|
Alexis de Tocqueville

|
|
Alexis de Tocqueville
French historian and political writer
born July 29, 1805, Paris, France
died April 16, 1859, Cannes
Main
political scientist, historian, and politician, best known for Democracy
in America, 4 vol. (1835–40), a perceptive analysis of the political and
social system of the United States in the early 19th century.
Early life
Tocqueville was a great-grandson of the statesman Chrétien de
Malesherbes (1721–94), a liberal aristocratic victim of the French
Revolution and a political model for the young Tocqueville. Almost
diminutive in stature, acutely sensitive, and plagued by severe bouts of
anxiety since childhood, he remained close to his parents throughout his
life.
Despite a frail voice in a fragile body, distaste for the daily
demands of parliamentary existence, and long periods of illness and
nervous exhaustion, Tocqueville chose politics as his vocation and
adhered to this choice until he was driven from office. His decision in
favour of a public career was made with some assurance of success. His
father was a loyal royalist prefect and in 1827 was made a peer of
France by Charles X. At that time, young Tocqueville moved easily into
government service as an apprentice magistrate. There he prepared
himself for political life while observing the impending constitutional
confrontation between the Conservatives and the Liberals, with growing
sympathy for the latter. He was strongly influenced by the lectures of
the historian and statesman François Guizot (1787–1874), who asserted
that the decline of aristocratic privilege was historically inevitable.
After the manner of Liberals under the autocratic regime of the restored
Bourbon kings, Tocqueville began to study English history as a model of
political development.
He entered public life in the company of a close friend who was to
become his alter ego—Gustave de Beaumont. Their life histories are
virtual mirror images. Of similar backgrounds and positions, they were
companions in their travels in America, England, and Algeria,
coordinated their writings, and ultimately entered the legislature
together.
The July Revolution of 1830 that put the “citizen king”
Louis-Philippe of Orléans on the throne was a turning point for
Tocqueville. It deepened his conviction that France was moving rapidly
toward complete social equality. Breaking with the older liberal
generation, he no longer compared France with the English constitutional
monarchy but compared it with democratic America. Of more personal
concern, despite his oath of loyalty to the new monarch, his position
had become precarious because of his family ties with the ousted Bourbon
king. He and Beaumont, seeking to escape from their uncomfortable
political situation, asked for and received official permission to study
the uncontroversial problem of prison reforms in America. They also
hoped to return with knowledge of a society that would mark them as
especially fit to help mold France’s political future.
Visit to the United States
Tocqueville and Beaumont spent nine months in the United States during
1831 and 1832, out of which came first their joint book, On the
Penitentiary System in the United States and Its Application in France
(1833); Beaumont’s Marie; or, Slavery in the United States (1835), on
America’s race problems; and the first part of Tocqueville’s Democracy
in America (1835–40). On the basis of observations, readings, and
discussions with a host of eminent Americans, Tocqueville attempted to
penetrate directly to the essentials of American society and to
highlight that aspect—equality of conditions—that was most relevant to
his own philosophy. Tocqueville’s study analyzed the vitality, the
excesses, and the potential future of American democracy. Above all, the
work was infused with his message that a society, properly organized,
could hope to retain liberty in a democratic social order.
The first part of Democracy in America won an immediate reputation
for its author as a political scientist. During this period, probably
the happiest and most optimistic of his life, Tocqueville was named to
the Legion of Honour, the Academy of Moral and Political Sciences
(1838), and the French Academy (1841). With the prizes and royalties
from the book, he even found himself able to rebuild his ancestral
chateau in Normandy. Within a few years his book had been published in
England, Belgium, Germany, Spain, Hungary, Denmark, and Sweden. Although
it was sometimes viewed as having been derived from politically biased
sources, it was soon accorded the status of a classic in the United
States.
In 1836 Tocqueville married Mary Mottely, an Englishwoman.
Tocqueville spent the next four years working on the final portion of
Democracy in America, which was published in 1840. Its composition took
far longer, moved farther afield, and ended far more soberly than
Tocqueville originally had intended. American society slid into the
background, and Tocqueville attempted to complete a picture of the
influence of equality itself on all aspects of modern society. France
increasingly became his principal example, and what he saw there altered
the tone of his work. He observed the curtailment of liberties by the
Liberals, who had come to power in 1830, as well as the growth of state
intervention in economic development. Most depressing to him was the
increased political apathy and acquiescence of his fellow citizens in
this rising paternalism. His chapters on democratic individualism and
centralization in Democracy in America contained a new warning based on
these observations. He argued that a mild, stagnant despotism was the
greatest threat to democracy.
