeing how careful I was to
satisfy them; so that I practised at once a thrifty, and withal a kind
of alluring, honesty. I naturally feel a kind of pleasure in paying, as
if I eased my shoulders of a troublesome weight and freed myself from an
image of slavery; as also that I find a ravishing kind of satisfaction
in pleasing another and doing a just action. I except payments where the
trouble of bargaining and reckoning is required; and in such cases;
where I can meet with nobody to ease me of that charge, I delay them,
how scandalously and injuriously soever, all I possibly can, for fear of
the wranglings for which both my humour and way of speaking are so
totally improper and unfit. There is nothing I hate so much as driving a
bargain; 'tis a mere traffic of cozenage and impudence, where, after an
hour's cheapening and hesitating, both parties abandon their word and
oath for five sols' abatement. Yet I always borrowed at great
disadvantage; for, wanting the confidence to speak to the person myself,
I committed my request to the persuasion of a letter, which usually is
no very successful advocate, and is of very great advantage to him who
has a mind to deny. I, in those days, more jocundly and freely referred
the conduct of my affairs to the stars, than I have since done to my own
providence and judgment. Most good managers look upon it as a horrible
thing to live always thus in uncertainty, and do not consider, in the
first place, that the greatest part of the world live so: how many
worthy men have wholly abandoned their own certainties, and yet daily do
it, to the winds, to trust to the inconstant favour of princes and of
fortune? Caesar ran above a million of gold, more than he was worth, in
debt to become Caesar; and how many merchants have begun their traffic
by the sale of their farms, which they sent into the Indies,
"Tot per impotentia freta."
["Through so many ungovernable seas."—Catullus, iv. 18.]
In so great a siccity of devotion as we see in these days, we have a
thousand and a thousand colleges that pass it over commodiously enough,
expecting every day their dinner from the liberality of Heaven.
Secondly, they do not take notice that this certitude upon which they so
much rely is not much less uncertain and hazardous than hazard itself. I
see misery as near beyond two thousand crowns a year as if it stood
close by me; for besides that it is in the power of chance to make a
hundred breaches to poverty through the greatest strength of our riches
—there being very often no mean betwixt the highest and the lowest
fortune:
"Fortuna vitrea est: turn, quum splendet, frangitur,"
["Fortune is glass: in its greatest brightness it breaks."
—Ex Mim. P. Syrus.]
and to turn all our barricadoes and bulwarks topsy-turvy, I find
that, by divers causes, indigence is as frequently seen to inhabit with
those who have estates as with those that have none; and that,
peradventure, it is then far less grievous when alone than when
accompanied with riches. These flow more from good management than from
revenue;
"Faber est suae quisque fortunae"
["Every one is the maker of his own fortune."
—Sallust, De Repub. Ord., i. I.]
and an uneasy, necessitous, busy, rich man seems to me more miserable
than he that is simply poor.
"In divitiis mopes, quod genus egestatis gravissimum est."
["Poor in the midst of riches, which is the sorest kind of poverty."
—Seneca, Ep., 74.]
The greatest and most wealthy princes are by poverty and want driven
to the most extreme necessity; for can there be any more extreme than to
become tyrants and unjust usurpers of their subjects' goods and estates?
My second condition of life was to have money of my own, wherein I so
ordered the matter that I had soon laid up a very notable sum out of a
mean fortune, considering with myself that that only was to be reputed
having which a man reserves from his ordinary expense, and that a man
cannot absolutely rely upon revenue he hopes to receive, how clear
soever the hope may be. For what, said I, if I should be surprised by
such or such an accident? And after such-like vain and vicious
imaginations, would very learnedly, by this hoarding of money, provide
against all inconveniences; and could, moreover, answer such as objected
to me that the number of these was too infinite, that if I could not lay
up for all, I could, however, do it at least for some and for many. Yet
was not this done without a great deal of solicitude and anxiety of
mind; I kept it very close, and though I dare talk so boldly of myself,
never spoke of my money, but falsely, as others do, who being rich,
pretend to be poor, and being poor, pretend to be rich, dispensing their
consciences from ever telling sincerely what they have: a ridiculous and
shameful prudence. Was I going a journey? Methought I was never enough
provided: and the more I loaded myself with money, the more also was I
loaded with fear, one while of the danger of the roads, another of the
fidelity of him who had the charge of my baggage, of whom, as some
others that I know, I was never sufficiently secure if I had him not
always in my eye. If I chanced to leave my cash-box behind me, O, what
strange suspicions and anxiety of mind did I enter into, and, which was
worse, without daring to acquaint anybody with it. My mind was eternally
taken up with such things as these, so that, all things considered,
there is more trouble in keeping money than in getting it. And if I did
not altogether so much as I say, or was not really so scandalously
solicitous of my money as I have made myself out to be, yet it cost me
something at least to restrain myself from being so. I reaped little or
no advantage by what I had, and my expenses seemed nothing less to me
for having the more to spend; for, as Bion said, the hairy men are as
angry as the bald to be pulled; and after you are once accustomed to it
and have once set your heart upon your heap, it is no more at your
service; you cannot find in your heart to break it: 'tis a building that
you will fancy must of necessity all tumble down to ruin if you stir but
the least pebble; necessity must first take you by the throat before you
can prevail upon yourself to touch it; and I would sooner have pawned
anything I had, or sold a horse, and with much less constraint upon
myself, than have made the least breach in that beloved purse I had so
carefully laid by. But the danger was that a man cannot easily prescribe
certain limits to this desire (they are hard to find in things that a
man conceives to be good), and to stint this good husbandry so that it
may not degenerate into avarice: men still are intent upon adding to the
heap and increasing the stock from sum to sum, till at last they vilely
deprive themselves of the enjoyment of their own proper goods, and throw
all into reserve, without making any use of them at all. According to
this rule, they are the richest people in the world who are set to guard
the walls and gates of a wealthy city. All moneyed men I conclude to be
covetous. Plato places corporal or human goods in this order: health,
beauty, strength, riches; and riches, says he, are not blind, but very
clear-sighted, when illuminated by prudence. Dionysius the son did a
very handsome act upon this subject; he was informed that one of the
Syracusans had hid a treasure in the earth, and thereupon sent to the
man to bring it to him, which he accordingly did, privately reserving a
small part of it only to himself, with which he went to another city,
where being cured of his appetite of hoarding, he began to live at a
more liberal rate; which Dionysius hearing, caused the rest of his
treasure to be restored to him, saying, that since he had learned to use
it, he very willingly returned it back to him.
I continued some years in this hoarding humour, when I know not what
good demon fortunately put me out of it, as he did the Syracusan, and
made me throw abroad all my reserve at random, the pleasure of a certain
journey I took at very great expense having made me spurn this fond love
of money underfoot; by which means I am now fallen into a third way of
living (I speak what I think of it), doubtless much more pleasant and
regular, which is, that I live at the height of my revenue; sometimes
the one, sometimes the other may perhaps exceed, but 'tis very little
and but rarely that they differ. I live from hand to mouth, and content
myself in having sufficient for my present and ordinary expense; for as
to extraordinary occasions, all the laying up in the world would never
suffice. And 'tis the greatest folly imaginable to expect that fortune
should ever sufficiently arm us against herself; 'tis with our own arms
that we are to fight her; accidental ones will betray us in the pinch of
the business. If I lay up, 'tis for some near and contemplated purpose;
not to purchase lands, of which I have no need, but to purchase
pleasure:
"Non esse cupidum, pecunia est; non esse emacem, vertigal est."
["Not to be covetous, is money; not to be acquisitive, is revenue."
—Cicero, Paradox., vi. 3.]
I neither am in any great apprehension of wanting, nor in desire of
any more:
"Divinarum fructus est in copia; copiam declarat satietas."
["The fruit of riches is in abundance; satiety declares abundance."
—Idem, ibid., vi. 2.]
And I am very well pleased that this reformation in me has fallen out
in an age naturally inclined to avarice, and that I see myself cleared
of a folly so common to old men, and the most ridiculous of all human
follies.
Feraulez, a man that had run through both fortunes, and found that
the increase of substance was no increase of appetite either to eating
or drinking, sleeping or the enjoyment of his wife, and who on the other
side felt the care of his economics lie heavy upon his shoulders, as it
does on mine, was resolved to please a poor young man, his faithful
friend, who panted after riches, and made him a gift of all his, which
were excessively great, and, moreover, of all he was in the daily way of
getting by the liberality of Cyrus, his good master, and by the war;
conditionally that he should take care handsomely to maintain and
plentifully to entertain him as his guest and friend; which being
accordingly done, they afterwards lived very happily together, both of
them equally content with the change of their condition. 'Tis an example
that I could imitate with all my heart; and I very much approve the
fortune of the aged prelate whom I see to have so absolutely stripped
himself of his purse, his revenue, and care of his expense, committing
them one while to one trusty servant, and another while to another, that
he has spun out a long succession of years, as ignorant, by this means,
of his domestic affairs as a mere stranger.
The confidence in another man's virtue is no light evidence of a
man's own, and God willingly favours such a confidence. As to what
concerns him of whom I am speaking, I see nowhere a better governed
house, more nobly and constantly maintained than his. Happy to have
regulated his affairs to so just a proportion that his estate is
sufficient to do it without his care or trouble, and without any
hindrance, either in the spending or laying it up, to his other more
quiet employments, and more suitable both to his place and liking.
Plenty, then, and indigence depend upon the opinion every one has of
them; and riches no more than glory or health have other beauty or
pleasure than he lends them by whom they are possessed.
Every one is well or ill at ease, according as he so finds himself;
not he whom the world believes, but he who believes himself to be so, is
content; and in this alone belief gives itself being and reality.
Fortune does us neither good nor hurt; she only presents us the matter
and the seed, which our soul, more powerful than she, turns and applies
as she best pleases; the sole cause and sovereign mistress of her own
happy or unhappy condition. All external accessions receive taste and
colour from the internal constitution, as clothes warm us, not with
their heat, but our own, which they are fit to cover and nourish; he who
would shield therewith a cold body, would do the same service for the
cold, for so snow and ice are preserved. And, certes, after the same
manner that study is a torment to an idle man, abstinence from wine to a
drunkard, frugality to the spendthrift, and exercise to a lazy,
tender-bred fellow, so it is of all the rest. The things are not so
painful and difficult of themselves, but our weakness or cowardice makes
them so. To judge of great, and high matters requires a suitable soul;
otherwise we attribute the vice to them which is really our own. A
straight oar seems crooked in the water it does not only import that we
see the thing, but how and after what manner we see it.
After all this, why, amongst so many discourses that by so many
arguments persuade men to despise death and to endure pain, can we not
find out one that helps us? And of so many sorts of imaginations as have
so prevailed upon others as to persuade them to do so, why does not
every one apply some one to himself, the most suitable to his own
humour? If he cannot digest a strong-working decoction to eradicate the
evil, let him at least take a lenitive to ease it:
["It is an effeminate and flimsy opinion, nor more so in pain than
in pleasure, in which, while we are at our ease, we cannot bear
without a cry the sting of a bee. The whole business is to commend
thyself."—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., ii. 22.]
As to the rest, a man does not transgress philosophy by permitting
the acrimony of pains and human frailty to prevail so much above
measure; for they constrain her to go back to her unanswerable replies:
"If it be ill to live in necessity, at least there is no necessity upon
a man to live in necessity": "No man continues ill long but by his own
fault." He who has neither the courage to die nor the heart to live, who
will neither resist nor fly, what can we do with him?
CHAPTER XLI——NOT TO COMMUNICATE A MAN'S HONOUR
Of all the follies of the world, that which is most universally
received is the solicitude of reputation and glory; which we are fond of
to that degree as to abandon riches, peace, life, and health, which are
effectual and substantial goods, to pursue this vain phantom and empty
word, that has neither body nor hold to be taken of it:
La fama, ch'invaghisce a un dolce suono
Gli superbi mortali, et par si bella,
E un eco, un sogno, anzi d'un sogno un'ombra,
Ch'ad ogni vento si dilegua a sgombra."
["Fame, which with alluring sound charms proud mortals, and appears
so fair, is but an echo, a dream, nay, the shadow of a dream, which
at every breath vanishes and dissolves."
—Tasso, Gerus., xiv. 63.]
And of all the irrational humours of men, it should seem that the
philosophers themselves are among the last and the most reluctant to
disengage themselves from this: 'tis the most restive and obstinate of
all:
"Quia etiam bene proficientes animos tentare non cessat."
["Because it ceases not to assail even well-directed minds"
—St. Augustin, De Civit. Dei, v. 14.]
There is not any one of which reason so clearly accuses the vanity;
but it is so deeply rooted in us that I dare not determine whether any
one ever clearly discharged himself from it or no. After you have said
all and believed all has been said to its prejudice, it produces so
intestine an inclination in opposition to your best arguments that you
have little power to resist it; for, as Cicero says, even those who most
controvert it, would yet that the books they write about it should visit
the light under their own names, and seek to derive glory from seeming
to despise it. All other things are communicable and fall into commerce:
we lend our goods and stake our lives for the necessity and service of
our friends; but to communicate a man's honour, and to robe another with
a man's own glory, is very rarely seen.
And yet we have some examples of that kind. Catulus Luctatius in the
Cimbrian war, having done all that in him lay to make his flying
soldiers face about upon the enemy, ran himself at last away with the
rest, and counterfeited the coward, to the end his men might rather seem
to follow their captain than to fly from the enemy; which was to abandon
his own reputation in order to cover the shame of others. When Charles
V. came into Provence in the year 1537, 'tis said that Antonio de Leva,
seeing the emperor positively resolved upon this expedition, and
believing it would redound very much to his honour, did, nevertheless,
very stiffly oppose it in the council, to the end that the entire glory
of that resolution should be attributed to his master, and that it might
be said his own wisdom and foresight had been such as that, contrary to
the opinion of all, he had brought about so great an enterprise; which
was to do him honour at his own expense. The Thracian ambassadors coming
to comfort Archileonida, the mother of Brasidas, upon the death of her
son, and commending him to that height as to say he had not left his
like behind him, she rejected this private and particular commendation
to attribute it to the public: "Tell me not that," said she; "I know the
city of Sparta has many citizens both greater and of greater worth than
he." In the battle of Crecy, the Prince of Wales, being then very young,
had the vanguard committed to him: the main stress of the battle
happened to be in that place, which made the lords who were with him,
finding themselves overmatched, send to King Edward to advance to their
relief. He inquired of the condition his son was in, and being answered
that he was alive and on horseback: "I should, then, do him wrong," said
the king, "now to go and deprive him of the honour of winning this
battle he has so long and so bravely sustained; what hazard soever he
runs, that shall be entirely his own"; and, accordingly, would neither
go nor send, knowing that if he went, it would be said all had been lost
without his succour, and that the honour of the victory would be wholly
attributed to him.
"Semper enim quod postremum adjectum est,
id rem totam videtur traxisse."
["For always that which is last added, seems to have accomplished
the whole affair."—Livy, xxvii. 45.]
Many at Rome thought, and would usually say, that the greatest of
Scipio's acts were in part due to Laelius, whose constant practice it
was still to advance and support Scipio's grandeur and renown, without
any care of his own. And Theopompus, king of Sparta, to him who told him
the republic could not miscarry since he knew so well how to command,
"Tis rather," answered he, "because the people know so well how to
obey." As women succeeding to peerages had, notwithstanding their sex,
the privilege to attend and give their votes in the trials that
appertained to the jurisdiction of peers; so the ecclesiastical peers,
notwithstanding their profession, were obliged to attend our kings in
their wars, not only with their friends and servants, but in their own
persons. As the Bishop of Beauvais did, who being with Philip Augustus
at the battle of Bouvines, had a notable share in that action; but he
did not think it fit for him to participate in the fruit and glory of
that violent and bloody trade. He with his own hand reduced several of
the enemy that day to his mercy, whom he delivered to the first
gentleman he met either to kill or receive them to quarter, referring
the whole execution to this other hand; and he did this with regard to
William, Earl of Salisbury, whom he gave up to Messire Jehan de Nesle.
With a like subtlety of conscience to that I have just named, he would
kill but not wound, and for that reason ever fought with a mace. And a
certain person of my time, being reproached by the king that he had laid
hands on a priest, stiffly and positively denied he had done any such
thing: the meaning of which was, he had cudgelled and kicked him.
CHAPTER XLII——OF THE INEQUALITY AMOUNGST US.
Plutarch says somewhere that he does not find so great a difference
betwixt beast and beast as he does betwixt man and man; which he says in
reference to the internal qualities and perfections of the soul. And, in
truth, I find so vast a distance betwixt Epaminondas, according to my
judgment of him, and some that I know, who are yet men of good sense,
that I could willingly enhance upon Plutarch, and say that there is more
difference betwixt such and such a man than there is betwixt such a man
and such a beast:
["Ah! how much may one man surpass another!"
—Terence, Eunuchus, ii. 2.]
and that there are as many and innumerable degrees of mind as there
are cubits betwixt this and heaven. But as touching the estimate of men,
'tis strange that, ourselves excepted, no other creature is esteemed
beyond its proper qualities; we commend a horse for his strength and
sureness of foot,
"Volucrem
Sic laudamus equum, facili cui plurima palma
Fervet, et exsultat rauco victoria circo,"
["So we praise the swift horse, for whose easy mastery many a hand
glows in applause, and victory exults in the hoarse circus.
—"Juvenal, viii. 57.]
and not for his rich caparison; a greyhound for his speed of heels,
not for his fine collar; a hawk for her wing, not for her gesses and
bells. Why, in like manner, do we not value a man for what is properly
his own? He has a great train, a beautiful palace, so much credit, so
many thousand pounds a year: all these are about him, but not in him.
You will not buy a pig in a poke: if you cheapen a horse, you will see
him stripped of his housing-cloths, you will see him naked and open to
your eye; or if he be clothed, as they anciently were wont to present
them to princes to sell, 'tis only on the less important parts, that you
may not so much consider the beauty of his colour or the breadth of his
crupper, as principally to examine his legs, eyes, and feet, which are
the members of greatest use:
"Regibus hic mos est: ubi equos mercantur, opertos
Inspiciunt; ne, si facies, ut saepe, decora
Molli fulta pede est, emptorem inducat hiantem"
["This is the custom of kings: when they buy horses, they have open
inspection, lest, if a fair head, as often chances, is supported by
a weak foot, it should tempt the gaping purchaser."
