Xenophon

Greek historian
born c. 430 bc, Attica, Greece
died shortly before 350, Attica
Main
Greek historian and philosopher whose numerous surviving
works are valuable for their depiction of late Classical
Greece. His Anabasis (“Upcountry March”) in particular was
highly regarded in antiquity and had a strong influence on
Latin literature.
Life
Xenophon’s life history before 401 is scantily recorded; at
that time, prompted by a Boeotian friend, he left postwar
Athens, joined the Greek mercenary army of the Achaemenian
prince Cyrus the Younger, and became involved in Cyrus’s
rebellion against his brother, the Persian king Artaxerxes
II. After Cyrus’s defeat at Cunaxa (about 50 miles [80 km]
from Babylon in what is now Iraq), the Greeks (later known
as the Ten Thousand) returned to Byzantium via Mesopotamia,
Armenia, and northern Anatolia. Xenophon was one of the men
selected to replace five generals seized and executed by the
Persians. The persistence and skill of the Greek soldiers
were used by proponents of Panhellenism as proof that the
Persians were vulnerable. Initially viewed with hostility by
Sparta (the current Greek hegemonic power), the mercenaries
found employment in the winter of 400–399 with the Thracian
prince Seuthes but then entered Spartan service for a war to
liberate Anatolian Greeks from Persian rule. Unpersuaded by
Seuthes’s offers of land and marriage to his daughter and
evidently disinclined (despite protestations to the
contrary) to return home, Xenophon remained with his
comrades. Although the Anabasis narrative stops at this
point and further details are lacking, he clearly became
closely involved with senior Spartans, notably (after 396)
King Agesilaus II. When a Greek coalition, including Athens,
rebelled against Spartan hegemony in mainland Greece,
Xenophon fought (at Coronea in 394) for Sparta.
Whether his service to Sparta caused or reflected his
formal exile from Athens remains a matter of some dispute,
but exiled he certainly was. The Spartans gave him somewhere
to live at Scillus (across the Alpheus River from Olympia),
a small city in the Triphylian state created after Sparta’s
defeat of Elis in 400. During his years there, Xenophon
served as Sparta’s representative at Olympia, and he sent
his sons to Sparta for their education. Some historians
believe that he also made a trip to Sicily during this
period. He certainly used his mercenary booty to buy land
and erect a small-scale copy of Artemis’s famous temple at
Ephesus. (In Anabasis, Book V, there is a well-known
description of this sacred estate and of the annual
quasi-civic festival celebrated there.) Too prominent to be
unscathed by Sparta’s loss of authority after the Battle of
Leuctra (371), Xenophon was expelled from Scillus and is
said to have settled in Corinth—though here, as elsewhere,
the biographical tradition is of debatable authority, since
the episode does not appear in Xenophon’s own writings. The
claim that his exile was formally repealed is another case
in point, but his Hipparchicus (Cavalry Commander) and
Vectigalia (Ways and Means) suggest that Xenophon had a
sympathetic interest in Athens’s fortunes, and rapprochement
is reflected in his sons’ service in the Athenian cavalry at
the second Battle of Mantinea (362). The death of Xenophon’s
son Gryllus there unleashed such a profusion of eulogies
that Aristotle later gave the subtitle Gryllus to a dialogue
that criticized Isocrates’ views of rhetoric. At the time of
his own death, Xenophon’s standing—as author of a
considerable oeuvre and hero of an adventure nearly five
decades old but ideologically vivid in a Greek world defined
by its relationship to Persia—had never been higher.
Posthumously his place in the canon of ancient authors was
secure; he was a historian, philosopher, and man of action,
a perfect model for the young (a view expressed, for
example, by Dion Chrysostom [Dio Cocceianus]) and an object
of systematic literary imitation by Arrian.
Works » General characteristics
Xenophon produced a large body of work, all of which
survives to the present day. (Indeed, the manuscript
tradition includes Constitution of the Athenians, which is
not by Xenophon.) The great majority of his works were
probably written during the last 15 to 20 years of his life,
but their chronology has not been decisively established.
His output was formally varied—the main categories were long
historical or ostensibly historical narratives, Socratic
texts, and short technical, biographical, or political
treatises—but these had common features, as enumerated
below.
First, Xenophon’s work is characterized by novelty. His
output includes the earliest or earliest surviving examples
of the short nonmedical treatise and of autobiographical
narrative (Anabasis). Other works, although not without
precedent in genre, are unusual in various ways; this is
true of the idiosyncratic contemporary history of Hellenica
(“Greek History”) and the fictive history of Cyropaedia
(“Education of Cyrus”); the second-order, philosophically
nontechnical response to (or exploitation of) Socratic
literature found in Memorabilia, Symposium (“Drinking
Party”), Oeconomicus (“Household Management”), and Apology;
and the novel form of encomiastic biography exemplified by
Agesilaus.