First political career
During this period Tocqueville fulfilled his lifelong ambition to enter
politics. He lost his first bid for the Chamber of Deputies in 1837 but
won election two years later. Eventually, Tocqueville built up an
enormous personal influence in his constituency, winning subsequent
elections by more than 70 percent of the vote and becoming president of
his departmental council (a local representative body). In local
politics his quest for preeminence was completely fulfilled, but his
need for uncompromised dignity and independence deprived him of
influence in the Chamber of Deputies for a much longer time. He was not
able to follow the leadership of others, nor did his oratorical style
win him quick recognition as a leader. As a result, he had no major
legislative accomplishment to his credit during the reign of
Louis-Philippe. His speech prophesying revolution only a few weeks
before it took place in France in February 1848 (part of the wider
Revolutions of 1848 that befell Europe that year) fell on deaf ears. The
biting sketches of friend, foe, and even himself in his Recollections
(1893) reflect his feeling of the general mediocrity of political
leadership before and after 1848.
Revolution of 1848
The Revolution of 1848 brought about a new political situation for
France and for Tocqueville. Having decried apathy as the chief danger
for France, Tocqueville recognized even before the revolution that
France was faced with a politically awakened working class that might
well propel French politics into socialist and revolutionary channels.
Tocqueville considered economic independence as necessary to the
preservation of his own intellectual independence. He thus viewed
pressures of the dependent poor for state welfare and of the unemployed
for state employment as the initial steps to a universal and degrading
dependence on the state by all social classes. Unsympathetic to
revolutionaries and contemptuous of socialists before the revolution,
Tocqueville opposed the demands of the Parisian workers during the June
days of 1848, when their uprising was bloodily suppressed by the
military dictator General Louis Cavaignac, as well as in the debates
over the constitution of 1848. The only intellectual change produced in
Tocqueville by the events of 1848 was a recognition of the strength of
socialist ideas and of the problematic nature of the proprietary
society. Although he had sought to reconcile the aristocracy to liberal
democracy in Democracy in America, he rejected social democracy as it
emerged in 1848 as incompatible with liberal democracy.
Politically, Tocqueville’s own position was dramatically improved by
the February Revolution. His electorate expanded from 700 to 160,000
under universal manhood suffrage. He was elected as a conservative
Republican to the Constituent Assembly by 79 percent of the voters and
again in 1849 by more than 87 percent. Along with Beaumont, he was
nominated to the committee that wrote the constitution of the Second
Republic, and the following year he became vice president of the
Assembly. A government crisis produced by French armed intervention to
restore papal authority in Rome prompted his appointment as minister of
foreign affairs between June and October 1849, during which time he
worked cautiously to preserve the balance of power in Europe and to
prevent France from extending its foreign involvements. His speeches
were more successful and his self-confidence soared, but the results
gave him little more durable satisfaction than those he had attained
during the July monarchy under Louis-Philippe.
Shortly after his dismissal from the Ministry of Foreign Affairs by
President Louis-Napoléon Bonaparte in October 1849, Tocqueville suffered
a physical collapse. After a slow recovery he performed a final service
for the Second French Republic. As reporter for the constitutional
revision committee, he attempted to avert the final confrontation
between the president and the legislature, which ended with an executive
seizure of dictatorial power. Briefly imprisoned for opposing Louis-Napoléon’s
coup d’état on December 2, 1851, Tocqueville was deprived of all
political offices for refusing his oath of loyalty to the new regime.
Thrown back on a small circle of political allies and friends, he felt a
deeper sense of isolation and political pessimism than ever before.
Return to politics
Seeking to reenter politics, he reverted to the strategy of his youthful
success—the publication of a book on the fundamental themes of liberty
and equality. He chose as his subject the French Revolution, and, after
years of research and intermittent illnesses, The Old Regime and the
Revolution appeared in 1856 as the first part of his projected study.
Tocqueville sought to demonstrate the continuity of political behaviour
and attitudes that made postrevolutionary French society as prepared to
accept despotism as that of the old regime. In this final study the
traumatic events of the years 1848–51 were clearly the source of his
emphasis on the durability of centralization and class hostility in
French history. France seemed less the democratic society of the future
he had glimpsed in America than the prisoner of its own past. Against
the pessimism of his analysis of French political tendencies, The Old
Regime reaffirmed the libertarian example of the Anglo-American world.
The acclaim that greeted this study briefly dispelled the gloom of his
last years. Once again a public figure, he made a visit to England in
1857 that culminated in an audience with the prince consort and was the
last public triumph of his life. He returned to his work, but, before he
could finish his study of the Revolution, he collapsed and died.