—Horace, Sat., i. 2, 86.]
why, in giving your estimate of a man, do you prize him wrapped and
muffled up in clothes? He then discovers nothing to you but such parts
as are not in the least his own, and conceals those by which alone one
may rightly judge of his value. 'Tis the price of the blade that you
inquire into, not of the scabbard: you would not peradventure bid a
farthing for him, if you saw him stripped. You are to judge him by
himself and not by what he wears; and, as one of the ancients very
pleasantly said: "Do you know why you repute him tall? You reckon withal
the height of his pattens."—[Seneca, Ep. 76.]—The pedestal is no part of
the statue. Measure him without his stilts; let him lay aside his
revenues and his titles; let him present himself in his shirt. Then
examine if his body be sound and sprightly, active and disposed to
perform its functions. What soul has he? Is she beautiful, capable, and
happily provided of all her faculties? Is she rich of what is her own,
or of what she has borrowed? Has fortune no hand in the affair? Can she,
without winking, stand the lightning of swords? is she indifferent
whether her life expire by the mouth or through the throat? Is she
settled, even and content? This is what is to be examined, and by that
you are to judge of the vast differences betwixt man and man. Is he:
"Sapiens, sibique imperiosus,
Quern neque pauperies, neque mors, neque vincula terrent;
Responsare cupidinibus, contemnere honores
Fortis; et in seipso totus teres atque rotundus,
Externi ne quid valeat per laeve morari;
In quem manca ruit semper fortuna?"
["The wise man, self-governed, whom neither poverty, nor death,
nor chains affright: who has the strength to resist his appetites
and to contemn honours: who is wholly self-contained: whom no
external objects affect: whom fortune assails in vain."
—Horace, Sat., ii. 7,]
such a man is five hundred cubits above kingdoms and duchies; he is
an absolute monarch in and to himself:
"Sapiens, . . . Pol! ipse fingit fortunam sibi;"
["The wise man is the master of his own fortune,"
—Plautus, Trin., ii. 2, 84.]
what remains for him to covet or desire?
"Nonne videmus,
Nil aliud sibi naturam latrare, nisi ut, quoi
Corpore sejunctus dolor absit, mente fruatur,
Jucundo sensu, cura semotu' metuque?"
["Do we not see that human nature asks no more for itself than
that, free from bodily pain, it may exercise its mind agreeably,
exempt from care and fear."—Lucretius, ii. 16.]
Compare with such a one the common rabble of mankind, stupid and
mean-spirited, servile, instable, and continually floating with the
tempest of various passions, that tosses and tumbles them to and fro,
and all depending upon others, and you will find a greater distance than
betwixt heaven and earth; and yet the blindness of common usage is such
that we make little or no account of it; whereas if we consider a
peasant and a king, a nobleman and a vassal, a magistrate and a private
man, a rich man and a poor, there appears a vast disparity, though they
differ no more, as a man may say, than in their breeches.
In Thrace the king was distinguished from his people after a very
pleasant and especial manner; he had a religion by himself, a god all
his own, and which his subjects were not to presume to adore, which was
Mercury, whilst, on the other hand, he disdained to have anything to do
with theirs, Mars, Bacchus, and Diana. And yet they are no other than
pictures that make no essential dissimilitude; for as you see actors in
a play representing the person of a duke or an emperor upon the stage,
and immediately after return to their true and original condition of
valets and porters, so the emperor, whose pomp and lustre so dazzle you
in public:
"Scilicet grandes viridi cum luce smaragdi
Auto includuntur, teriturque thalassina vestis
Assidue, et Veneris sudorem exercita potat;"
["Because he wears great emeralds richly set in gold, darting green
lustre; and the sea-blue silken robe, worn with pressure, and moist
with illicit love (and absorbs the sweat of Venus)."
—Lucretius, iv. 1123.]
do but peep behind the curtain, and you will see no thing more than
an ordinary man, and peradventure more contemptible than the meanest of
his subjects:
"Ille beatus introrsum est, istius bracteata felicitas est;"
["The one is happy in himself; the happiness of the other is
counterfeit."—Seneca, Ep., 115.]
cowardice, irresolution, ambition, spite, and envy agitate him as
much as another:
"Non enim gazae, neque consularis
Submovet lictor miseros tumultus
Mentis, et curas laqueata circum
Tecta volantes."
["For not treasures, nor the consular lictor, can remove the
miserable tumults of the mind, nor cares that fly about panelled
ceilings."—Horace, Od., ii. 16, 9.]
Care and fear attack him even in the centre of his battalions:
"Re veraque metus hominum curaeque sequaces
Nec metuunt sonitus armorum, nee fera tela;
Audacterque inter reges, rerumque potentes
Versantur, neque fulgorem reverentur ab auro."
["And in truth the fears and haunting cares of men fear not the
clash of arms nor points of darts, and mingle boldly with great
kings and men in authority, nor respect the glitter of gold."
—Lucretius, ii. 47.]
Do fevers, gout, and apoplexies spare him any more than one of us?
When old age hangs heavy upon his shoulders, can the yeomen of his guard
ease him of the burden? When he is astounded with the apprehension of
death, can the gentlemen of his bedchamber comfort and assure him? When
jealousy or any other caprice swims in his brain, can our compliments
and ceremonies restore him to his good-humour? The canopy embroidered
with pearl and gold he lies under has no virtue against a violent fit of
the colic:
"Nee calidae citius decedunt corpore febres
Textilibus si in picturis, ostroque rubenti
Jactaris, quam si plebeia in veste cubandum est."
["Nor do burning fevers quit you sooner if you are stretched on a
couch of rich tapestry and in a vest of purple dye, than if you be
in a coarse blanket."—Idem, ii. 34.]
The flatterers of Alexander the Great possessed him that he was the
son of Jupiter; but being one day wounded, and observing the blood
stream from his wound: "What say you now, my masters," said he, "is not
this blood of a crimson colour and purely human? This is not of the
complexion of that which Homer makes to issue from the wounded gods."
The poet Hermodorus had written a poem in honour of Antigonus, wherein
he called him the son of the sun: "He who has the emptying of my
close-stool," said Antigonus, "knows to the contrary." He is but a man
at best, and if he be deformed or ill-qualified from his birth, the
empire of the universe cannot set him to rights:
"Puellae
Hunc rapiant; quidquid calcaverit hic, rosa fiat,"
["Let girls carry him off; wherever he steps let there spring up a
rose!"—Persius, Sat., ii. 38.]
what of all that, if he be a fool? even pleasure and good fortune are
not relished without vigour and understanding:
"Haec perinde sunt, ut ilius animus; qui ea possidet
Qui uti scit, ei bona; illi, qui non uritur recte, mala."
["Things are, as is the mind of their possessor; who knows how to
use them, to him they are good; to him who abuses them, ill."
—Terence, Heart., i. 3, 21.]
Whatever the benefits of fortune are, they yet require a palate to
relish them. 'Tis fruition, and not possession, that renders us happy:
["'Tis not lands, or a heap of brass and gold, that has removed
fevers from the ailing body of the owner, or cares from his mind.
The possessor must be healthy, if he thinks to make good use of his
realised wealth. To him who is covetous or timorous his house and
estate are as a picture to a blind man, or a fomentation to a
gouty."—Horace, Ep., i. 2, 47.]
He is a sot, his taste is palled and flat; he no more enjoys what he
has than one that has a cold relishes the flavour of canary, or than a
horse is sensible of his rich caparison. Plato is in the right when he
tells us that health, beauty, vigour, and riches, and all the other
things called goods, are equally evil to the unjust as good to the just,
and the evil on the contrary the same. And therefore where the body and
the mind are in disorder, to what use serve these external conveniences:
considering that the least prick with a pin, or the least passion of the
soul, is sufficient to deprive one of the pleasure of being sole monarch
of the world. At the first twitch of the gout it signifies much to be
called Sir and Your Majesty!
"Totus et argento conflatus, totus et auro;"
["Wholly made up of silver and gold."—Tibullus, i. 2, 70.]
does he not forget his palaces and girandeurs? If he be angry, can
his being a prince keep him from looking red and looking pale, and
grinding his teeth like a madman? Now, if he be a man of parts and of
right nature, royalty adds very little to his happiness;
"Si ventri bene, si lateri est, pedibusque tuffs, nil
Divitix poterunt regales addere majus;"
["If it is well with thy belly, thy side and thy feet, regal wealth
will be able to add nothing."—Horace, Ep., i. 12, 5.]
he discerns 'tis nothing but counterfeit and gullery. Nay, perhaps he
would be of King Seleucus' opinion, that he who knew the weight of a
sceptre would not stoop to pick it up, if he saw it lying before him, so
great and painful are the duties incumbent upon a good king.—[Plutarch,
If a Sage should Meddle with Affairs of Stale, c. 12.]—Assuredly it can
be no easy task to rule others, when we find it so hard a matter to
govern ourselves; and as to dominion, that seems so charming, the
frailty of human judgment and the difficulty of choice in things that
are new and doubtful considered, I am very much of opinion that it is
far more easy and pleasant to follow than to lead; and that it is a
great settlement and satisfaction of mind to have only one path to walk
in, and to have none to answer for but a man's self;
"Ut satius multo jam sit parere quietum,
Quam regere imperio res velle."
["'Tis much better quietly to obey than wish to rule."
—Lucretius, V, 1126.]
To which we may add that saying of Cyrus, that no man was fit to rule
but he who in his own worth was of greater value than those he was to
govern; but King Hiero in Xenophon says further, that in the fruition
even of pleasure itself they are in a worse condition than private men;
forasmuch as the opportunities and facility they have of commanding
those things at will takes off from the delight that ordinary folks
enjoy:
"Pinguis amor, nimiumque patens, in taedia nobis
Vertitur, et, stomacho dulcis ut esca, nocet."
["Love in excess and too palpable turns to weariness, and, like
sweetmeats to the stomach, is injurious."—Ovid, Amoy., ii. 19, 25.]
Can we think that the singing boys of the choir take any great
delight in music? the satiety rather renders it troublesome and tedious
to them. Feasts, balls, masquerades and tiltings delight such as but
rarely see, and desire to see, them; but having been frequently at such
entertainments, the relish of them grows flat and insipid. Nor do women
so much delight those who make a common practice of the sport. He who
will not give himself leisure to be thirsty can never find the true
pleasure of drinking. Farces and tumbling tricks are pleasant to the
spectators, but a wearisome toil to those by whom they are performed.
And that this is so, we see that princes divert themselves sometimes in
disguising their quality, awhile to depose themselves, and to stoop to
the poor and ordinary way of living of the meanest of their people.
"Plerumque gratae divitibus vices
Mundaeque parvo sub lare pauperum
Coenae, sine aulaeis et ostro,
Soliicitam explicuere frontem."
["The rich are often pleased with variety; and the plain supper in a
poor cottage, without tapestry and purple, has relaxed the anxious
brow."—Horace, Od., iii. 29, 13.]
Nothing is so distasteful and clogging as abundance. What appetite
would not be baffled to see three hundred women at its mercy, as the
grand signor has in his seraglio? And, of his ancestors what fruition or
taste of sport did he reserve to himself, who never went hawking without
seven thousand falconers? And besides all this, I fancy that this lustre
of grandeur brings with it no little disturbance and uneasiness upon the
enjoyment of the most tempting pleasures; the great are too conspicuous
and lie too open to every one's view. Neither do I know to what end a
man should more require of them to conceal their errors, since what is
only reputed indiscretion in us, the people in them brand with the names
of tyranny and contempt of the laws, and, besides their proclivity to
vice, are apt to hold that it is a heightening of pleasure to them, to
insult over and to trample upon public observances. Plato, indeed, in
his Goygias, defines a tyrant to be one who in a city has licence to do
whatever his own will leads him to do; and by reason of this impunity,
the display and publication of their vices do ofttimes more mischief
than the vice itself. Every one fears to be pried into and overlooked;
but princes are so, even to their very gestures, looks and thoughts, the
people conceiving they have right and title to be judges of them besides
that the blemishes of the great naturally appear greater by reason of
the eminence and lustre of the place where they are seated, and that a
mole or a wart appears greater in them than a wide gash in others. And
this is the reason why the poets feign the amours of Jupiter to be
performed in the disguises of so many borrowed shapes, and that amongst
the many amorous practices they lay to his charge, there is only one, as
I remember, where he appears in his own majesty and grandeur.
But let us return to Hiero, who further complains of the
inconveniences he found in his royalty, in that he could not look abroad
and travel the world at liberty, being as it were a prisoner in the
bounds and limits of his own dominion, and that in all his actions he
was evermore surrounded with an importunate crowd. And in truth, to see
our kings sit all alone at table, environed with so many people prating
about them, and so many strangers staring upon them, as they always are,
I have often been moved rather to pity than to envy their condition.
King Alfonso was wont to say, that in this asses were in a better
condition than kings, their masters permitting them to feed at their own
ease and pleasure, a favour that kings cannot obtain of their servants.
And it has never come into my fancy that it could be of any great
benefit to the life of a man of sense to have twenty people prating
about him when he is at stool; or that the services of a man of ten
thousand livres a year, or that has taken Casale or defended Siena,
should be either more commodious or more acceptable to him, than those
of a good groom of the chamber who understands his place. The advantages
of sovereignty are in a manner but imaginary: every degree of fortune
has in it some image of principality. Caesar calls all the lords of
France, having free franchise within their own demesnes, roitelets or
petty kings; and in truth, the name of sire excepted, they go pretty far
towards kingship; for do but look into the provinces remote from court,
as Brittany for example; take notice of the train, the vassals, the
officers, the employments, service, ceremony, and state of a lord who
lives retired from court in his own house, amongst his own tenants and
servants; and observe withal the flight of his imagination; there is
nothing more royal; he hears talk of his master once a year, as of a
king of Persia, without taking any further recognition of him, than by
some remote kindred his secretary keeps in some register. And, to speak
the truth, our laws are easy enough, so easy that a gentleman of France
scarce feels the weight of sovereignty pinch his shoulders above twice
in his life. Real and effectual subjection only concerns such amongst us
as voluntarily thrust their necks under the yoke, and who design to get
wealth and honours by such services: for a man that loves his own
fireside, and can govern his house without falling by the ears with his
neighbours or engaging in suits of law, is as free as a Duke of Venice.
"Paucos servitus, plures servitutem tenent."
["Servitude enchains few, but many enchain themselves to
servitude."—Seneca, Ep., 22.]
But that which Hiero is most concerned at is, that he finds himself
stripped of all friendship, deprived of all mutual society, wherein the
true and most perfect fruition of human life consists. For what
testimony of affection and goodwill can I extract from him that owes me,
whether he will or no, all that he is able to do? Can I form any
assurance of his real respect to me, from his humble way of speaking and
submissive behaviour, when these are ceremonies it is not in his choice
to deny? The honour we receive from those that fear us is not honour;
those respects are due to royalty and not to me:
"Maximum hoc regni bonum est
Quod facta domini cogitur populus sui
Quam ferre, tam laudare."
["'Tis the greatest benefit of a kingdom that the people is forced
to commend, as well as to bear the acts of the ruler."
—Seneca, Thyestes, ii. i, 30.]
Do I not see that the wicked and the good king, he that is hated and
he that is beloved, have the one as much reverence paid him as the
other? My predecessor was, and my successor shall be, served with the
same ceremony and state. If my subjects do me no harm, 'tis no evidence
of any good affection; why should I look upon it as such, seeing it is
not in their power to do it if they would? No one follows me or obeys my
commands upon the account of any friendship, betwixt him and me; there
can be no contracting of friendship where there is so little relation
and correspondence: my own height has put me out of the familiarity of
and intelligence with men; there is too great disparity and
disproportion betwixt us. They follow me either upon the account of
decency and custom; or rather my fortune, than me, to increase their
own. All they say to me or do for me is but outward paint, appearance,
their liberty being on all parts restrained by the great power and
authority I have over them. I see nothing about me but what is
dissembled and disguised.
The Emperor Julian being one day applauded by his courtiers for his
exact justice: "I should be proud of these praises," said he, "did they
come from persons that durst condemn or disapprove the contrary, in case
I should do it." All the real advantages of princes are common to them
with men of meaner condition ('tis for the gods to mount winged horses
and feed upon ambrosia): they have no other sleep, nor other appetite
than we; the steel they arm themselves withal is of no better temper
than that we also use; their crowns neither defend them from the rain
nor the sun.
Diocletian, who wore a crown so fortunate and revered, resigned it to
retire to the felicity of a private life; and some time after the
necessity of public affairs requiring that he should reassume his
charge, he made answer to those who came to court him to it: "You would
not offer," said he, "to persuade me to this, had you seen the fine
order of the trees I have planted in my orchard, and the fair melons I
have sown in my garden."
In Anacharsis' opinion, the happiest state of government would be
where, all other things being equal, precedence should be measured out
by the virtues, and repulses by the vices of men.
When King Pyrrhus prepared for his expedition into Italy, his wise
counsellor Cyneas, to make him sensible of the vanity of his ambition:
"Well, sir," said he, "to what end do you make all this mighty
preparation?"—"To make myself master of Italy," replied the king. "And
what after that is done?" said Cyneas. "I will pass over into Gaul and
Spain," said the other. "And what then?"—"I will then go to subdue
Africa; and lastly, when I have brought the whole world to my
subjection, I will sit down and rest content at my own ease."
"For God sake, sir," replied Cyneas, "tell me what hinders that you
may not, if you please, be now in the condition you speak of? Why do you
not now at this instant settle yourself in the state you seem to aim at,
and spare all the labour and hazard you interpose?"
"Nimirum, quia non cognovit, qux esset habendi
Finis, et omnino quoad crescat vera voluptas."
["Forsooth because he does not know what should be the limit of
acquisition, and altogether how far real pleasure should increase."
—Lucretius, v. 1431]
I will conclude with an old versicle, that I think very apt to the
purpose:
"Mores cuique sui fingunt fortunam."
["Every man frames his own fortune."
