Zeno of Elea

Greek philosopher and mathematician
(c. 495 bc–c. 430 bc), Greek philosopher and mathematician,
whom Aristotle called the inventor of dialectic. He is
especially known for his paradoxes that contributed to the
development of logical and mathematical rigour and that were
insoluble until the development of precise concepts of
continuity and infinity.
Zeno was famous for the paradoxes whereby, in order to
recommend the Parmenidean doctrine of the existence of “the
one” (i.e., indivisible reality), he sought to controvert
the common-sense belief in the existence of “the many”
(i.e., distinguishable qualities and things capable of
motion). Zeno was the son of a certain Teleutagoras and the
pupil and friend of Parmenides. In Plato’s Parmenides,
Socrates, “then very young,” converses with Parmenides and
Zeno, “a man of about forty”; but it may be doubted whether
such a meeting was chronologically possible. Plato’s account
of Zeno’s purpose (Parmenides), however, is presumably
accurate. In reply to those who thought that Parmenides’
theory of the existence of “the one” involved
inconsistencies, Zeno tried to show that the assumption of
the existence of a plurality of things in time and space
carried with it more serious inconsistencies. In early youth
he collected his arguments in a book, which, according to
Plato, was put into circulation without his knowledge.
Zeno made use of three premises: first, that any unit has
magnitude; second, that it is infinitely divisible; and
third, that it is indivisible. Yet he incorporated arguments
for each: for the first premise, he argued that that which,
added to or subtracted from something else, does not
increase or decrease the second unit is nothing; for the
second, that a unit, being one, is homogeneous and that
therefore, if divisible, it cannot be divisible at one point
rather than another; for the third, that a unit, if
divisible, is divisible either into extended minima, which
contradicts the second premise or, because of the first
premise, into nothing. He had in his hands a very powerful
complex argument in the form of a dilemma, one horn of which
supposed indivisibility, the other infinite divisibility,
both leading to a contradiction of the original hypothesis.
His method had great influence and may be summarized as
follows: he continued Parmenides’ abstract, analytic manner
but started from his opponents’ theses and refuted them by
reductio ad absurdum. It was probably the two latter
characteristics which Aristotle had in mind when he called
him the inventor of dialectic.
That Zeno was arguing against actual opponents,
Pythagoreans who believed in a plurality composed of numbers
that were thought of as extended units, is a matter of
controversy. It is not likely that any mathematical
implications received attention in his lifetime. But in fact
the logical problems which his paradoxes raise about a
mathematical continuum are serious, fundamental, and
inadequately solved by Aristotle.