Second, the subject matter reflects Xenophon’s personal
experiences. Anabasis and Cyropaedia flowed from the
adventure of 401–400; the Socratic writings stemmed from
youthful association with a charismatic teacher; Hellenica
arose from a personal take on the politico-military history
of his times; treatises on military command, horsemanship,
household management, and hunting derived from prolonged
personal experience of each; Ways and Means was inspired by
concern about Athens’s finances and political fortunes; and
Hiero may have originated in a visit to Sicily.
Third, Xenophon’s agenda was essentially didactic
(usually with direct or indirect reference to military or
leadership skills), and it was often advanced through the
use of history as a source of material. As a narrative
historian Xenophon has a reputation for inaccuracy and
incompleteness, but he clearly assumed that people and
events from the past were tools for promoting political and
ethical improvement. His ethical system contained little
that jars in modern terms; but in today’s cynical world, the
apparent ingenuousness of its expression strikes some as by
turns bland and irritating. The system’s interconnection
with the gods may challenge readers who either disavow the
divine or are not reconciled to a pagan theological
environment, simply because—in ethical contexts, though not
in specific ritual ones (as illustrated in Anabasis, Book
VII)—divine power in Xenophon is frequently anonymous and
often singular or because he could apparently take a
pragmatic attitude (e.g., posing a question to the Delphic
oracle that was framed to produce the “right” answer). His
contemporaries perhaps saw things differently: for them the
gods were unproblematic (not that everyone thought the same
way about them, but Xenophon’s terms of reference were
readily understood), and his insistence on a moral component
to practical and (broadly) political skills may have been
distinctive.
Fourth, charges of ingenuousness have been partly fueled
by Xenophon’s style. Judged in antiquity to be plain, sweet,
persuasive, graceful, poetic, and a model of Attic purity,
it now strikes some as jejune. A more charitable, and
fairer, description would be that his style is
understated—the range of stylistic figures is modest, and
the finest effects are produced by his simplicity of
expression. Rereading a famous passage in which the Ten
Thousand first glimpse the sea, one is struck by the
disproportion between its remembered impact and its brevity
and indirect approach. Xenophon does not describe seeing the
sea; instead he describes, first, his gradual realization
that a commotion up ahead is caused by the shouts of those
who have seen the sea and, second, the scenes of celebration
as men embrace with tears and laughter, build a huge cairn
of stones, and shower gifts upon their local guide.
Works » Historical themes
Hellenica is a seven-book account of 411–362 in two distinct
(perhaps chronologically widely separated) sections: the
first (Book I and Book II through chapter 3, line 10)
“completes” Thucydides (in largely un-Thucydidean fashion)
by covering the last years of the Peloponnesian War (i.e.,
411–404); the second (the remainder) recounts the long-term
results of Spartan victory, ending with Greece in an
unabated state of uncertainty and confusion after the
indecisive second Battle of Mantinea (362). It is an
idiosyncratic account, notable for omissions, an unexpected
focus, a critical attitude to all parties, and a hostility
to hegemonic aspirations—an intensely personal reaction to
the period rather than an orderly history.
Anabasis, which probably initially circulated
pseudonymously (under the name Themistogenes of Syracuse),
tells the story of the Ten Thousand in a distinctive
version, one in which Xenophon himself plays a central role
in Books III–VII. The work provides a narrative that is
varied and genuinely arresting in its own right, but it also
invites the reader to think about the tactical, strategic,
and leadership skills of those involved. On a political and
ethnocultural front, it expresses a general view of Greek
superiority to “barbarians,” but, although it evokes
Panhellenism (the thesis that Persia was vulnerable to
concerted attack—and should therefore be attacked), it does
not provide unambiguous support for that view.
In Cyropaedia Xenophon investigated leadership by
presenting the life story of Cyrus II, founder of the
Persian Empire. Because the story differs flagrantly from
other sources and the narrative’s pace and texture are
unlike those of ordinary Greek historiography, many analysts
have classed the work as fiction. Story line is certainly
subordinate to didactic agenda, but Xenophon may have drawn
opportunistically on current versions of the Cyrus story
rather than pure imagination. The result is fictive history,
more analogous to Socratic literature than to the Greek
novel (to which it is sometimes pictured as antecedent). In
the Cyropaedia, techniques of military and political
leadership are exposed both through example and through
direct instruction; but Cyrus’s achievement (i.e., absolute
autocracy) is not an unambiguous (or readily transferable)
good, and the final chapter recalls that, Cyrus
notwithstanding, Persia had declined. (As is often the case
in the stories of Classical Greece, barbarian achievements
worthy of respect lie in the past.)
Works » Socratic works
Xenophon’s longest Socratic work is Memorabilia, a four-book
collection whose often charming conversational vignettes
depict a down-to-earth Socrates dispensing practical wisdom
on all manner of topics. The work also refutes the charges
of corruption and religious deviance advanced at Socrates’
trial (also addressed in Apology—a work very different from
Plato’s) by showing someone whose views on religion,
friendship, personal relations, ambition, education,
theology, temperance, and justice were entirely proper.