—Cornelius Nepos, Life of Atticus]
CHAPTER XLIII——OF SUMPTUARY LAWS
The way by which our laws attempt to regulate idle and vain expenses
in meat and clothes, seems to be quite contrary to the end designed. The
true way would be to beget in men a contempt of silks and gold, as vain,
frivolous, and useless; whereas we augment to them the honours, and
enhance the value of such things, which, sure, is a very improper way to
create a disgust. For to enact that none but princes shall eat turbot,
shall wear velvet or gold lace, and interdict these things to the
people, what is it but to bring them into a greater esteem, and to set
every one more agog to eat and wear them? Let kings leave off these
ensigns of grandeur; they have others enough besides; those excesses are
more excusable in any other than a prince. We may learn by the example
of several nations better ways of exterior distinction of quality
(which, truly, I conceive to be very requisite in a state) enough,
without fostering to this purpose such corruption and manifest
inconvenience. 'Tis strange how suddenly and with how much ease custom
in these indifferent things establishes itself and becomes authority. We
had scarce worn cloth a year, in compliance with the court, for the
mourning of Henry II., but that silks were already grown into such
contempt with every one, that a man so clad was presently concluded a
citizen: silks were divided betwixt the physicians and surgeons, and
though all other people almost went in the same habit, there was,
notwithstanding, in one thing or other, sufficient distinction of the
several conditions of men. How suddenly do greasy chamois and linen
doublets become the fashion in our armies, whilst all neatness and
richness of habit fall into contempt? Let kings but lead the dance and
begin to leave off this expense, and in a month the business will be
done throughout the kingdom, without edict or ordinance; we shall all
follow. It should be rather proclaimed, on the contrary, that no one
should wear scarlet or goldsmiths' work but courtesans and tumblers.
Zeleucus by the like invention reclaimed the corrupted manners of the
Locrians. His laws were, that no free woman should be allowed any more
than one maid to follow her, unless she was drunk: nor was to stir out
of the city by night, wear jewels of gold about her, or go in an
embroidered robe, unless she was a professed and public prostitute;
that, bravos excepted, no man was to wear a gold ring, nor be seen in
one of those effeminate robes woven in the city of Miletus. By which
infamous exceptions he discreetly diverted his citizens from
superfluities and pernicious pleasures, and it was a project of great
utility to attract then by honour and ambition to their duty and
obedience.
Our kings can do what they please in such external reformations;
their own inclination stands in this case for a law:
"Quicquid principes faciunt, praecipere videntur."
["What princes themselves do, they seem to prescribe."
—Quintil., Declam., 3.]
Whatever is done at court passes for a rule through the rest of
France. Let the courtiers fall out with these abominable breeches, that
discover so much of those parts should be concealed; these great bellied
doublets, that make us look like I know not what, and are so unfit to
admit of arms; these long effeminate locks of hair; this foolish custom
of kissing what we present to our equals, and our hands in saluting
them, a ceremony in former times only due to princes. Let them not
permit that a gentleman shall appear in place of respect without his
sword, unbuttoned and untrussed, as though he came from the house of
office; and that, contrary to the custom of our forefathers and the
particular privilege of the nobles of this kingdom, we stand a long time
bare to them in what place soever, and the same to a hundred others, so
many tiercelets and quartelets of kings we have got nowadays and other
like vicious innovations: they will see them all presently vanish and
cried down. These are, 'tis true, but superficial errors; but they are
of ill augury, and enough to inform us that the whole fabric is crazy
and tottering, when we see the roughcast of our walls to cleave and
split.
Plato in his Laws esteems nothing of more pestiferous consequence to
his city than to give young men the liberty of introducing any change in
their habits, gestures, dances, songs, and exercises, from one form to
another; shifting from this to that, hunting after novelties, and
applauding the inventors; by which means manners are corrupted and the
old institutions come to be nauseated and despised. In all things,
saving only in those that are evil, a change is to be feared; even the
change of seasons, winds, viands, and humours. And no laws are in their
true credit, but such to which God has given so long a continuance that
no one knows their beginning, or that there ever was any other.
CHAPTER XLIV——OF SLEEP
Reason directs that we should always go the same way, but not always
at the same pace. And, consequently, though a wise man ought not so much
to give the reins to human passions as to let him deviate from the right
path, he may, notwithstanding, without prejudice to his duty, leave it
to them to hasten or to slacken his speed, and not fix himself like a
motionless and insensible Colossus. Could virtue itself put on flesh and
blood, I believe the pulse would beat faster going on to assault than in
going to dinner: that is to say, there is a necessity she should heat
and be moved upon this account. I have taken notice, as of an
extraordinary thing, of some great men, who in the highest enterprises
and most important affairs have kept themselves in so settled and serene
a calm, as not at all to break their sleep. Alexander the Great, on the
day assigned for that furious battle betwixt him and Darius, slept so
profoundly and so long in the morning, that Parmenio was forced to enter
his chamber, and coming to his bedside, to call him several times by his
name, the time to go to fight compelling him so to do. The Emperor Otho,
having put on a resolution to kill himself that night, after having
settled his domestic affairs, divided his money amongst his servants,
and set a good edge upon a sword he had made choice of for the purpose,
and now staying only to be satisfied whether all his friends had retired
in safety, he fell into so sound a sleep that the gentlemen of his
chamber heard him snore. The death of this emperor has in it
circumstances paralleling that of the great Cato, and particularly this
just related for Cato being ready to despatch himself, whilst he only
stayed his hand in expectation of the return of a messenger he had sent
to bring him news whether the senators he had sent away were put out
from the Port of Utica, he fell into so sound a sleep, that they heard
him snore in the next room; and the man, whom he had sent to the port,
having awakened him to let him know that the tempestuous weather had
hindered the senators from putting to sea, he despatched away another
messenger, and composing again himself in the bed, settled to sleep, and
slept till by the return of the last messenger he had certain
intelligence they were gone. We may here further compare him with
Alexander in the great and dangerous storm that threatened him by the
sedition of the tribune Metellus, who, attempting to publish a decree
for the calling in of Pompey with his army into the city at the time of
Catiline's conspiracy, was only and that stoutly opposed by Cato, so
that very sharp language and bitter menaces passed betwixt them in the
senate about that affair; but it was the next day, in the forenoon, that
the controversy was to be decided, where Metellus, besides the favour of
the people and of Caesar—at that time of Pompey's faction—was to appear
accompanied with a rabble of slaves and gladiators; and Cato only
fortified with his own courage and constancy; so that his relations,
domestics, and many virtuous people of his friends were in great
apprehensions for him; and to that degree, that some there were who
passed over the whole night without sleep, eating, or drinking, for the
danger they saw him running into; his wife and sisters did nothing but
weep and torment themselves in his house; whereas, he, on the contrary,
comforted every one, and after having supped after his usual manner,
went to bed, and slept profoundly till morning, when one of his
fellow-tribunes roused him to go to the encounter. The knowledge we have
of the greatness of this man's courage by the rest of his life, may
warrant us certainly to judge that his indifference proceeded from a
soul so much elevated above such accidents, that he disdained to let it
take any more hold of his fancy than any ordinary incident.
In the naval engagement that Augustus won of Sextus Pompeius in
Sicily, just as they were to begin the fight, he was so fast asleep that
his friends were compelled to wake him to give the signal of battle: and
this was it that gave Mark Antony afterwards occasion to reproach him
that he had not the courage so much as with open eyes to behold the
order of his own squadrons, and not to have dared to present himself
before the soldiers, till first Agrippa had brought him news of the
victory obtained. But as to the young Marius, who did much worse (for
the day of his last battle against Sylla, after he had marshalled his
army and given the word and signal of battle, he laid him down under the
shade of a tree to repose himself, and fell so fast asleep that the rout
and flight of his men could hardly waken him, he having seen nothing of
the fight), he is said to have been at that time so extremely spent and
worn out with labour and want of sleep, that nature could hold out no
longer. Now, upon what has been said, the physicians may determine
whether sleep be so necessary that our lives depend upon it: for we read
that King Perseus of Macedon, being prisoner at Rome, was killed by
being kept from sleep; but Pliny instances such as have lived long
without sleep. Herodotus speaks of nations where the men sleep and wake
by half-years, and they who write the life of the sage Epimenides affirm
that he slept seven-and-fifty years together.
CHAPTER XLV——OF THE BATTLE OF DREUX
[December 19, 1562, in which the Catholics, under the command of the
Duc de Guise and the Constable de Montmorenci, defeated the
Protestants, commanded by the Prince de Conde. See Sismondi, Hist.
des Francais, vol. xviii., p. 354.]
Our battle of Dreux is remarkable for several extraordinary
incidents; but such as have no great kindness for M. de Guise, nor much
favour his reputation, are willing to have him thought to blame, and
that his making a halt and delaying time with the forces he commanded,
whilst the Constable, who was general of the army, was racked through
and through with the enemy's artillery, his battalion routed, and
himself taken prisoner, is not to be excused; and that he had much
better have run the hazard of charging the enemy in flank, than staying
for the advantage of falling in upon the rear, to suffer so great and so
important a loss. But, besides what the event demonstrated, he who will
consider it without passion or prejudice will easily be induced to
confess that the aim and design, not of a captain only, but of every
private soldier, ought to regard the victory in general, and that no
particular occurrences, how nearly soever they may concern his own
interest, should divert him from that pursuit. Philopoemen, in an
encounter with Machanidas, having sent before a good strong party of his
archers and slingers to begin the skirmish, and these being routed and
hotly pursued by the enemy, who, pushing on the fortune of their arms,
and in that pursuit passing by the battalion where Philopoemen was,
though his soldiers were impatient to fall on, he did not think fit to
stir from his post nor to present himself to the enemy to relieve his
men, but having suffered these to be chased and cut in pieces before his
face, charged in upon the enemy's foot when he saw them left unprotected
by the horse, and notwithstanding that they were Lacedaemonians, yet
taking them in the nick, when thinking themselves secure of the victory,
they began to disorder their ranks; he did this business with great
facility, and then put himself in pursuit of Machanidas. Which case is
very like that of Monsieur de Guise.
In that bloody battle betwixt Agesilaus and the Boeotians, which
Xenophon, who was present at it, reports to be the sharpest that he had
ever seen, Agesilaus waived the advantage that fortune presented him, to
let the Boeotian battalions pass by and then to charge them in the rear,
how certain soever he might make himself of the victory, judging it
would rather be an effect of conduct than valour, to proceed that way;
and therefore, to show his prowess, rather chose with a marvellous
ardour of courage to charge them in the front; but he was well beaten
and well wounded for his pains, and constrained at last to disengage
himself, and to take the course he had at first neglected; opening his
battalion to give way to this torrent of Boeotians, and they being
passed by, taking notice that they marched in disorder, like men who
thought themselves out of danger, he pursued and charged them in flank;
yet could not so prevail as to bring it to so general a rout but that
they leisurely retreated, still facing about upon him till they had
retired to safety.
CHAPTER XLVI——OF NAMES
What variety of herbs soever are shufed together in the dish, yet the
whole mass is swallowed up under one name of a sallet. In like manner,
under the consideration of names, I will make a hodge-podge of divers
articles.
Every nation has certain names, that, I know not why, are taken in no
good sense, as with us, John, William, Benedict. In the genealogy of
princes, also, there seem to be certain names fatally affected, as the
Ptolemies of Egypt, the Henries in England, the Charleses in France, the
Baldwins in Flanders, and the Williams of our ancient Aquitaine, from
whence, 'tis said, the name of Guyenne has its derivation; which would
seem far fetched were there not as crude derivations in Plato himself.
Item, 'tis a frivolous thing in itself, but nevertheless worthy to be
recorded for the strangeness of it, that is written by an eyewitness,
that Henry, Duke of Normandy, son of Henry II., king of England, making
a great feast in France, the concourse of nobility and gentry was so
great, that being, for sport's sake, divided into troops, according to
their names, in the first troop, which consisted of Williams, there were
found an hundred and ten knights sitting at the table of that name,
without reckoning the ordinary gentlemen and servants.
It is as pleasant to distinguish the tables by the names of the
guests as it was in the Emperor Geta to distinguish the several courses
of his meat by the first letters of the meats themselves; so that those
that began with B were served up together, as brawn, beef, bream,
bustards, becca-ficos; and so of the others. Item, there is a saying
that it is a good thing to have a good name, that is to say, credit and
a good repute; but besides this, it is really convenient to have a
well-sounding name, such as is easy of pronunciation and easy to be
remembered, by reason that kings and other great persons do by that
means the more easily know and the more hardly forget us; and indeed of
our own servants we more frequently call and employ those whose names
are most ready upon the tongue. I myself have seen Henry II., when he
could not for his heart hit of a gentleman's name of our country of
Gascony, and moreover was fain to call one of the queen's maids of
honour by the general name of her race, her own family name being so
difficult to pronounce or remember; and Socrates thinks it worthy a
father's care to give fine names to his children.
Item,'tis said that the foundation of Notre Dame la Grande at
Poitiers took its original from hence that a debauched young fellow
formerly living in that place, having got to him a wench, and, at her
first coming in, asking her name, and being answered that it was Mary,
he felt himself so suddenly pierced through with the awe of religion and
the reverence to that sacred name of the Blessed Virgin, that he not
only immediately sent the girl away, but became a reformed man and so
continued the remainder of his life; and that, in consideration of this
miracle, there was erected upon the place where this young man's house
stood, first a chapel dedicated to our Lady and afterwards the church
that we now see standing there. This vocal and auricular reproof wrought
upon the conscience, and that right into the soul; this that follows,
insinuated itself merely by the senses. Pythagoras being in company with
some wild young fellows, and perceiving that, heated with the feast,
they comploted to go violate an honest house, commanded the singing
wench to alter her wanton airs; and by a solemn, grave, and spondaic
music, gently enchanted and laid asleep their ardour.
Item, will not posterity say that our modern reformation has been
wonderfully delicate and exact, in having not only combated errors and
vices, and filled the world with devotion, humility, obedience, peace,
and all sorts of virtue; but in having proceeded so far as to quarrel
with our ancient baptismal names of Charles, Louis, Francis, to fill the
world with Methuselahs, Ezekiels, and Malachis, names of a more
spiritual sound? A gentleman, a neighbour of mine, a great admirer of
antiquity, and who was always extolling the excellences of former times
in comparison with this present age of ours, did not, amongst the rest,
forget to dwell upon the lofty and magnificent sound of the gentleman's
names of those days, Don Grumedan, Quedregan, Agesilan, which, but to
hear named he conceived to denote other kind of men than Pierre,
Guillot, and Michel.
Item, I am mightily pleased with Jacques Amyot for leaving,
throughout a whole French oration, the Latin names entire, without
varying and garbling them to give them a French cadence. It seemed a
little harsh and rough at first; but already custom, by the authority of
his Plutarch, has overcome that novelty. I have often wished that such
as write histories in Latin would leave our names as they find them and
as they are; for in making Vaudemont into Vallemontanus, and
metamorphosing names to make them suit better with the Greek or Latin,
we know not where we are, and with the persons of the men lose the
benefit of the story.
To conclude, 'tis a scurvy custom and of very ill consequence that we
have in our kingdom of France to call every one by the name of his manor
or seigneury; 'tis the thing in the world that the most prejudices and
confounds families and descents. A younger brother of a good family,
having a manor left him by his father, by the name of which he has been
known and honoured, cannot handsomely leave it; ten years after his
decease it falls into the hand of a stranger, who does the same: do but
judge whereabouts we shall be concerning the knowledge of these men. We
need look no further for examples than our own royal family, where every
partition creates a new surname, whilst, in the meantime, the original
of the family is totally lost. There is so great liberty taken in these
mutations, that I have not in my time seen any one advanced by fortune
to any extraordinary condition who has not presently had genealogical
titles added to him, new and unknown to his father, and who has not been
inoculated into some illustrious stem by good luck; and the obscurest
families are the most apt for falsification. How many gentlemen have we
in France who by their own account are of royal extraction? more, I
think, than who will confess they are not. Was it not a pleasant passage
of a friend of mine? There were, several gentlemen assembled together
about the dispute of one seigneur with another; which other had, in
truth, some preeminence of titles and alliances above the ordinary
gentry. Upon the debate of this prerogative, every one, to make himself
equal to him, alleged, this one extraction, that another; this, the near
resemblance of name, that, of arms; another, an old worm-eaten patent;
the very least of them was great-grandchild to some foreign king. When
they came to sit down, to dinner, my friend, instead of taking his place
amongst them, retiring with most profound conges, entreated the company
to excuse him for having hitherto lived with them at the saucy rate of a
companion; but being now better informed of their quality, he would
begin to pay them the respect due to their birth and grandeur, and that
it would ill become him to sit down among so many princes—ending this
farce with a thousand reproaches: "Let us, in God's name, satisfy
ourselves with what our fathers were contented with, with what we are.
We are great enough, if we rightly understand how to maintain it. Let us
not disown the fortune and condition of our ancestors, and let us lay
aside these ridiculous pretences, that can never be wanting to any one
that has the impudence to allege them."
Arms have no more security than surnames. I bear azure powdered with
trefoils or, with a lion's paw of the same armed gules in fesse. What
privilege has this to continue particularly in my house? A son-in-law
will transport it into another family, or some paltry purchaser will
make them his first arms. There is nothing wherein there is more change
and confusion.
But this consideration leads me, perforce, into another subject. Let
us pry a little narrowly into, and, in God's name, examine upon what
foundation we erect this glory and reputation for which the world is
turned topsy-turvy: wherein do we place this renown that we hunt after
with so much pains? It is, in the end, Peter or William that carries it,
takes it into his possession, and whom it only concerns. O what a
valiant faculty is hope, that in a mortal subject, and in a moment,
makes nothing of usurping infinity, immensity, eternity, and of
supplying its master's indigence, at its pleasure, with all things he
can imagine or desire! Nature has given us this passion for a pretty toy
to play withal. And this Peter or William, what is it but a sound, when
all is done? or three or four dashes with a pen, so easy to be varied
that I would fain know to whom is to be attributed the glory of so many
victories, to Guesquin, to Glesquin, or to Gueaquin? and yet there would
be something of greater moment in the case than in Lucian, that Sigma
should serve Tau with a process; for
"Non levia aut ludicra petuntur
Praemia;"
["They aim at no slight or jocular rewards."—AEneid, xii. 764.]
the chase is there in very good earnest: the question is, which of
these letters is to be rewarded for so many sieges, battles, wounds,
imprisonments, and services done to the crown of France by this famous
constable? Nicholas Denisot—[Painter and poet, born at Le Mans,1515.]—
never concerned himself further than the letters of his name, of which
he has altered the whole contexture to build up by anagram the Count
d'Alsinois, whom he has handsomely endowed with the glory of his poetry
and painting. The historian Suetonius was satisfied with only the
meaning of his name, which made him cashier his father's surname, Lenis,
to leave Tranquillus successor to the reputation of his writings. Who
would believe that Captain Bayard should have no honour but what he
derives from the deeds of Peter Terrail; and that Antonio Iscalin should
suffer himself to his face to be robbed of the honour of so many
navigations and commands at sea and land by Captain Paulin and the Baron
de la Garde? Secondly, these are dashes of the pen common to a thousand
people. How many are there, in every family, of the same name and
surname? and how many more in several families, ages, and countries?
History tells us of three of the name of Socrates, of five Platos, of
eight Aristotles, of seven Xenophons, of twenty Demetrii, and of twenty
Theodores; and how many more she was not acquainted with we may imagine.
Who hinders my groom from calling himself Pompey the Great? But after
all, what virtue, what authority, or what secret springs are there that
fix upon my deceased groom, or the other Pompey, who had his head cut
off in Egypt, this glorious renown, and these so much honoured
flourishes of the pen, so as to be of any advantage to them?
"Id cinerem et manes credis curare sepultos?"
["Do you believe the dead regard such things?"—AEneid, iv. 34.]
What sense have the two companions in greatest esteem amongst me,
Epaminondas, of this fine verse that has been so many ages current in
his praise,
"Consiliis nostris laus est attrita Laconum;"
["The glory of the Spartans is extinguished by my plans.
—"Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., v. 17.]
or Africanus, of this other,
"A sole exoriente supra Maeotis Paludes
Nemo est qui factis me aequiparare queat."
["From where the sun rises over the Palus Maeotis, to where it sets,
there is no one whose acts can compare with mine"—Idem, ibid.]
Survivors indeed tickle themselves with these fine phrases, and by
them incited to jealousy and desire, inconsiderately and according to
their own fancy, attribute to the dead this their own feeling, vainly
flattering themselves that they shall one day in turn be capable of the
same character. However:
"Ad haec se
Romanus Graiusque, et Barbaras induperator
Erexit; caucus discriminis atque laboris
Inde habuit: tanto major famae sitis est, quam
Virtutis."
["For these the Roman, the Greek, and the Barbarian commander hath
aroused himself; he has incurred thence causes of danger and toil:
so much greater is the thirst for fame than for virtue."
—Juvenal, x. 137.]
CHAPTER XLVII——OF THE UNCERTAINTY OF OUR JUDGMENT
Well says this verse:
["There is everywhere much liberty of speech."—Iliad, xx. 249.]
For example:
["Hannibal conquered, but knew not how to make the best use of his
victorious venture."—Petrarch, Son., 83.]
Such as would improve this argument, and condemn the oversight of our
leaders in not pushing home the victory at Moncontour, or accuse the
King of Spain of not knowing how to make the best use of the advantage
he had against us at St. Quentin, may conclude these oversights to
proceed from a soul already drunk with success, or from a spirit which,
being full and overgorged with this beginning of good fortune, had lost
the appetite of adding to it, already having enough to do to digest what
it had taken in: he has his arms full, and can embrace no more: unworthy
of the benefit fortune has conferred upon him and the advantage she had
put into his hands: for what utility does he reap from it, if,
notwithstanding, he give his enemy respite to rally and make head
against him? What hope is there that he will dare at another time to
attack an enemy reunited and recomposed, and armed anew with anger and
revenge, who did not dare to pursue them when routed and unmanned by
fear?
"Dum fortuna calet, dum conficit omnia terror."
["Whilst fortune is fresh, and terror finishes all."
—Lucan, vii. 734.]
But withal, what better opportunity can he expect than that he has
lost? 'Tis not here, as in fencing, where the most hits gain the prize;
for so long as the enemy is on foot, the game is new to begin, and that
is not to be called a victory that puts not an end to the war. In the
encounter where Caesar had the worst, near the city of Oricum, he
reproached Pompey's soldiers that he had been lost had their general
known how to overcome; and afterwards clawed him in a very different
fashion when it came to his turn.
But why may not a man also argue, on the contrary, that it is the
effect of a precipitous and insatiate spirit not to know how to bound
and restrain its coveting; that it is to abuse the favours of God to
exceed the measure He has prescribed them: and that again to throw a
man's self into danger after a victory obtained is again to expose
himself to the mercy of fortune: that it is one of the greatest
discretions in the rule of war not to drive an enemy to despair? Sylla
and Marius in the social war, having defeated the Marsians, seeing yet a
body of reserve that, prompted by despair, was coming on like enraged
brutes to dash in upon them, thought it not convenient to stand their
charge. Had not Monsieur de Foix's ardour transported him so furiously
to pursue the remains of the victory of Ravenna, he had not obscured it
by his own death. And yet the recent memory of his example served to
preserve Monsieur d'Anguien from the same misfortune at the battle of
Serisoles. 'Tis dangerous to attack a man you have deprived of all means
to escape but by his arms, for necessity teaches violent resolutions:
"Gravissimi sunt morsus irritatae necessitatis."
["Irritated necessity bites deepest."—Portius Latro., Declam.]
"Vincitur haud gratis, jugulo qui provocat hostem."
["He is not readily beaten who provokes the enemy by shewing
his throat."—or: "He who presents himself to his foe, sells his
life dear."—Lucan, iv. 275.]
This was it that made Pharax withhold the King of Lacedaemon, who had
won a battle against the Mantineans, from going to charge a thousand
Argians, who had escaped in an entire body from the defeat, but rather
let them steal off at liberty that he might not encounter valour whetted
and enraged by mischance. Clodomir, king of Aquitaine, after his victory
pursuing Gondemar, king of Burgundy, beaten and making off as fast as he
could for safety, compelled him to face about and make head, wherein his
obstinacy deprived him of the fruit of his conquest, for he there lost
his life.
In like manner, if a man were to choose whether he would have his
soldiers richly and sumptuously accoutred or armed only for the
necessity of the matter in hand, this argument would step in to favour
the first, of which opinion was Sertorius, Philopcemen, Brutus, Caesar,
and others, that it is to a soldier an enflaming of courage and a spur
himself in brave attire; and withal a motive to be more obstinate in
fight, having his arms, which are in a manner his estate and whole
inheritance to defend; which is the reason, says Xenophon, why those of
Asia carried their wives and concubines, with their choicest jewels and
greatest wealth, along with them to the wars. But then these arguments
would be as ready to stand up for the other side; that a general ought
rather to lessen in his men their solicitude of preserving themselves
than to increase it; that by such means they will be in a double fear of
hazarding their persons, as it will be a double temptation to the enemy
to fight with greater resolution where so great booty and so rich spoils
are to be obtained; and this very thing has been observed in former
times, notably to encourage the Romans against the Samnites. Antiochus,
shewing Hannibal the army he had raised, wonderfully splendid and rich
in all sorts of equipage, asked him if the Romans would be satisfied
with that army? "Satisfied," replied the other, "yes, doubtless, were
their avarice never so great." Lycurgus not only forbad his soldiers all
manner of bravery in their equipage, but, moreover, to strip their
conquered enemies, because he would, as he said, that poverty and
frugality should shine with the rest of the battle.
At sieges and elsewhere, where occasion draws us near to the enemy,
we willingly suffer our men to brave, rate, and affront him with all
sorts of injurious language; and not without some colour of reason: for
it is of no little consequence to take from them all hopes of mercy and
composition, by representing to them that there is no fair quarter to be
expected from an enemy they have incensed to that degree, nor other
remedy remaining but in victory. And yet Vitellius found himself
deceived in this way of proceeding; for having to do with Otho, weaker
in the valour of his soldiers, long unaccustomed to war and effeminated
with the delights of the city, he so nettled them at last with injurious
language, reproaching them with cowardice and regret for the mistresses
and entertainments they had left behind at Rome, that by this means he
inspired them with such resolution as no exhortation had had the power
to have done, and himself made them fall upon him, with whom their own
captains before could by no means prevail. And, indeed, when they are
injuries that touch to the quick, it may very well fall out that he who
went but unwillingly to work in the behalf of his prince will fall to't
with another sort of mettle when the quarrel is his own.
Considering of how great importance is the preservation of the
general of an army, and that the universal aim of an enemy is levelled
directly at the head, upon which all the others depend, the course seems
to admit of no dispute, which we know has been taken by so many great
captains, of changing their habit and disguising their persons upon the
point of going to engage. Nevertheless, the inconvenience a man by so
doing runs into is not less than that he thinks to avoid; for the
captain, by this means being concealed from the knowledge of his own
men, the courage they should derive from his presence and example
happens by degrees to cool and to decay; and not seeing the wonted marks
and ensigns of their leader, they presently conclude him either dead, or
that, despairing of the business, he is gone to shift for himself. And
experience shows us that both these ways have been successful and
otherwise. What befell Pyrrhus in the battle he fought against the
Consul Levinus in Italy will serve us to both purposes; for though by
shrouding his person under the armour of Megacles and making him wear
his own, he undoubtedly preserved his own life, yet, by that very means,
he was withal very near running into the other mischief of losing the
battle. Alexander, Caesar, and Lucullus loved to make themselves known
in a battle by rich accoutrements and armour of a particular lustre and
colour: Agis, Agesilaus, and that great Gilippus, on the contrary, used
to fight obscurely armed, and without any imperial attendance or
distinction.
Amongst other oversights Pompey is charged withal at the battle of
Pharsalia, he is condemned for making his army stand still to receive
the enemy's charge; by "reason that" (I shall here steal Plutarch's own
words, which are better than mine) "he by so doing deprived himself of
the violent impression the motion of running adds to the first shock of
arms, and hindered that clashing of the combatants against one another
which is wont to give them greater impetuosity and fury; especially when
they come to rush in with their utmost vigour, their courages increasing
by the shouts and the career; 'tis to render the soldiers' ardour, as a
man may say, more reserved and cold." This is what he says. But if
Caesar had come by the worse, why might it not as well have been urged
by another, that, on the contrary, the strongest and most steady posture
of fighting is that wherein a man stands planted firm without motion;
and that they who are steady upon the march, closing up, and reserving
their force within themselves for the push of the business, have a great
advantage against those who are disordered, and who have already spent
half their breath in running on precipitately to the charge? Besides
that an army is a body made up of so many individual members, it is
impossible for it to move in this fury with so exact a motion as not to
break the order of battle, and that the best of them are not engaged
before their fellows can come on to help them. In that unnatural battle
betwixt the two Persian brothers, the Lacedaemonian Clearchus, who
commanded the Greeks of Cyrus' party, led them on softly and without
precipitation to the charge; but, coming within fifty paces, hurried
them on full speed, hoping in so short a career both to keep their order
and to husband their breath, and at the same time to give the advantage
of impetuosity and impression both to their persons and their missile
arms. Others have regulated this question as to their armies thus if
your enemy come full drive upon you, stand firm to receive him; if he
stand to receive you, run full drive upon him.
In the expedition of the Emperor Charles V. into Provence, King
Francis was put to choose either to go meet him in Italy or to await him
in his own dominions; wherein, though he very well considered of how
great advantage it was to preserve his own territory entire and clear
from the troubles of war, to the end that, being unexhausted of its
stores, it might continually supply men and money at need; that the
necessity of war requires at every turn to spoil and lay waste the
country before us, which cannot very well be done upon one's own; to
which may be added, that the country people do not so easily digest such
a havoc by those of their own party as from an enemy, so that seditions
and commotions might by such means be kindled amongst us; that the
licence of pillage and plunder (which are not to be tolerated at home)
is a great ease and refreshment against the fatigues and sufferings of
war; and that he who has no other prospect of gain than his bare pay
will hardly be kept from running home, being but two steps from his wife
and his own house; that he who lays the cloth is ever at the charge of
the feast; that there is more alacrity in assaulting than defending; and
that the shock of a battle's loss in our own bowels is so violent as to
endanger the disjointing of the whole body, there being no passion so
contagious as that of fear, that is so easily believed, or that so
suddenly diffuses itself; and that the cities that should hear the
rattle of this tempest at their gates, that should take in their
captains and soldiers yet trembling and out of breath, would be in
danger in this heat and hurry to precipitate themselves upon some
untoward resolution: notwithstanding all this, so it was that he chose
to recall the forces he had beyond the mountains and to suffer the enemy
to come to him. For he might, on the other hand, imagine that, being at
home and amongst his friends, he could not fail of plenty of all manner
of conveniences; the rivers and passes he had at his devotion would
bring him in both provisions and money in all security, and without the
trouble of convoy; that he should find his subjects by so much the more
affectionate to him, by how much their danger was more near and
pressing; that having so many cities and barriers to secure him, it
would be in his power to give the law of battle at his own opportunity
and advantage; and that, if it pleased him to delay the time, under
cover and at his ease he might see his enemy founder and defeat himself
with the difficulties he was certain to encounter, being engaged in a
hostile country, where before, behind, and on every side war would be
made upon him; no means to refresh himself or to enlarge his quarters,
should diseases infest them, or to lodge his wounded men in safety; no
money, no victuals, but at the point of the lance; no leisure to repose
and take breath; no knowledge of the ways or country to secure him from
ambushes and surprises; and in case of losing a battle, no possible
means of saving the remains. Neither is there want of example in both
these cases.
Scipio thought it much better to go and attack his enemy's
territories in Africa than to stay at home to defend his own and to
fight him in Italy, and it succeeded well with him. But, on the
contrary, Hannibal in the same war ruined himself by abandoning the
conquest of a foreign country to go and defend his own. The Athenians
having left the enemy in their own dominions to go over into Sicily,
were not favoured by fortune in their design; but Agathocles, king of
Syracuse, found her favourable to him when he went over into Africa and
left the war at home.
By which examples we are wont to conclude, and with some reason, that
events, especially in war, for the most part depend upon fortune, who
will not be governed by nor submit unto human reasons and prudence,
according to the poet:
"Et male consultis pretium est: prudentia fallit
Nec fortune probat causas, sequiturque merentes,
Sed vaga per cunctos nullo discrimine fertur.
Scilicet est aliud, quod nos cogatque regatque
Majus, et in proprias ducat mortalia leges."
["And there is value in ill counsel: prudence deceives: nor does
fortune inquire into causes, nor aid the most deserving, but turns
hither and thither without discrimination. Indeed there is a
greater power which directs and rules us, and brings mortal affairs
under its own laws."—Manilius, iv. 95.]
But, to take the thing right, it should seem that our counsels and
deliberations depend as much upon fortune as anything else we do, and
that she engages also our arguments in her uncertainty and confusion.
"We argue rashly and adventurously," says Timaeus in Plato, "by reason
that, as well as ourselves, our discourses have great participation in
the temerity of chance."
CHAPTER XLVIII——OF WAR HORSES, OR DESTRIERS
I here have become a grammarian, I who never learned any language but
by rote, and who do not yet know adjective, conjunction, or ablative. I
think I have read that the Romans had a sort of horses by them called
'funales' or 'dextrarios', which were either led horses, or horses laid
on at several stages to be taken fresh upon occasion, and thence it is
that we call our horses of service 'destriers'; and our romances
commonly use the phrase of 'adestrer' for 'accompagner', to accompany.
They also called those that were trained in such sort, that running full
speed, side by side, without bridle or saddle, the Roman gentlemen,
armed at all pieces, would shift and throw themselves from one to the
other, 'desultorios equos'. The Numidian men-at-arms had always a led
horse in one hand, besides that they rode upon, to change in the heat of
battle:
"Quibus, desultorum in modum, binos trahentibus equos, inter
acerrimam saepe pugnam, in recentem equum, ex fesso, armatis
transultare mos erat: tanta velocitas ipsis, tamque docile
equorum genus."
["To whom it was a custom, leading along two horses, often in the
hottest fight, to leap armed from a tired horse to a fresh one; so
active were the men, and the horses so docile."—Livy, xxiii. 29.]
There are many horses trained to help their riders so as to run upon
any one, that appears with a drawn sword, to fall both with mouth and
heels upon any that front or oppose them: but it often happens that they
do more harm to their friends than to their enemies; and, moreover, you
cannot loose them from their hold, to reduce them again into order, when
they are once engaged and grappled, by which means you remain at the
mercy of their quarrel. It happened very ill to Artybius, general of the
Persian army, fighting, man to man, with Onesilus, king of Salamis, to
be mounted upon a horse trained after this manner, it being the occasion
of his death, the squire of Onesilus cleaving the horse down with a
scythe betwixt the shoulders as it was reared up upon his master. And
what the Italians report, that in the battle of Fornova, the horse of
Charles VIII., with kicks and plunges, disengaged his master from the
enemy that pressed upon him, without which he had been slain, sounds
like a very great chance, if it be true.
[In the narrative which Philip de Commines has given of this battle,
in which he himself was present (lib. viii. ch. 6), he tells us
of wonderful performances by the horse on which the king was
mounted. The name of the horse was Savoy, and it was the most
beautiful horse he had ever seen. During the battle the king was
personally attacked, when he had nobody near him but a valet de
chambre, a little fellow, and not well armed. "The king," says
Commines, "had the best horse under him in the world, and therefore
he stood his ground bravely, till a number of his men, not a great
way from him, arrived at the critical minute."]
The Mamalukes make their boast that they have the most ready horses
of any cavalry in the world; that by nature and custom they were taught
to know and distinguish the enemy, and to fall foul upon them with mouth
and heels, according to a word or sign given; as also to gather up with
their teeth darts and lances scattered upon the field, and present them
to their riders, on the word of command. 'T is said, both of Caesar and
Pompey, that amongst their other excellent qualities they were both very
good horsemen, and particularly of Caesar, that in his youth, being
mounted on the bare back, without saddle or bridle, he could make the
horse run, stop, and turn, and perform all its airs, with his hands
behind him. As nature designed to make of this person, and of Alexander,
two miracles of military art, so one would say she had done her utmost
to arm them after an extraordinary manner for every one knows that
Alexander's horse, Bucephalus, had a head inclining to the shape of a
bull; that he would suffer himself to be mounted and governed by none
but his master, and that he was so honoured after his death as to have a
city erected to his name. Caesar had also one which had forefeet like
those of a man, his hoofs being divided in the form of fingers, which
likewise was not to be ridden, by any but Caesar himself, who, after his
death, dedicated his statue to the goddess Venus.