Symposium narrates a party where conversation,
interspersed with cabaret, shifts continually between
frivolity and seriousness. Personal relationships are a
common theme in the two most substantial sections (the
guests’ quirky accounts of their own most prized assets and
Socrates’ speech on physical and spiritual love) and
elsewhere. The work’s conclusion—a suggestive tableau of
Dionysus and Ariadne has the guests going home full of
libidinous thoughts—typically challenges the earnestness of
what has just preceded, while leaving a distinct, if
tantalizing, feeling that it is not all simply a joke. “What
good men do when having fun is as interesting as their
serious activities,” Xenophon wrote at the beginning of the
work; the beautifully realized, rather brittle comedy of
manners that ensues certainly justifies this assertion.
In Oeconomicus Socrates discusses agriculture and
household management. Leadership (“a harder skill than
agriculture”) is often the real subject. The most famous
section is an account of how the rich Ischomachus trains his
ingenuous young wife for an important role in running their
home. That there was a real Ischomachus who lost his fortune
and whose wife and daughter became involved in a squalid
sexual ménage with Callias (the host of Symposium) poses a
typical Xenophontic puzzle. His Socratic world often
resembles a sanitized version of reality; Xenophon created a
fictive history in which propositions about the pursuit of
virtue—though they derive authority from being rooted in the
past—acquire either a mythical aura or an intriguing
piquancy through the use of a deviant version of that past.
Works » Other writings
Six other works came from Xenophon’s pen. Cynegeticus (“On
Hunting”) offers technical advice on hunting (on foot, with
dogs and nets, the usual prey being a hare); Xenophon sees
the pursuit as a pleasurable and divinely ordained means of
promoting military, intellectual, and moral excellence
(something neither sophists nor politicians can match). De
re equestri (“On Horsemanship”) deals with various aspects
of horse ownership and riding, and Cavalry Commander is a
somewhat unsystematic (but serious) discussion of how to
improve the Athenian cavalry corps. Also Athenocentric is
Ways and Means, a plan to alleviate the city’s financial
problems (and remove excuses for aggressive imperialism) by
paying citizens a dole from taxes on foreign residents and
from the profits generated by using state-owned slaves in
the silver mines.
In Hiero the location is Syracuse (on the east coast of
Sicily), perhaps in allusion to contemporary Syracusan
tyrants. The 5th-century tyrant Hiero bewails the
unpleasantness of his situation, prompting the praise-poet
Simonides to suggest that things could improve if Hiero were
to adopt some recognizably Xenophontic leadership principles
and become a benevolent and much-loved autocrat. There are
shades of Cyropaedia (except that the story does not suggest
that Hiero’s transformation happened) and of the warnings
praise-poets sometimes offered tyrants (except that they
tried to check tyrannical self-confidence, whereas
Xenophon’s Simonides wants both to enhance and to eliminate
it). When defining leadership modes tyrants make good cases.
So do Spartan kings, or at least the “completely good man”
whose virtues are presented through narrative and analysis
in Agesilaus.
Finally, Respublica Lacedaemoniorum (“Constitution of the
Spartans”) celebrates the rational eccentricity of the
Lycurgan system while admitting its failure to maintain
Spartan values—a failure some find perceptibly implicit in
the system itself. In this work are shades of the Cyropaedia
again, and here the reader may see another example of the
slippery nature of the lessons of history.
Assessment
In post-Renaissance Europe Xenophon continued to be highly
valued as long as the valuation by antiquity retained its
authority. His works were widely edited and translated, and
the environment was one in which, for example, the esteem in
which Cyropaedia had been held by Romans such as Scipio
Aemilianus found an echo. More generally, Xenophon’s moral
posture and his conviction that proper instruction, both
practical and moral, could achieve human improvement had an
appeal even in a world of secular enlightenment.
By the 19th century the onset of the critical study of
historical sources, a growing preference for epistemology
over ethics, and the general professionalization of research
on the Classical world did Xenophon no favours. It became
harder to find much relevance in his practical treatises,
and a political philosophy that appeared monarchic rather
than republican was out of tune with the times. He remained
an author commonly read by those learning Greek, but he
ceased to be intellectually fashionable both among academics
and the wider educated public.
In the late 20th century his reputation began to rise
again. Scholars became more interested in early 4th-century
history and increasingly concerned with socioeconomic
structures, social institutions, and gender issues. They
also became more sensitive to the pitfalls of biographical
or quasi-biographical discourse in antiquity. There was a
considerable increase in the quantity and sophistication of
historical work on Persia and Sparta, and war studies
regained its status as a respectable branch of sociocultural
history. All these trends made Xenophon an author of crucial
importance and encouraged more-discriminating reading of his
works.
Xenophon was long characterized as a second-rate
practitioner of other people’s literary trades, but
more-sympathetic study suggests that the artfully simple
style masks a writer of some sophistication. Xenophon was in
the early 21st century starting to be taken seriously as a
distinctive voice on the history, society, and intellectual
attitudes of the later Classical era.
Christopher J. Tuplin