I do not willingly alight when I am once on horseback, for it is the
place where, whether well or sick, I find myself most at ease. Plato
recommends it for health, as also Pliny says it is good for the stomach
and the joints. Let us go further into this matter since here we are.
We read in Xenophon a law forbidding any one who was master of a
horse to travel on foot. Trogus Pompeius and Justin say that the
Parthians were wont to perform all offices and ceremonies, not only in
war but also all affairs whether public or private, make bargains,
confer, entertain, take the air, and all on horseback; and that the
greatest distinction betwixt freemen and slaves amongst them was that
the one rode on horseback and the other went on foot, an institution of
which King Cyrus was the founder.
There are several examples in the Roman history (and Suetonius more
particularly observes it of Caesar) of captains who, on pressing
occasions, commanded their cavalry to alight, both by that means to take
from them all hopes of flight, as also for the advantage they hoped in
this sort of fight.
"Quo baud dubie superat Romanus,"
["Wherein the Roman does questionless excel."—Livy, ix. 22.]
says Livy. And so the first thing they did to prevent the mutinies
and insurrections of nations of late conquest was to take from them
their arms and horses, and therefore it is that we so often meet in
Caesar:
"Arma proferri, jumenta produci, obsides dari jubet."
["He commanded the arms to be produced, the horses brought out,
hostages to be given."—De Bello Gall., vii. II.]
The Grand Signior to this day suffers not a Christian or a Jew to
keep a horse of his own throughout his empire.
Our ancestors, and especially at the time they had war with the
English, in all their greatest engagements and pitched battles fought
for the most part on foot, that they might have nothing but their own
force, courage, and constancy to trust to in a quarrel of so great
concern as life and honour. You stake (whatever Chrysanthes in Xenophon
says to the contrary) your valour and your fortune upon that of your
horse; his wounds or death bring your person into the same danger; his
fear or fury shall make you reputed rash or cowardly; if he have an ill
mouth or will not answer to the spur, your honour must answer for it.
And, therefore, I do not think it strange that those battles were more
firm and furious than those that are fought on horseback:
"Caedebant pariter, pariterque ruebant
Victores victique; neque his fuga nota, neque illis."
["They fought and fell pell-mell, victors and vanquished; nor was
flight thought of by either."—AEneid, x. 756.]
Their battles were much better disputed. Nowadays there are nothing
but routs:
"Primus clamor atque impetus rem decernit."
["The first shout and charge decides the business."—Livy, xxv. 41.]
And the means we choose to make use of in so great a hazard should be
as much as possible at our own command: wherefore I should advise to
choose weapons of the shortest sort, and such of which we are able to
give the best account. A man may repose more confidence in a sword he
holds in his hand than in a bullet he discharges out of a pistol,
wherein there must be a concurrence of several circumstances to make it
perform its office, the powder, the stone, and the wheel: if any of
which fail it endangers your fortune. A man himself strikes much surer
than the air can direct his blow:
"Et, quo ferre velint, permittere vulnera ventis
Ensis habet vires; et gens quaecumque virorum est,
Bella gerit gladiis."
["And so where they choose to carry [the arrows], the winds allow
the wounds; the sword has strength of arm: and whatever nation of
men there is, they wage war with swords."—Lucan, viii. 384.]
But of that weapon I shall speak more fully when I come to compare
the arms of the ancients with those of modern use; only, by the way, the
astonishment of the ear abated, which every one grows familiar with in a
short time, I look upon it as a weapon of very little execution, and
hope we shall one day lay it aside. That missile weapon which the
Italians formerly made use of both with fire and by sling was much more
terrible: they called a certain kind of javelin, armed at the point with
an iron three feet long, that it might pierce through and through an
armed man, Phalarica, which they sometimes in the field darted by hand,
sometimes from several sorts of engines for the defence of beleaguered
places; the shaft being rolled round with flax, wax, rosin, oil, and
other combustible matter, took fire in its flight, and lighting upon the
body of a man or his target, took away all the use of arms and limbs.
And yet, coming to close fight, I should think they would also damage
the assailant, and that the camp being as it were planted with these
flaming truncheons, would produce a common inconvenience to the whole
crowd:
"Magnum stridens contorta Phalarica venit,
Fulminis acta modo."
["The Phalarica, launched like lightning, flies through
the air with a loud rushing sound."—AEneid, ix. 705.]
They had, moreover, other devices which custom made them perfect in
(which seem incredible to us who have not seen them), by which they
supplied the effects of our powder and shot. They darted their spears
with so great force, as ofttimes to transfix two targets and two armed
men at once, and pin them together. Neither was the effect of their
slings less certain of execution or of shorter carriage:
["Culling round stones from the beach for their slings; and with
these practising over the waves, so as from a great distance to
throw within a very small circuit, they became able not only to
wound an enemy in the head, but hit any other part at pleasure."
—Livy, xxxviii. 29.]
Their pieces of battery had not only the execution but the thunder of
our cannon also:
"Ad ictus moenium cum terribili sonitu editos,
pavor et trepidatio cepit."
["At the battery of the walls, performed with a terrible noise,
the defenders began to fear and tremble."—Idem, ibid., 5.]
The Gauls, our kinsmen in Asia, abominated these treacherous missile
arms, it being their use to fight, with greater bravery, hand to hand:
["They are not so much concerned about large gashes-the bigger and
deeper the wound, the more glorious do they esteem the combat but
when they find themselves tormented by some arrow-head or bullet
lodged within, but presenting little outward show of wound,
transported with shame and anger to perish by so imperceptible a
destroyer, they fall to the ground."—-Livy, xxxviii. 21.]
A pretty description of something very like an arquebuse-shot. The
ten thousand Greeks in their long and famous retreat met with a nation
who very much galled them with great and strong bows, carrying arrows so
long that, taking them up, one might return them back like a dart, and
with them pierce a buckler and an armed man through and through. The
engines, that Dionysius invented at Syracuse to shoot vast massy darts
and stones of a prodigious greatness with so great impetuosity and at so
great a distance, came very near to our modern inventions.
But in this discourse of horses and horsemanship, we are not to
forget the pleasant posture of one Maistre Pierre Pol, a doctor of
divinity, upon his mule, whom Monstrelet reports always to have ridden
sideways through the streets of Paris like a woman. He says also,
elsewhere, that the Gascons had terrible horses, that would wheel in
their full speed, which the French, Picards, Flemings, and Brabanters
looked upon as a miracle, "having never seen the like before," which are
his very words.
Caesar, speaking of the Suabians: "in the charges they make on
horseback," says he, "they often throw themselves off to fight on foot,
having taught their horses not to stir in the meantime from the place,
to which they presently run again upon occasion; and according to their
custom, nothing is so unmanly and so base as to use saddles or pads, and
they despise such as make use of those conveniences: insomuch that,
being but a very few in number, they fear not to attack a great many."
That which I have formerly wondered at, to see a horse made to perform
all his airs with a switch only and the reins upon his neck, was common
with the Massilians, who rid their horses without saddle or bridle:
"Et gens, quae nudo residens Massylia dorso,
Ora levi flectit, fraenorum nescia, virga."
["The Massylians, mounted on the bare backs of their horses,
bridleless, guide them by a mere switch."—Lucan, iv. 682.]
"Et Numidae infraeni cingunt."
["The Numidians guiding their horses without bridles."
—AEneid, iv. 41.]
"Equi sine fraenis, deformis ipse cursus,
rigida cervice et extento capite currentium."
["The career of a horse without a bridle is ungraceful; the neck
extended stiff, and the nose thrust out."—Livy, xxxv. II.]
King Alfonso,—[Alfonso XI., king of Leon and Castile, died 1350.]— he
who first instituted the Order of the Band or Scarf in Spain, amongst
other rules of the order, gave them this, that they should never ride
mule or mulet, upon penalty of a mark of silver; this I had lately out
of Guevara's Letters. Whoever gave these the title of Golden Epistles
had another kind of opinion of them than I have. The Courtier says, that
till his time it was a disgrace to a gentleman to ride on one of these
creatures: but the Abyssinians, on the contrary, the nearer they are to
the person of Prester John, love to be mounted upon large mules, for the
greatest dignity and grandeur.
Xenophon tells us, that the Assyrians were fain to keep their horses
fettered in the stable, they were so fierce and vicious; and that it
required so much time to loose and harness them, that to avoid any
disorder this tedious preparation might bring upon them in case of
surprise, they never sat down in their camp till it was first well
fortified with ditches and ramparts. His Cyrus, who was so great a
master in all manner of horse service, kept his horses to their due
work, and never suffered them to have anything to eat till first they
had earned it by the sweat of some kind of exercise. The Scythians when
in the field and in scarcity of provisions used to let their horses
blood, which they drank, and sustained themselves by that diet:
"Venit et epoto Sarmata pastus equo."
["The Scythian comes, who feeds on horse-flesh"
—Martial, De Spectaculis Libey, Epigr. iii. 4.]
Those of Crete, being besieged by Metellus, were in so great
necessity for drink that they were fain to quench their thirst with
their horses urine.—[Val. Max., vii. 6, ext. 1.]
To shew how much cheaper the Turkish armies support themselves than
our European forces, 'tis said that besides the soldiers drink nothing
but water and eat nothing but rice and salt flesh pulverised (of which
every one may easily carry about with him a month's provision), they
know how to feed upon the blood of their horses as well as the Muscovite
and Tartar, and salt it for their use.
These new-discovered people of the Indies [Mexico and Yucatan D.W.],
when the Spaniards first landed amongst them, had so great an opinion
both of the men and horses, that they looked upon the first as gods and
the other as animals ennobled above their nature; insomuch that after
they were subdued, coming to the men to sue for peace and pardon, and to
bring them gold and provisions, they failed not to offer of the same to
the horses, with the same kind of harangue to them they had made to the
others: interpreting their neighing for a language of truce and
friendship.
In the other Indies, to ride upon an elephant was the first and royal
place of honour; the second to ride in a coach with four horses; the
third to ride upon a camel; and the last and least honour to be carried
or drawn by one horse only. Some one of our late writers tells us that
he has been in countries in those parts where they ride upon oxen with
pads, stirrups, and bridles, and very much at their ease.
Quintus Fabius Maximus Rullianus, in a battle with the Samnites,
seeing his horse, after three or four charges, had failed of breaking
into the enemy's battalion, took this course, to make them unbridle all
their horses and spur their hardest, so that having nothing to check
their career, they might through weapons and men open the way to his
foot, who by that means gave them a bloody defeat. The same command was
given by Quintus Fulvius Flaccus against the Celtiberians:
["You will do your business with greater advantage of your horses'
strength, if you send them unbridled upon the enemy, as it is
recorded the Roman horse to their great glory have often done; their
bits being taken off, they charged through and again back through
the enemy's ranks with great slaughter, breaking down all their
spears."—Idem, xl. 40.]
The Duke of Muscovy was anciently obliged to pay this reverence to
the Tartars, that when they sent an embassy to him he went out to meet
them on foot, and presented them with a goblet of mares' milk (a
beverage of greatest esteem amongst them), and if, in drinking, a drop
fell by chance upon their horse's mane, he was bound to lick it off with
his tongue. The army that Bajazet had sent into Russia was overwhelmed
with so dreadful a tempest of snow, that to shelter and preserve
themselves from the cold, many killed and embowelled their horses, to
creep into their bellies and enjoy the benefit of that vital heat.
Bajazet, after that furious battle wherein he was overthrown by
Tamerlane, was in a hopeful way of securing his own person by the
fleetness of an Arabian mare he had under him, had he not been
constrained to let her drink her fill at the ford of a river in his way,
which rendered her so heavy and indisposed, that he was afterwards
easily overtaken by those that pursued him. They say, indeed, that to
let a horse stale takes him off his mettle, but as to drinking, I should
rather have thought it would refresh him.
Croesus, marching his army through certain waste lands near Sardis,
met with an infinite number of serpents, which the horses devoured with
great appetite, and which Herodotus says was a prodigy of ominous
portent to his affairs.
We call a horse entire, that has his mane and ears so, and no other
will pass muster. The Lacedaemonians, having defeated the Athenians in
Sicily, returning triumphant from the victory into the city of Syracuse,
amongst other insolences, caused all the horses they had taken to be
shorn and led in triumph. Alexander fought with a nation called Dahas,
whose discipline it was to march two and two together armed on one
horse, to the war; and being in fight, one of them alighted, and so they
fought on horseback and on foot, one after another by turns.
I do not think that for graceful riding any nation in the world
excels the French. A good horseman, according to our way of speaking,
seems rather to have respect to the courage of the man than address in
riding. Of all that ever I saw, the most knowing in that art, who had
the best seat and the best method in breaking horses, was Monsieur de
Carnavalet, who served our King Henry II.
I have seen a man ride with both his feet upon the saddle, take off
his saddle, and at his return take it up again and replace it, riding
all the while full speed; having galloped over a cap, make at it very
good shots backwards with his bow; take up anything from the ground,
setting one foot on the ground and the other in the stirrup: with twenty
other ape's tricks, which he got his living by.
There has been seen in my time at Constantinople two men upon one
horse, who, in the height of its speed, would throw themselves off and
into the saddle again by turn; and one who bridled and saddled his horse
with nothing but his teeth; an other who betwixt two horses, one foot
upon one saddle and the other upon another, carrying the other man upon
his shoulders, would ride full career, the other standing bolt upright
upon and making very good shots with his bow; several who would ride
full speed with their heels upward, and their heads upon the saddle
betwixt several scimitars, with the points upwards, fixed in the
harness. When I was a boy, the prince of Sulmona, riding an unbroken
horse at Naples, prone to all sorts of action, held reals—[A small coin
of Spain, the Two Sicilies, &c.]—under his knees and toes, as if they
had been nailed there, to shew the firmness of his seat.
CHAPTER XLIX——OF ANCIENT CUSTOMS
I should willingly pardon our people for admitting no other pattern
or rule of perfection than their own peculiar manners and customs; for
'tis a common vice, not of the vulgar only, but almost of all men, to
walk in the beaten road their ancestors have trod before them. I am
content, when they see Fabricius or Laelius, that they look upon their
countenance and behaviour as barbarous, seeing they are neither clothed
nor fashioned according to our mode. But I find fault with their
singular indiscretion in suffering themselves to be so blinded and
imposed upon by the authority of the present usage as every month to
alter their opinion, if custom so require, and that they should so vary
their judgment in their own particular concern. When they wore the busk
of their doublets up as high as their breasts, they stiffly maintained
that they were in their proper place; some years after it was slipped
down betwixt their thighs, and then they could laugh at the former
fashion as uneasy and intolerable. The fashion now in use makes them
absolutely condemn the other two with so great resolution and so
universal consent, that a man would think there was a certain kind of
madness crept in amongst them, that infatuates their understandings to
this strange degree. Now, seeing that our change of fashions is so
prompt and sudden, that the inventions of all the tailors in the world
cannot furnish out new whim-whams enow to feed our vanity withal, there
will often be a necessity that the despised forms must again come in
vogue, these immediately after fall into the same contempt; and that the
same judgment must, in the space of fifteen or twenty years, take up
half-a-dozen not only divers but contrary opinions, with an incredible
lightness and inconstancy; there is not any of us so discreet, who
suffers not himself to be gulled with this contradiction, and both in
external and internal sight to be insensibly blinded.
I wish to muster up here some old customs that I have in memory, some
of them the same with ours, the others different, to the end that,
bearing in mind this continual variation of human things, we may have
our judgment more clearly and firmly settled.
The thing in use amongst us of fighting with rapier and cloak was in
practice amongst the Romans also:
"Sinistras sagis involvunt, gladiosque distringunt,"
["They wrapt their cloaks upon the left arm, and drew their
swords."—De Bello Civili, i. 75.]
says Caesar; and he observes a vicious custom of our nation, that
continues yet amongst us, which is to stop passengers we meet upon the
road, to compel them to give an account who they are, and to take it for
an affront and just cause of quarrel if they refuse to do it.
At the Baths, which the ancients made use of every day before they
went to dinner, and as frequently as we wash our hands, they at first
only bathed their arms and legs; but afterwards, and by a custom that
has continued for many ages in most nations of the world, they bathed
stark naked in mixed and perfumed water, looking upon it as a great
simplicity to bathe in mere water. The most delicate and affected
perfumed themselves all over three or four times a day. They often
caused their hair to be pinched off, as the women of France have some
time since taken up a custom to do their foreheads,
"Quod pectus, quod crura tibi, quod brachia veilis,"
["You pluck the hairs out of your breast, your arms, and thighs."
—Martial, ii. 62, i.]
though they had ointments proper for that purpose:
"Psilotro nitet, aut acids latet oblita creta."
["She shines with unguents, or with chalk dissolved in vinegar."
—Idem, vi. 93, 9.]
They delighted to lie soft, and alleged it as a great testimony of
hardiness to lie upon a mattress. They ate lying upon beds, much after
the manner of the Turks in this age:
"Inde thoro pater AEneas sic orsus ab alto."
["Thus Father AEneas, from his high bed of state, spoke."
—AEneid, ii. 2.]
And 'tis said of the younger Cato, that after the battle of
Pharsalia, being entered into a melancholy disposition at the ill
posture of the public affairs, he took his repasts always sitting,
assuming a strict and austere course of life. It was also their custom
to kiss the hands of great persons; the more to honour and caress them.
And meeting with friends, they always kissed in salutation, as do the
Venetians:
"Gratatusque darem cum dulcibus oscula verbis."
["And kindest words I would mingle with kisses."
—Ovid, De Pont., iv. 9, 13]
In petitioning or saluting any great man, they used to lay their
hands upon his knees. Pasicles the philosopher, brother of Crates,
instead of laying his hand upon the knee laid it upon the private parts,
and being roughly repulsed by him to whom he made that indecent
compliment: "What," said he, "is not that part your own as well as the
other?" —[Diogenes Laertius, vi. 89.]—They used to eat fruit, as we do,
after dinner. They wiped their fundaments (let the ladies, if they
please, mince it smaller) with a sponge, which is the reason that
'spongia' is a smutty word in Latin; which sponge was fastened to the
end of a stick, as appears by the story of him who, as he was led along
to be thrown to the wild beasts in the sight of the people, asking leave
to do his business, and having no other way to despatch himself, forced
the sponge and stick down his throat and choked himself.—[Seneca, Ep.,
70.] They used to wipe, after coition, with perfumed wool:
"At tibi nil faciam; sed Iota mentula lana."
They had in the streets of Rome vessels and little tubs for
passengers to urine in:
"Pusi saepe lacum propter se, ac dolia curta.
Somno devincti, credunt extollere vestem."
["The little boys in their sleep often think they are near the
public urinal, and raise their coats to make use of it."
—Lucretius, iv.]
They had collation betwixt meals, and had in summer cellars of snow
to cool their wine; and some there were who made use of snow in winter,
not thinking their wine cool enough, even at that cold season of the
year. The men of quality had their cupbearers and carvers, and their
buffoons to make them sport. They had their meat served up in winter
upon chafing dishes, which were set upon the table, and had portable
kitchens (of which I myself have seen some) wherein all their service
was carried about with them:
"Has vobis epulas habete, lauti
Nos offendimur ambulante caena."
["Do you, if you please, esteem these feasts: we do not like the
ambulatory suppers."—Martial, vii. 48, 4.]
In summer they had a contrivance to bring fresh and clear rills
through their lower rooms, wherein were great store of living fish,
which the guests took out with their own hands to be dressed every man
according to his own liking. Fish has ever had this pre-eminence, and
keeps it still, that the grandees, as to them, all pretend to be cooks;
and indeed the taste is more delicate than that of flesh, at least to my
fancy. But in all sorts of magnificence, debauchery, and voluptuous
inventions of effeminacy and expense, we do, in truth, all we can to
parallel them; for our wills are as corrupt as theirs: but we want
ability to equal them. Our force is no more able to reach them in their
vicious, than in their virtuous, qualities, for both the one and the
other proceeded from a vigour of soul which was without comparison
greater in them than in us; and souls, by how much the weaker they are,
by so much have they less power to do either very well or very ill.
The highest place of honour amongst them was the middle. The name
going before, or following after, either in writing or speaking, had no
signification of grandeur, as is evident by their writings; they will as
soon say Oppius and Caesar, as Caesar and Oppius; and me and thee, as
thee and me. This is the reason that made me formerly take notice in the
life of Flaminius, in our French Plutarch, of one passage, where it
seems as if the author, speaking of the jealousy of honour betwixt the
AEtolians and Romans, about the winning of a battle they had with their
joined forces obtained, made it of some importance, that in the Greek
songs they had put the AEtolians before the Romans: if there be no
amphibology in the words of the French translation.
The ladies, in their baths, made no scruple of admitting men amongst
them, and moreover made use of their serving-men to rub and anoint them:
"Inguina succinctus nigri tibi servus aluta
Stat, quoties calidis nuda foveris aquis."
["A slave—his middle girded with a black apron—stands before you,
when, naked, you take a hot bath."—Martial, vii. 35, i.]
They all powdered themselves with a certain powder, to moderate their
sweats.
The ancient Gauls, says Sidonius Apollinaris, wore their hair long
before and the hinder part of the head shaved, a fashion that begins to
revive in this vicious and effeminate age.
The Romans used to pay the watermen their fare at their first
stepping into the boat, which we never do till after landing:
"Dum aes exigitur, dum mula ligatur,
Tota abit hora."
["Whilst the fare's paying, and the mule is being harnessed, a whole
hour's time is past."—Horace, Sat. i. 5, 13.]
The women used to lie on the side of the bed next the wall: and for
that reason they called Caesar,
"Spondam regis Nicomedis,"
["The bed of King Nicomedes."—Suetonius, Life of Caesar, 49.]
They took breath in their drinking, and watered their wine
"Quis puer ocius
Restinguet ardentis Falerni
Pocula praetereunte lympha?"
["What boy will quickly come and cool the heat of the Falernian
wine with clear water?"—Horace, Od., ii. z, 18.]
And the roguish looks and gestures of our lackeys were also in use
amongst them:
"O Jane, a tergo quern nulls ciconia pinsit,
Nec manus, auriculas imitari est mobilis albas,
Nec lingua, quantum sitiat canis Appula, tantum."
["O Janus, whom no crooked fingers, simulating a stork, peck at
behind your back, whom no quick hands deride behind you, by
imitating the motion of the white ears of the ass, against whom no
mocking tongue is thrust out, as the tongue of the thirsty Apulian
dog."—Persius, i. 58.]
The Argian and Roman ladies mourned in white, as ours did formerly
and should do still, were I to govern in this point. But there are whole
books on this subject.
CHAPTER L——OF DEMOCRITUS AND HERACLITUS
The judgment is an utensil proper for all subjects, and will have an
oar in everything: which is the reason, that in these Essays I take hold
of all occasions where, though it happen to be a subject I do not very
well understand, I try, however, sounding it at a distance, and finding
it too deep for my stature, I keep me on the shore; and this knowledge
that a man can proceed no further, is one effect of its virtue, yes, one
of those of which it is most proud. One while in an idle and frivolous
subject, I try to find out matter whereof to compose a body, and then to
prop and support it; another while, I employ it in a noble subject, one
that has been tossed and tumbled by a thousand hands, wherein a man can
scarce possibly introduce anything of his own, the way being so beaten
on every side that he must of necessity walk in the steps of another: in
such a case, 'tis the work of the judgment to take the way that seems
best, and of a thousand paths, to determine that this or that is the
best. I leave the choice of my arguments to fortune, and take that she
first presents to me; they are all alike to me, I never design to go
through any of them; for I never see all of anything: neither do they
who so largely promise to show it others. Of a hundred members and faces
that everything has, I take one, onewhile to look it over only, another
while to ripple up the skin, and sometimes to pinch it to the bones: I
give a stab, not so wide but as deep as I can, and am for the most part
tempted to take it in hand by some new light I discover in it. Did I
know myself less, I might perhaps venture to handle something or other
to the bottom, and to be deceived in my own inability; but sprinkling
here one word and there another, patterns cut from several pieces and
scattered without design and without engaging myself too far, I am not
responsible for them, or obliged to keep close to my subject, without
varying at my own liberty and pleasure, and giving up myself to doubt
and uncertainty, and to my own governing method, ignorance.
All motion discovers us: the very same soul of Caesar, that made
itself so conspicuous in marshalling and commanding the battle of
Pharsalia, was also seen as solicitous and busy in the softer affairs of
love and leisure. A man makes a judgment of a horse, not only by seeing
him when he is showing off his paces, but by his very walk, nay, and by
seeing him stand in the stable.
Amongst the functions of the soul, there are some of a lower and
meaner form; he who does not see her in those inferior offices as well
as in those of nobler note, never fully discovers her; and,
peradventure, she is best shown where she moves her simpler pace. The
winds of passions take most hold of her in her highest flights; and the
rather by reason that she wholly applies herself to, and exercises her
whole virtue upon, every particular subject, and never handles more than
one thing at a time, and that not according to it, but according to
herself. Things in respect to themselves have, peradventure, their
weight, measures, and conditions; but when we once take them into us,
the soul forms them as she pleases. Death is terrible to Cicero, coveted
by Cato, indifferent to Socrates. Health, conscience, authority,
knowledge, riches, beauty, and their contraries, all strip themselves at
their entering into us, and receive a new robe, and of another fashion,
from the soul; and of what colour, brown, bright, green, dark, and of
what quality, sharp, sweet, deep, or superficial, as best pleases each
of them, for they are not agreed upon any common standard of forms,
rules, or proceedings; every one is a queen in her own dominions. Let
us, therefore, no more excuse ourselves upon the external qualities of
things; it belongs to us to give ourselves an account of them. Our good
or ill has no other dependence but on ourselves. 'Tis there that our
offerings and our vows are due, and not to fortune she has no power over
our manners; on the contrary, they draw and make her follow in their
train, and cast her in their own mould. Why should not I judge of
Alexander at table, ranting and drinking at the prodigious rate he
sometimes used to do?
Or, if he played at chess? what string of his soul was not touched by
this idle and childish game? I hate and avoid it, because it is not play
enough, that it is too grave and serious a diversion, and I am ashamed
to lay out as much thought and study upon it as would serve to much
better uses. He did not more pump his brains about his glorious
expedition into the Indies, nor than another in unravelling a passage
upon which depends the safety of mankind. To what a degree does this
ridiculous diversion molest the soul, when all her faculties are
summoned together upon this trivial account! and how fair an opportunity
she herein gives every one to know and to make a right judgment of
himself? I do not more thoroughly sift myself in any other posture than
this: what passion are we exempted from in it? Anger, spite, malice,
impatience, and a vehement desire of getting the better in a concern
wherein it were more excusable to be ambitious of being overcome; for to
be eminent, to excel above the common rate in frivolous things, nowise
befits a man of honour. What I say in this example may be said in all
others. Every particle, every employment of man manifests him equally
with any other.
Democritus and Heraclitus were two philosophers, of whom the first,
finding human condition ridiculous and vain, never appeared abroad but
with a jeering and laughing countenance; whereas Heraclitus
commiserating that same condition of ours, appeared always with a
sorrowful look, and tears in his eyes:
"Alter
Ridebat, quoties a limine moverat unum
Protuleratque pedem; flebat contrarius alter."
["The one always, as often as he had stepped one pace from his
threshold, laughed, the other always wept."—Juvenal, Sat., x. 28.]
[Or, as Voltaire: "Life is a comedy to those who think;
a tragedy to those who feel." D.W.]
I am clearly for the first humour; not because it is more pleasant to
laugh than to weep, but because it expresses more contempt and
condemnation than the other, and I think we can never be despised
according to our full desert. Compassion and bewailing seem to imply
some esteem of and value for the thing bemoaned; whereas the things we
laugh at are by that expressed to be of no moment. I do not think that
we are so unhappy as we are vain, or have in us so much malice as folly;
we are not so full of mischief as inanity; nor so miserable as we are
vile and mean. And therefore Diogenes, who passed away his time in
rolling himself in his tub, and made nothing of the great Alexander,
esteeming us no better than flies or bladders puffed up with wind, was a
sharper and more penetrating, and, consequently in my opinion, a juster
judge than Timon, surnamed the Man-hater; for what a man hates he lays
to heart. This last was an enemy to all mankind, who passionately
desired our ruin, and avoided our conversation as dangerous, proceeding
from wicked and depraved natures: the other valued us so little that we
could neither trouble nor infect him by our example; and left us to herd
one with another, not out of fear, but from contempt of our society:
concluding us as incapable of doing good as evil.
Of the same strain was Statilius' answer, when Brutus courted him
into the conspiracy against Caesar; he was satisfied that the enterprise
was just, but he did not think mankind worthy of a wise man's concern';
according to the doctrine of Hegesias, who said, that a wise man ought
to do nothing but for himself, forasmuch as he only was worthy of it:
and to the saying of Theodorus, that it was not reasonable a wise man
should hazard himself for his country, and endanger wisdom for a company
of fools. Our condition is as ridiculous as risible.
CHAPTER LI——OF THE VANITY OF WORDS
A rhetorician of times past said, that to make little things appear
great was his profession. This was a shoemaker, who can make a great
shoe for a little foot.—[A saying of Agesilaus.]—They would in Sparta
have sent such a fellow to be whipped for making profession of a tricky
and deceitful act; and I fancy that Archidamus, who was king of that
country, was a little surprised at the answer of Thucydides, when
inquiring of him, which was the better wrestler, Pericles, or he, he
replied, that it was hard to affirm; for when I have thrown him, said
he, he always persuades the spectators that he had no fall and carries
away the prize. —[Quintilian, ii. 15.]—The women who paint, pounce, and
plaster up their ruins, filling up their wrinkles and deformities, are
less to blame, because it is no great matter whether we see them in
their natural complexions; whereas these make it their business to
deceive not our sight only but our judgments, and to adulterate and
corrupt the very essence of things. The republics that have maintained
themselves in a regular and well-modelled government, such as those of
Lacedaemon and Crete, had orators in no very great esteem. Aristo wisely
defined rhetoric to be "a science to persuade the people;" Socrates and
Plato "an art to flatter and deceive." And those who deny it in the
general description, verify it throughout in their precepts. The
Mohammedans will not suffer their children to be instructed in it, as
being useless, and the Athenians, perceiving of how pernicious
consequence the practice of it was, it being in their city of universal
esteem, ordered the principal part, which is to move the affections,
with their exordiums and perorations, to be taken away. 'Tis an engine
invented to manage and govern a disorderly and tumultuous rabble, and
that never is made use of, but like physic to the sick, in a discomposed
state. In those where the vulgar or the ignorant, or both together, have
been all-powerful and able to give the law, as in those of Athens,
Rhodes, and Rome, and where the public affairs have been in a continual
tempest of commotion, to such places have the orators always repaired.
And in truth, we shall find few persons in those republics who have
pushed their fortunes to any great degree of eminence without the
assistance of eloquence.
Pompey, Caesar, Crassus, Lucullus, Lentulus, Metellus, thence took
their chiefest spring, to mount to that degree of authority at which
they at last arrived, making it of greater use to them than arms,
contrary to the opinion of better times; for, L. Volumnius speaking
publicly in favour of the election of Q. Fabius and Pub. Decius, to the
consular dignity: "These are men," said he, "born for war and great in
execution; in the combat of the tongue altogether wanting; spirits truly
consular. The subtle, eloquent, and learned are only good for the city,
to make praetors of, to administer justice."—[Livy, x. 22.]
Eloquence most flourished at Rome when the public affairs were in the
worst condition and most disquieted with intestine commotions; as a free
and untilled soil bears the worst weeds. By which it should seem that a
monarchical government has less need of it than any other: for the
stupidity and facility natural to the common people, and that render
them subject to be turned and twined and, led by the ears by this
charming harmony of words, without weighing or considering the truth and
reality of things by the force of reason: this facility, I say, is not
easily found in a single person, and it is also more easy by good
education and advice to secure him from the impression of this poison.
There was never any famous orator known to come out of Persia or
Macedon.
I have entered into this discourse upon the occasion of an Italian I
lately received into my service, and who was clerk of the kitchen to the
late Cardinal Caraffa till his death. I put this fellow upon an account
of his office: when he fell to discourse of this palate-science, with
such a settled countenance and magisterial gravity, as if he had been
handling some profound point of divinity. He made a learned distinction
of the several sorts of appetites; of that a man has before he begins to
eat, and of those after the second and third service; the means simply
to satisfy the first, and then to raise and actuate the other two; the
ordering of the sauces, first in general, and then proceeded to the
qualities of the ingredients and their effects; the differences of
salads according to their seasons, those which ought to be served up
hot, and which cold; the manner of their garnishment and decoration to
render them acceptable to the eye. After which he entered upon the order
of the whole service, full of weighty and important considerations:
"Nec minimo sane discrimine refert,
Quo gestu lepores, et quo gallina secetur;"
["Nor with less discrimination observes how we should carve a hare,
and how a hen." or, ("Nor with the least discrimination relates how
we should carve hares, and how cut up a hen.)"
—Juvenal, Sat., v. 123.]
and all this set out with lofty and magnificent words, the very same
we make use of when we discourse of the government of an empire. Which
learned lecture of my man brought this of Terence into my memory:
"Hoc salsum est, hoc adustum est, hoc lautum est, parum:
Illud recte: iterum sic memento: sedulo
Moneo, qux possum, pro mea sapientia.
Postremo, tanquam in speculum, in patinas,
Demea, Inspicere jubeo, et moneo, quid facto usus sit."
["This is too salt, that's burnt, that's not washed enough; that's
well; remember to do so another time. Thus do I ever advise them to
have things done properly, according to my capacity; and lastly,
Demea, I command my cooks to look into every dish as if it were a
mirror, and tell them what they should do."
—Terence, Adelph., iii. 3, 71.]
And yet even the Greeks themselves very much admired and highly
applauded the order and disposition that Paulus AEmilius observed in the
feast he gave them at his return from Macedon. But I do not here speak
of effects, I speak of words only.
I do not know whether it may have the same operation upon other men
that it has upon me, but when I hear our architects thunder out their
bombast words of pilasters, architraves, and cornices, of the Corinthian
and Doric orders, and suchlike jargon, my imagination is presently
possessed with the palace of Apollidon; when, after all, I find them but
the paltry pieces of my own kitchen door.
To hear men talk of metonomies, metaphors, and allegories, and other
grammar words, would not one think they signified some rare and exotic
form of speaking? And yet they are phrases that come near to the babble
of my chambermaid.
And this other is a gullery of the same stamp, to call the offices of
our kingdom by the lofty titles of the Romans, though they have no
similitude of function, and still less of authority and power. And this
also, which I doubt will one day turn to the reproach of this age of
ours, unworthily and indifferently to confer upon any we think fit the
most glorious surnames with which antiquity honoured but one or two
persons in several ages. Plato carried away the surname of Divine, by so
universal a consent that never any one repined at it, or attempted to
take it from him; and yet the Italians, who pretend, and with good
reason, to more sprightly wits and sounder sense than the other nations
of their time, have lately bestowed the same title upon Aretin, in whose
writings, save tumid phrases set out with smart periods, ingenious
indeed but far-fetched and fantastic, and the eloquence, be it what it
may, I see nothing in him above the ordinary writers of his time, so far
is he from approaching the ancient divinity. And we make nothing of
giving the surname of great to princes who have nothing more than
ordinary in them.
CHAPTER LII——OF THE PARSIMONY OF THE ANCIENTS
Attilius Regulus, general of the Roman army in Africa, in the height
of all his glory and victories over the Carthaginians, wrote to the
Republic to acquaint them that a certain hind he had left in trust with
his estate, which was in all but seven acres of land, had run away with
all his instruments of husbandry, and entreating therefore, that they
would please to call him home that he might take order in his own
affairs, lest his wife and children should suffer by this disaster.
Whereupon the Senate appointed another to manage his business, caused
his losses to be made good, and ordered his family to be maintained at
the public expense.
The elder Cato, returning consul from Spain, sold his warhorse to
save the money it would have cost in bringing it back by sea into Italy;
and being Governor of Sardinia, he made all his visits on foot, without
other train than one officer of the Republic who carried his robe and a
censer for sacrifices, and for the most part carried his trunk himself.
He bragged that he had never worn a gown that cost above ten crowns, nor
had ever sent above tenpence to the market for one day's provision; and
that as to his country houses, he had not one that was rough-cast on the
outside.
Scipio AEmilianus, after two triumphs and two consulships, went an
embassy with no more than seven servants in his train. 'Tis said that
Homer had never more than one, Plato three, and Zeno, founder of the
sect of Stoics, none at all. Tiberius Gracchus was allowed but fivepence
halfpenny a day when employed as public minister about the public
affairs, and being at that time the greatest man of Rome.
CHAPTER LIII——OF A SAYING OF CAESAR
If we would sometimes bestow a little consideration upon ourselves,
and employ the time we spend in prying into other men's actions, and
discovering things without us, in examining our own abilities we should
soon perceive of how infirm and decaying material this fabric of ours is
composed. Is it not a singular testimony of imperfection that we cannot
establish our satisfaction in any one thing, and that even our own fancy
and desire should deprive us of the power to choose what is most proper
and useful for us? A very good proof of this is the great dispute that
has ever been amongst the philosophers, of finding out man's sovereign
good, that continues yet, and will eternally continue, without solution
or accord:
"Dum abest quod avemus, id exsuperare videtur
Caetera; post aliud, quum contigit illud, avemus,
Et sitis aequa tenet."
["While that which we desire is wanting, it seems to surpass all the
rest; then, when we have got it, we want something else; 'tis ever
the same thirst"—Lucretius, iii. 1095.]
Whatever it is that falls into our knowledge and possession, we find
that it satisfies not, and we still pant after things to come and
unknown, inasmuch as those present do not suffice for us; not that, in
my judgment, they have not in them wherewith to do it, but because we
seize them with an unruly and immoderate haste:
"Nam quum vidit hic, ad victum qux flagitat usus,
Et per quae possent vitam consistere tutam,
Omnia jam ferme mortalibus esse parata;
Divitiis homines, et honore, et laude potentes
Aflluere, atque bona natorum excellere fama;
Nec minus esse domi cuiquam tamen anxia corda,
Atque animi ingratis vitam vexare querelis
Causam, quae infestis cogit saevire querelis,
Intellegit ibi; vitium vas efficere ipsum,
Omniaque, illius vitio, corrumpier intus,
Qux collata foris et commoda quomque venirent."
["For when he saw that almost all things necessarily required for
subsistence, and which may render life comfortable, are already
prepared to their hand, that men may abundantly attain wealth,
honour, praise, may rejoice in the reputation of their children, yet
that, notwithstanding, every one has none the less in his heart and
home anxieties and a mind enslaved by wearing complaints, he saw
that the vessel itself was in fault, and that all good things which
were brought into it from without were spoilt by its own
imperfections."—Lucretius, vi. 9.]
Our appetite is irresolute and fickle; it can neither keep nor enjoy
anything with a good grace: and man concluding it to be the fault of the
things he is possessed of, fills himself with and feeds upon the idea of
things he neither knows nor understands, to which he devotes his hopes
and his desires, paying them all reverence and honour, according to the
saying of Caesar:
"Communi fit vitio naturae, ut invisis, latitantibus
atque incognitis rebus magis confidamas,
vehementiusque exterreamur."
["'Tis the common vice of nature, that we at once repose most
confidence, and receive the greatest apprehensions, from things
unseen, concealed, and unknown."—De Bello Civil, xi. 4.]
CHAPTER LIV——OF VAIN SUBTLETIES
There are a sort of little knacks and frivolous subtleties from which
men sometimes expect to derive reputation and applause: as poets, who
compose whole poems with every line beginning with the same letter; we
see the shapes of eggs, globes, wings, and hatchets cut out by the
ancient Greeks by the measure of their verses, making them longer or
shorter, to represent such or such a figure. Of this nature was his
employment who made it his business to compute into how many several
orders the letters of the alphabet might be transposed, and found out
that incredible number mentioned in Plutarch. I am mightily pleased with
the humour of him,
["Alexander, as may be seen in Quintil., Institut. Orat., lib.
ii., cap. 20, where he defines Maratarexvia to be a certain
unnecessary imitation of art, which really does neither good nor
harm, but is as unprofitable and ridiculous as was the labour of
that man who had so perfectly learned to cast small peas through the
eye of a needle at a good distance that he never missed one, and was
justly rewarded for it, as is said, by Alexander, who saw the
performance, with a bushel of peas."—Coste.]
who having a man brought before him that had learned to throw a grain
of millet with such dexterity and assurance as never to miss the eye of
a needle; and being afterwards entreated to give something for the
reward of so rare a performance, he pleasantly, and in my opinion
justly, ordered a certain number of bushels of the same grain to be
delivered to him, that he might not want wherewith to exercise so famous
an art. 'Tis a strong evidence of a weak judgment when men approve of
things for their being rare and new, or for their difficulty, where
worth and usefulness are not conjoined to recommend them.
I come just now from playing with my own family at who could find out
the most things that hold by their two extremities; as Sire, which is a
title given to the greatest person in the nation, the king, and also to
the vulgar, as merchants, but never to any degree of men between. The
women of great quality are called Dames, inferior gentlewomen,
Demoiselles, and the meanest sort of women, Dames, as the first. The
cloth of state over our tables is not permitted but in the palaces of
princes and in taverns. Democritus said, that gods and beasts had
sharper sense than men, who are of a middle form. The Romans wore the
same habit at funerals and feasts. It is most certain that an extreme
fear and an extreme ardour of courage equally trouble and relax the
belly. The nickname of Trembling with which they surnamed Sancho XII.,
king of Navarre, tells us that valour will cause a trembling in the
limbs as well as fear. Those who were arming that king, or some other
person, who upon the like occasion was wont to be in the same disorder,
tried to compose him by representing the danger less he was going to
engage himself in: "You understand me ill," said he, "for could my flesh
know the danger my courage will presently carry it into, it would sink
down to the ground." The faintness that surprises us from frigidity or
dislike in the exercises of Venus are also occasioned by a too violent
desire and an immoderate heat. Extreme coldness and extreme heat boil
and roast. Aristotle says, that sows of lead will melt and run with cold
and the rigour of winter just as with a vehement heat. Desire and
satiety fill all the gradations above and below pleasure with pain.
Stupidity and wisdom meet in the same centre of sentiment and
resolution, in the suffering of human accidents. The wise control and
triumph over ill, the others know it not: these last are, as a man may
say, on this side of accidents, the others are beyond them, who after
having well weighed and considered their qualities, measured and judged
them what they are, by virtue of a vigorous soul leap out of their
reach; they disdain and trample them underfoot, having a solid and
well-fortified soul, against which the darts of fortune, coming to
strike, must of necessity rebound and blunt themselves, meeting with a
body upon which they can fix no impression; the ordinary and middle
condition of men are lodged betwixt these two extremities, consisting of
such as perceive evils, feel them, and are not able to support them.
Infancy and decrepitude meet in the imbecility of the brain; avarice and
profusion in the same thirst and desire of getting.
A man may say with some colour of truth that there is an Abecedarian
ignorance that precedes knowledge, and a doctoral ignorance that comes
after it: an ignorance that knowledge creates and begets, at the same
time that it despatches and destroys the first. Of mean understandings,
little inquisitive, and little instructed, are made good Christians, who
by reverence and obedience simply believe and are constant in their
belief. In the average understandings and the middle sort of capacities,
the error of opinion is begotten; they follow the appearance of the
first impression, and have some colour of reason on their side to impute
our walking on in the old beaten path to simplicity and stupidity,
meaning us who have not informed ourselves by study. The higher and
nobler souls, more solid and clear-sighted, make up another sort of true
believers, who by a long and religious investigation of truth, have
obtained a clearer and more penetrating light into the Scriptures, and
have discovered the mysterious and divine secret of our ecclesiastical
polity; and yet we see some, who by the middle step, have arrived at
that supreme degree with marvellous fruit and confirmation, as to the
utmost limit of Christian intelligence, and enjoy their victory with
great spiritual consolation, humble acknowledgment of the divine favour,
reformation of manners, and singular modesty. I do not intend with these
to rank those others, who to clear themselves from all suspicion of
their former errors and to satisfy us that they are sound and firm,
render themselves extremely indiscreet and unjust, in the carrying on
our cause, and blemish it with infinite reproaches of violence and
oppression. The simple peasants are good people, and so are the
philosophers, or whatever the present age calls them, men of strong and
clear reason, and whose souls are enriched with an ample instruction of
profitable sciences. The mongrels who have disdained the first form of
the ignorance of letters, and have not been able to attain to the other
(sitting betwixt two stools, as I and a great many more of us do), are
dangerous, foolish, and importunate; these are they that trouble the
world. And therefore it is that I, for my own part, retreat as much as I
can towards the first and natural station, whence I so vainly attempted
to advance.
Popular and purely natural poesy
["The term poesie populaire was employed, for the first time, in the
French language on this occasion. Montaigne created the expression,
and indicated its nature."—Ampere.]
has in it certain artless graces, by which she may come into
comparison with the greatest beauty of poetry perfected by art: as we
see in our Gascon villanels and the songs that are brought us from
nations that have no knowledge of any manner of science, nor so much as
the use of writing. The middle sort of poesy betwixt these two is
despised, of no value, honour, or esteem.
But seeing that the path once laid open to the fancy, I have found,
as it commonly falls out, that what we have taken for a difficult
exercise and a rare subject, prove to be nothing so, and that after the
invention is once warm, it finds out an infinite number of parallel
examples. I shall only add this one—that, were these Essays of mine
considerable enough to deserve a critical judgment, it might then, I
think, fall out that they would not much take with common and vulgar
capacities, nor be very acceptable to the singular and excellent sort of
men; the first would not understand them enough, and the last too much;
and so they may hover in the middle region.
CHAPTER LV——OF SMELLS
It has been reported of some, as of Alexander the Great, that their
sweat exhaled an odoriferous smell, occasioned by some rare and
extraordinary constitution, of which Plutarch and others have been
inquisitive into the cause. But the ordinary constitution of human
bodies is quite otherwise, and their best and chiefest excellency is to
be exempt from smell. Nay, the sweetness even of the purest breath has
nothing in it of greater perfection than to be without any offensive
smell, like those of healthful children, which made Plautus say of a
woman:
"Mulier tum bene olet, ubi nihil olet."
["She smells sweetest, who smells not at all."
—Plautus, Mostel, i. 3, 116.]
And such as make use of fine exotic perfumes are with good reason to
be suspected of some natural imperfection which they endeavour by these
odours to conceal. To smell, though well, is to stink:
"Rides nos, Coracine, nil olentes
Malo, quam bene olere, nil olere."
["You laugh at us, Coracinus, because we are not scented; I would,
rather than smell well, not smell at all."—Martial, vi. 55, 4.]
And elsewhere:
"Posthume, non bene olet, qui bene semper olet."
["Posthumus, he who ever smells well does not smell well."
—Idem, ii. 12, 14.]
I am nevertheless a great lover of good smells, and as much abominate
the ill ones, which also I scent at a greater distance, I think, than
other men:
"Namque sagacius unus odoror,
Polypus, an gravis hirsutis cubet hircus in aliis
Quam canis acer, ubi latest sus."
["My nose is quicker to scent a fetid sore or a rank armpit, than a
dog to smell out the hidden sow."—Horace, Epod., xii. 4.]
Of smells, the simple and natural seem to me the most pleasing. Let
the ladies look to that, for 'tis chiefly their concern: amid the most
profound barbarism, the Scythian women, after bathing, were wont to
powder and crust their faces and all their bodies with a certain
odoriferous drug growing in their country, which being cleansed off,
when they came to have familiarity with men they were found perfumed and
sleek. 'Tis not to be believed how strangely all sorts of odours cleave
to me, and how apt my skin is to imbibe them. He that complains of
nature that she has not furnished mankind with a vehicle to convey
smells to the nose had no reason; for they will do it themselves,
especially to me; my very mustachios, which are full, perform that
office; for if I stroke them but with my gloves or handkerchief, the
smell will not out a whole day; they manifest where I have been, and the
close, luscious, devouring, viscid melting kisses of youthful ardour in
my wanton age left a sweetness upon my lips for several hours after. And
yet I have ever found myself little subject to epidemic diseases, that
are caught, either by conversing with the sick or bred by the contagion
of the air, and have escaped from those of my time, of which there have
been several sorts in our cities and armies. We read of Socrates, that
though he never departed from Athens during the frequent plagues that
infested the city, he only was never infected.
Physicians might, I believe, extract greater utility from odours than
they do, for I have often observed that they cause an alteration in me
and work upon my spirits according to their several virtues; which makes
me approve of what is said, that the use of incense and perfumes in
churches, so ancient and so universally received in all nations and
religions, was intended to cheer us, and to rouse and purify the senses,
the better to fit us for contemplation.
I could have been glad, the better to judge of it, to have tasted the
culinary art of those cooks who had so rare a way of seasoning exotic
odours with the relish of meats; as it was particularly observed in the
service of the king of Tunis, who in our days—[Muley-Hassam, in 1543.]
—landed at Naples to have an interview with Charles the Emperor. His
dishes were larded with odoriferous drugs, to that degree of expense
that the cookery of one peacock and two pheasants amounted to a hundred
ducats to dress them after their fashion; and when the carver came to
cut them up, not only the dining-room, but all the apartments of his
palace and the adjoining streets were filled with an aromatic vapour
which did not presently vanish.
My chiefest care in choosing my lodgings is always to avoid a thick
and stinking air; and those beautiful cities, Venice and Paris, very
much lessen the kindness I have for them, the one by the offensive smell
of her marshes, and the other of her dirt.
CHAPTER LVI——OF PRAYERS
I propose formless and undetermined fancies, like those who publish
doubtful questions, to be after a disputed upon in the schools, not to
establish truth but to seek it; and I submit them to the judgments of
those whose office it is to regulate, not my writings and actions only,
but moreover my very thoughts. Let what I here set down meet with
correction or applause, it shall be of equal welcome and utility to me,
myself beforehand condemning as absurd and impious, if anything shall be
found, through ignorance or inadvertency, couched in this rhapsody,
contrary to the holy resolutions and prescriptions of the Catholic
Apostolic and Roman Church, into which I was born and in which I will
die. And yet, always submitting to the authority of their censure, which
has an absolute power over me, I thus rashly venture at everything, as
in treating upon this present subject.
I know not if or no I am wrong, but since, by a particular favour of
the divine bounty, a certain form of prayer has been prescribed and
dictated to us, word by word, from the mouth of God Himself, I have ever
been of opinion that we ought to have it in more frequent use than we
yet have; and if I were worthy to advise, at the sitting down to and
rising from our tables, at our rising from and going to bed, and in
every particular action wherein prayer is used, I would that Christians
always make use of the Lord's Prayer, if not alone, yet at least always.
The Church may lengthen and diversify prayers, according to the
necessity of our instruction, for I know very well that it is always the
same in substance and the same thing: but yet such a privilege ought to
be given to that prayer, that the people should have it continually in
their mouths; for it is most certain that all necessary petitions are
comprehended in it, and that it is infinitely proper for all occasions.
'Tis the only prayer I use in all places and conditions, and which I
still repeat instead of changing; whence it also happens that I have no
other so entirely by heart as that.
It just now came into my mind, whence it is we should derive that
error of having recourse to God in all our designs and enterprises, to
call Him to our assistance in all sorts of affairs, and in all places
where our weakness stands in need of support, without considering
whether the occasion be just or otherwise; and to invoke His name and
power, in what state soever we are, or action we are engaged in,
howsoever vicious. He is indeed, our sole and unique protector, and can
do all things for us: but though He is pleased to honour us with this
sweet paternal alliance, He is, notwithstanding, as just as He is good
and mighty; and more often exercises His justice than His power, and
favours us according to that, and not according to our petitions.
Plato in his Laws, makes three sorts of belief injurious to the gods;
"that there are none; that they concern not themselves about our
affairs; that they never refuse anything to our vows, offerings, and
sacrifices." The first of these errors (according to his opinion, never
continued rooted in any man from his infancy to his old age); the other
two, he confesses, men might be obstinate in.
God's justice and His power are inseparable; 'tis in vain we invoke
His power in an unjust cause. We are to have our souls pure and clean,
at that moment at least wherein we pray to Him, and purified from all
vicious passions; otherwise we ourselves present Him the rods wherewith
to chastise us; instead of repairing anything we have done amiss, we
double the wickedness and the offence when we offer to Him, to whom we
are to sue for pardon, an affection full of irreverence and hatred.
Which makes me not very apt to applaud those whom I observe to be so
frequent on their knees, if the actions nearest to the prayer do not
give me some evidence of amendment and reformation:
"Si, nocturnus adulter,
Tempora Santonico velas adoperta cucullo."
["If a night adulterer, thou coverest thy head with a Santonic
cowl."—Juvenal, Sat., viii. 144.—The Santones were the people
who inhabited Saintonge in France, from whom the Romans derived the
use of hoods or cowls covering the head and face.]
And the practice of a man who mixes devotion with an execrable life
seems in some sort more to be condemned than that of a man conformable
to his own propension and dissolute throughout; and for that reason it
is that our Church denies admittance to and communion with men obstinate
and incorrigible in any notorious wickedness. We pray only by custom and
for fashion's sake; or rather, we read or pronounce our prayers aloud,
which is no better than an hypocritical show of devotion; and I am
scandalised to see a man cross himself thrice at the Benedicite, and as
often at Grace (and the more, because it is a sign I have in great
veneration and continual use, even when I yawn), and to dedicate all the
other hours of the day to acts of malice, avarice, and injustice. One
hour to God, the rest to the devil, as if by composition and
compensation. 'Tis a wonder to see actions so various in themselves
succeed one another with such an uniformity of method as not to
interfere nor suffer any alteration, even upon the very confines and
passes from the one to the other. What a prodigious conscience must that
be that can be at quiet within itself whilst it harbours under the same
roof, with so agreeing and so calm a society, both the crime and the
judge?
A man whose whole meditation is continually working upon nothing but
impurity which he knows to be so odious to Almighty God, what can he say
when he comes to speak to Him? He draws back, but immediately falls into
a relapse. If the object of divine justice and the presence of his Maker
did, as he pretends, strike and chastise his soul, how short soever the
repentance might be, the very fear of offending the Infinite Majesty
would so often present itself to his imagination that he would soon see
himself master of those vices that are most natural and vehement in him.
But what shall we say of those who settle their whole course of life
upon the profit and emolument of sins, which they know to be mortal? How
many trades and vocations have we admitted and countenanced amongst us,
whose very essence is vicious? And he that, confessing himself to me,
voluntarily told me that he had all his lifetime professed and practised
a religion, in his opinion damnable and contrary to that he had in his
heart, only to preserve his credit and the honour of his employments,
how could his courage suffer so infamous a confession? What can men say
to the divine justice upon this subject?
Their repentance consisting in a visible and manifest reparation,
they lose the colour of alleging it both to God and man. Are they so
impudent as to sue for remission without satisfaction and without
penitence? I look upon these as in the same condition with the first:
but the obstinacy is not there so easy to be overcome. This contrariety
and volubility of opinion so sudden, so violent, that they feign, are a
kind of miracle to me: they present us with the state of an indigestible
agony of mind.
It seemed to me a fantastic imagination in those who, these late
years past, were wont to reproach every man they knew to be of any
extraordinary parts, and made profession of the Catholic religion, that
it was but outwardly; maintaining, moreover, to do him honour forsooth,
that whatever he might pretend to the contrary he could not but in his
heart be of their reformed opinion. An untoward disease, that a man
should be so riveted to his own belief as to fancy that others cannot
believe otherwise than as he does; and yet worse, that they should
entertain so vicious an opinion of such great parts as to think any man
so qualified, should prefer any present advantage of fortune to the
promises of eternal life and the menaces of eternal damnation. They may
believe me: could anything have tempted my youth, the ambition of the
danger and difficulties in the late commotions had not been the least
motives.
It is not without very good reason, in my opinion, that the Church
interdicts the promiscuous, indiscreet, and irreverent use of the holy
and divine Psalms, with which the Holy Ghost inspired King David. We
ought not to mix God in our actions, but with the highest reverence and
caution; that poesy is too holy to be put to no other use than to
exercise the lungs and to delight our ears; it ought to come from the
conscience, and not from the tongue. It is not fit that a prentice in
his shop, amongst his vain and frivolous thoughts, should be permitted
to pass away his time and divert himself with such sacred things.
Neither is it decent to see the Holy Book of the holy mysteries of our
belief tumbled up and down a hall or a kitchen they were formerly
mysteries, but are now become sports and recreations. 'Tis a book too
serious and too venerable to be cursorily or slightly turned over: the
reading of the scripture ought to be a temperate and premeditated act,
and to which men should always add this devout preface, 'sursum corda',
preparing even the body to so humble and composed a gesture and
countenance as shall evidence a particular veneration and attention.
Neither is it a book for everyone to fist, but the study of select men
set apart for that purpose, and whom Almighty God has been pleased to
call to that office and sacred function: the wicked and ignorant grow
worse by it. 'Tis, not a story to tell, but a history to revere, fear,
and adore. Are not they then pleasant men who think they have rendered
this fit for the people's handling by translating it into the vulgar
tongue? Does the understanding of all therein contained only stick at
words? Shall I venture to say further, that by coming so near to
understand a little, they are much wider of the whole scope than before.
A pure and simple ignorance and wholly depending upon the exposition of
qualified persons, was far more learned and salutary than this vain and
verbal knowledge, which has only temerity and presumption.
And I do further believe that the liberty every one has taken to
disperse the sacred writ into so many idioms carries with it a great
deal more of danger than utility. The Jews, Mohammedans, and almost all
other peoples, have reverentially espoused the language wherein their
mysteries were first conceived, and have expressly, and not without
colour of reason, forbidden the alteration of them into any other. Are
we assured that in Biscay and in Brittany there are enough competent
judges of this affair to establish this translation into their own
language? The universal Church has not a more difficult and solemn
judgment to make. In preaching and speaking the interpretation is vague,
free, mutable, and of a piece by itself; so 'tis not the same thing.
One of our Greek historians age justly censures the he lived in,
because the secrets of the Christian religion were dispersed into the
hands of every mechanic, to expound and argue upon, according to his own
fancy, and that we ought to be much ashamed, we who by God's especial
favour enjoy the pure mysteries of piety, to suffer them to be profaned
by the ignorant rabble; considering that the Gentiles expressly forbad
Socrates, Plato, and the other sages to inquire into or so much as
mention the things committed to the priests of Delphi; and he says,
moreover, that the factions of princes upon theological subjects are
armed not with zeal but fury; that zeal springs from the divine wisdom
and justice, and governs itself with prudence and moderation, but
degenerates into hatred and envy, producing tares and nettles instead of
corn and wine when conducted by human passions. And it was truly said by
another, who, advising the Emperor Theodosius, told him that disputes
did not so much rock the schisms of the Church asleep, as it roused and
animated heresies; that, therefore, all contentions and dialectic
disputations were to be avoided, and men absolutely to acquiesce in the
prescriptions and formulas of faith established by the ancients. And the
Emperor Andronicus having overheard some great men at high words in his
palace with Lapodius about a point of ours of great importance, gave
them so severe a check as to threaten to cause them to be thrown into
the river if they did not desist. The very women and children nowadays
take upon them to lecture the oldest and most experienced men about the
ecclesiastical laws; whereas the first of those of Plato forbids them to
inquire so much as into the civil laws, which were to stand instead of
divine ordinances; and, allowing the old men to confer amongst
themselves or with the magistrate about those things, he adds, provided
it be not in the presence of young or profane persons.
A bishop has left in writing that at the other end of the world there
is an isle, by the ancients called Dioscorides, abundantly fertile in
all sorts of trees and fruits, and of an exceedingly healthful air; the
inhabitants of which are Christians, having churches and altars, only
adorned with crosses without any other images, great observers of fasts
and feasts, exact payers of their tithes to the priests, and so chaste,
that none of them is permitted to have to do with more than one woman in
his life—[What Osorius says is that these people only had one wife at a
time.]—as to the rest, so content with their condition, that environed
with the sea they know nothing of navigation, and so simple that they
understand not one syllable of the religion they profess and wherein
they are so devout: a thing incredible to such as do not know that the
Pagans, who are so zealous idolaters, know nothing more of their gods
than their bare names and their statues. The ancient beginning of
'Menalippus', a tragedy of Euripides, ran thus:
"O Jupiter! for that name alone
Of what thou art to me is known."
I have also known in my time some men's writings found fault with for
being purely human and philosophical, without any mixture of theology;
and yet, with some show of reason, it might, on the contrary, be said
that the divine doctrine, as queen and regent of the rest, better keeps
her state apart, that she ought to be sovereign throughout, not
subsidiary and suffragan, and that, peradventure, grammatical,
rhetorical, logical examples may elsewhere be more suitably chosen, as
also the material for the stage, games, and public entertainments, than
from so sacred a matter; that divine reasons are considered with greater
veneration and attention by themselves, and in their own proper style,
than when mixed with and adapted to human discourse; that it is a fault
much more often observed that the divines write too humanly, than that
the humanists write not theologically enough. Philosophy, says St.
Chrysostom, has long been banished the holy schools, as an handmaid
altogether useless and thought unworthy to look, so much as in passing
by the door, into the sanctuary of the holy treasures of the celestial
doctrine; that the human way of speaking is of a much lower form and
ought not to adopt for herself the dignity and majesty of divine
eloquence. Let who will 'verbis indisciplinatis' talk of fortune,
destiny, accident, good and evil hap, and other suchlike phrases,
according to his own humour; I for my part propose fancies merely human
and merely my own, and that simply as human fancies, and separately
considered, not as determined by any decree from heaven, incapable of
doubt or dispute; matter of opinion, not matter of faith; things which I
discourse of according to my own notions, not as I believe, according to
God; after a laical, not clerical, and yet always after a very religious
manner, as children prepare their exercises, not to instruct but to be
instructed.
And might it not be said, that an edict enjoining all people but such
as are public professors of divinity, to be very reserved in writing of
religion, would carry with it a very good colour of utility and justice
—and to me, amongst the rest peradventure, to hold my prating? I have
been told that even those who are not of our Church nevertheless amongst
themselves expressly forbid the name of God to be used in common
discourse, nor so much even by way of interjection, exclamation,
assertion of a truth, or comparison; and I think them in the right: upon
what occasion soever we call upon God to accompany and assist us, it
ought always to be done with the greatest reverence and devotion.
There is, as I remember, a passage in Xenophon where he tells us that
we ought so much the more seldom to call upon God, by how much it is
hard to compose our souls to such a degree of calmness, patience, and
devotion as it ought to be in at such a time; otherwise our prayers are
not only vain and fruitless, but vicious: "forgive us," we say, "our
trespasses, as we forgive them that trespass against us"; what do we
mean by this petition but that we present to God a soul free from all
rancour and revenge? And yet we make nothing of invoking God's
assistance in our vices, and inviting Him into our unjust designs:
"Quae, nisi seductis, nequeas committere divis"
["Which you can only impart to the gods, when you have gained them
over."—Persius, ii. 4.]
the covetous man prays for the conservation of his vain and
superfluous riches; the ambitious for victory and the good conduct of
his fortune; the thief calls Him to his assistance, to deliver him from
the dangers and difficulties that obstruct his wicked designs, or
returns Him thanks for the facility he has met with in cutting a man's
throat; at the door of the house men are going to storm or break into by
force of a petard, they fall to prayers for success, their intentions
and hopes of cruelty, avarice, and lust.
"Hoc igitur, quo to Jovis aurem impellere tentas,
Dic agedum Staio: 'proh Jupiter! O bone, clamet,
Jupiter!' At sese non clamet Jupiter ipse."
["This therefore, with which you seek to draw the ear of Jupiter,
say to Staius. 'O Jupiter! O good Jupiter!' let him cry. Think
you Jupiter himself would not cry out upon it?"—Persius, ii. 21.]
Marguerite, Queen of Navarre,—[In the Heptameron.]—tells of a young
prince, who, though she does not name him, is easily enough by his great
qualities to be known, who going upon an amorous assignation to lie with
an advocate's wife of Paris, his way thither being through a church, he
never passed that holy place going to or returning from his pious
exercise, but he always kneeled down to pray. Wherein he would employ
the divine favour, his soul being full of such virtuous meditations, I
leave others to judge, which, nevertheless, she instances for a
testimony of singular devotion. But this is not the only proof we have
that women are not very fit to treat of theological affairs.
A true prayer and religious reconciling of ourselves to Almighty God
cannot enter into an impure soul, subject at the very time to the
dominion of Satan. He who calls God to his assistance whilst in a course
of vice, does as if a cut-purse should call a magistrate to help him, or
like those who introduce the name of God to the attestation of a lie.
"Tacito mala vota susurro
Concipimus."
["We whisper our guilty prayers."—-Lucan, v. 104.]
There are few men who durst publish to the world the prayers they
make to Almighty God:
"Haud cuivis promptum est, murmurque, humilesque susurros
Tollere de templis, et aperto vivere voto"
["'Tis not convenient for every one to bring the prayers he mutters
out of the temple, and to give his wishes to the public ear.
—"Persius, ii. 6.]
and this is the reason why the Pythagoreans would have them always
public and heard by every one, to the end they might not prefer indecent
or unjust petitions as this man:
"Clare quum dixit, Apollo!
Labra movet, metuens audiri: Pulcra Laverna,
Da mihi fallere, da justum sanctumque videri;
Noctem peccatis, et fraudibus objice nubem."
["When he has clearly said Apollo! he moves his lips, fearful to be
heard; he murmurs: O fair Laverna, grant me the talent to deceive;
grant me to appear holy and just; shroud my sins with night, and
cast a cloud over my frauds."—Horace, Ep., i. 16, 59.—(Laverna
was the goddess of thieves.)]
The gods severely punished the wicked prayers of OEdipus in granting
them: he had prayed that his children might amongst themselves determine
the succession to his throne by arms, and was so miserable as to see
himself taken at his word. We are not to pray that all things may go as
we would have them, but as most concurrent with prudence.
We seem, in truth, to make use of our prayers as of a kind of jargon,
and as those do who employ holy words about sorceries and magical
operations; and as if we reckoned the benefit we are to reap from them
as depending upon the contexture, sound, and jingle of words, or upon
the grave composing of the countenance. For having the soul contaminated
with concupiscence, not touched with repentance, or comforted by any
late reconciliation with God, we go to present Him such words as the
memory suggests to the tongue, and hope from thence to obtain the
remission of our sins. There is nothing so easy, so sweet, and so
favourable, as the divine law: it calls and invites us to her, guilty
and abominable as we are; extends her arms and receives us into her
bosom, foul and polluted as we at present are, and are for the future to
be. But then, in return, we are to look upon her with a respectful eye;
we are to receive this pardon with all gratitude and submission, and for
that instant at least, wherein we address ourselves to her, to have the
soul sensible of the ills we have committed, and at enmity with those
passions that seduced us to offend her; neither the gods nor good men
(says Plato) will accept the present of a wicked man:
"Immunis aram si terigit manus,
Non sumptuosa blandior hostia
Mollivit aversos Penates
Farre pio et saliente mica."
["If a pure hand has touched the altar, the pious offering of a
small cake and a few grains of salt will appease the offended gods
more effectually than costly sacrifices."
—Horace, Od., iii. 23, 17.]
CHAPTER LVII——OF AGE
I cannot allow of the way in which we settle for ourselves the
duration of our life. I see that the sages contract it very much in
comparison of the common opinion: "what," said the younger Cato to those
who would stay his hand from killing himself, "am I now of an age to be
reproached that I go out of the world too soon?" And yet he was but
eight-and-forty years old. He thought that to be a mature and advanced
age, considering how few arrive unto it. And such as, soothing their
thoughts with I know not what course of nature, promise to themselves
some years beyond it, could they be privileged from the infinite number
of accidents to which we are by a natural subjection exposed, they might
have some reason so to do. What am idle conceit is it to expect to die
of a decay of strength, which is the effect of extremest age, and to
propose to ourselves no shorter lease of life than that, considering it
is a kind of death of all others the most rare and very seldom seen? We
call that only a natural death; as if it were contrary to nature to see
a man break his neck with a fall, be drowned in shipwreck, be snatched
away with a pleurisy or the plague, and as if our ordinary condition did
not expose us to these inconveniences. Let us no longer flatter
ourselves with these fine words; we ought rather, peradventure, to call
that natural which is general, common, and universal.
To die of old age is a death rare, extraordinary, and singular, and,
therefore, so much less natural than the others; 'tis the last and
extremest sort of dying: and the more remote, the less to be hoped for.
It is, indeed, the bourn beyond which we are not to pass, and which the
law of nature has set as a limit, not to be exceeded; but it is, withal,
a privilege she is rarely seen to give us to last till then. 'Tis a
lease she only signs by particular favour, and it may be to one only in
the space of two or three ages, and then with a pass to boot, to carry
him through all the traverses and difficulties she has strewed in the
way of this long career. And therefore my opinion is, that when once
forty years we should consider it as an age to which very few arrive.
For seeing that men do not usually proceed so far, it is a sign that we
are pretty well advanced; and since we have exceeded the ordinary
bounds, which is the just measure of life, we ought not to expect to go
much further; having escaped so many precipices of death, whereinto we
have seen so many other men fall, we should acknowledge that so
extraordinary a fortune as that which has hitherto rescued us from those
eminent perils, and kept us alive beyond the ordinary term of living, is
not like to continue long.
'Tis a fault in our very laws to maintain this error: these say that
a man is not capable of managing his own estate till he be
five-and-twenty years old, whereas he will have much ado to manage his
life so long. Augustus cut off five years from the ancient Roman
standard, and declared that thirty years old was sufficient for a judge.
Servius Tullius superseded the knights of above seven-and-forty years of
age from the fatigues of war; Augustus dismissed them at forty-five;
though methinks it seems a little unreasonable that men should be sent
to the fireside till five-and-fifty or sixty years of age. I should be
of opinion that our vocation and employment should be as far as possible
extended for the public good: I find the fault on the other side, that
they do not employ us early enough. This emperor was arbiter of the
whole world at nineteen, and yet would have a man to be thirty before he
could be fit to determine a dispute about a gutter.
For my part, I believe our souls are adult at twenty as much as they
are ever like to be, and as capable then as ever. A soul that has not by
that time given evident earnest of its force and virtue will never after
come to proof. The natural qualities and virtues produce what they have
of vigorous and fine, within that term or never,
"Si l'espine rion picque quand nai,
A pene que picque jamai,"
["If the thorn does not prick at its birth,
'twill hardly ever prick at all."]
as they say in Dauphin.
Of all the great human actions I ever heard or read of, of what sort
soever, I have observed, both in former ages and our own, more were
performed before the age of thirty than after; and this ofttimes in the
very lives of the same men. May I not confidently instance in those of
Hannibal and his great rival Scipio? The better half of their lives they
lived upon the glory they had acquired in their youth; great men after,
'tis true, in comparison of others; but by no means in comparison of
themselves. As to my own particular, I do certainly believe that since
that age, both my understanding and my constitution have rather decayed
than improved, and retired rather than advanced. 'Tis possible, that
with those who make the best use of their time, knowledge and experience
may increase with their years; but vivacity, promptitude, steadiness,
and other pieces of us, of much greater importance, and much more
essentially our own, languish and decay:
"Ubi jam validis quassatum est viribus aevi
Corpus, et obtusis ceciderunt viribus artus,
Claudicat ingenium, delirat linguaque, mensque."
["When once the body is shaken by the violence of time,
blood and vigour ebbing away, the judgment halts,
the tongue and the mind dote."—Lucretius, iii. 452.]
Sometimes the body first submits to age, sometimes the mind; and I
have seen enough who have got a weakness in their brains before either
in their legs or stomach; and by how much the more it is a disease of no
great pain to the sufferer, and of obscure symptoms, so much greater is
the danger. For this reason it is that I complain of our laws, not that
they keep us too long to our work, but that they set us to work too
late. For the frailty of life considered, and to how many ordinary and
natural rocks it is exposed, one ought not to give up so large a portion
of it to childhood, idleness, and apprenticeship.
[Which Cotton thus renders: "Birth though noble, ought not to share
so large a vacancy, and so tedious a course of education." Florio
(1613) makes the passage read as-follows: "Methinks that,
considering the weakness of our life, and seeing the infinite number
of ordinary rocks and natural dangers it is subject unto, we should
not, so soon as we come into the world, allot so large a share
thereof unto unprofitable wantonness in youth, ill-breeding
idleness, and slow-learning prentisage."]