Reputation
Tocqueville’s reputation in the 19th century reached its high point
during the decade following his death as the great European powers
accommodated themselves to universal suffrage. He died just at the onset
of a revival of liberalism in France. The nine-volume publication of his
works, edited by Beaumont (1860–66), was received as the legacy of a
martyr of liberty. In England his name was invoked during the franchise
reform debates of the 1860s, and in Germany it was linked to
controversies over liberalization and federalization in the years
preceding the empire devised by Otto von Bismarck. After 1870 his
influence began to decline, a process not substantially reversed by
either the posthumous publication of his Recollections in 1893 or that
of his correspondence with his friend, the diplomatist and philosopher
Arthur de Gobineau. By the turn of the century, he was almost forgotten,
and his works, which seemed too abstract and speculative for a
generation that believed only in ascertained knowledge, were generally
regarded as outdated classics. Moreover, Tocqueville’s prediction of
democracy as a vast and uniformly leveling power seemed to have
miscarried by not foreseeing both the extent of the new inequalities and
conflicts produced by industrialization and those produced by European
nationalisms and imperialism. The classless society had failed to appear
in Europe, and America seemed to have become European by becoming
nationalist and imperialist. In France, Tocqueville’s name was too
closely identified with a narrowly defined Liberal tradition, which
rapidly lost influence during the Third Republic. Although his work as
an innovative historian was acknowledged, it is significant that the
revival of his ideas and reputation as a political sociologist owes so
much to American, English, and German scholarship.
The 20th-century totalitarian challenge to the survival of liberal
institutions produced by two world wars and by the Great Depression of
the 1930s fostered a “Tocqueville renaissance.” The outdated facts of
his books seemed less significant than the political philosophy implicit
in his search to preserve liberty in public life and his strategies for
analyzing latent social tendencies. His work was found to display a
wealth of fruitful philosophical and sociological hypotheses. At a
popular level, the renewed upsurge of social democracy in Europe after
1945 combined with the polarization of the Cold War to produce a view of
Tocqueville in the West as an alternative to Marx as a prophet of social
change. Again, as in the late 1850s and 1860s, Tocqueville rose to
heights of popularity, especially in the 1990s in the United States,
where his travels were retraced. It seems certain that Tocqueville will
continue to be invoked as an authority and inspiration by those sharing
his contempt of static authoritarian societies as well as his belief in
the final disappearance of class divisions and in liberty as the
ultimate political value.
Seymour Drescher
|
|

|
DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA
|
Type of work: Essays in political science
Author: Alexis de Tocqueville (1805-1859)
First published: Volume I, 1835; Volume II, 1840
|
Alexis de Tocqueville lived in a time of enormous political change,
when every conceivable variety of political theory flourished. He was
born shortly after the French Revolution had turned itself into the
Empire, and in his lifetime occurred those further changes which
transformed France, at least nominally, into a Republic. His object in
writing Democracy in America was twofold: to write about the new nation
that he so much admired and to establish a new way of examining ideas of
politics. Instead of proceeding from ideas of right and responsibility,
Tocqueville preferred to begin by analyzing social institutions as they
functioned in reality. Instead of working, as Rousseau had worked, from
an arbitrary picture of the beginnings of humanity in a "natural"
condition, Tocqueville preferred to work from what was statistically
observable. Thus, Democracy in America begins with a picture of the
geography of the new continent, its weather, its indigenous tribes, its
economy, and its natural resources. In this respect Democracy in America
is the forerunner of the scientific spirit in the investigation of
social structures.
Much of Democracy in America is concerned with institutions, and the
first of these described by its author is that of the partition of
property. He points out that it is customary in the nations of Europe to
divide property by the laws of primogeniture. The result is that
property remains fixed in extent and in possession; the family, no
matter how changed in each generation, is linked to the wealth and
political power of landed property. The family represents the estate,
the estate the family, and naturally a strong inequality is carried from
one generation to another. The foundations of American culture are to be
found, Tocqueville points out, in the equal partition of land and
fortune. Land is continually broken up into parcels, sold, developed,
and transformed. The accompanying wealth and power is much more fluid
than in societies in which descent really dominates fortune. The
subsidiary effect of equal partition is the access of careers to men who
might in another system be blocked from advancement.
Tocqueville was fascinated by the practice of equality, a phenomenon
rarely encountered in France during his lifetime. His next series of
chapters concerns political equality; he is one of the first great
commentators on the democracy of the township and corporation in early
nineteenth century America. He emphasizes that it is fundamental to
understand the nature of the township, particularly in its New England
tradition. The key to the nature of the American nation, he finds, is
the wide and responsible nature of freedom at the level of municipal
government. This gives the citizen direct voice in his government and
trains him for the representative democracy of the Federal government.
Tocqueville points out that under this form of government, power is
actually concentrated in the hands of the voter; the legislative and
executive branches have no power of their own, but merely represent
those who appoint them. To us this fact is commonplace, but it was a new
idea for the citizens of Europe.
Although much of this work is in praise of American democracy,
Tocqueville makes some important qualifications. His first principle is
that abuse in government occurs when one special interest is served to
the exclusion of all others. This kind of abuse, he remarks, formerly
occurred when the upper classes imposed their will on the lower, when
the military, or feudal, or financial, or even religious values operate
to the exclusion of all others. His great reservation concerning
democracy is that in this form of government a kind of tyranny is also
possible, that of the majority. He states that it is conceivable that
the free institutions of America may be destroyed by forcing all
minorities to give up their freedoms for what is supposedly the good of
the majority. In that case, he concludes, democracy will give way first
to despotism and then to anarchy. Above all things Tocqueville is taken
with equality, and that principle, regardless of the greatest good for
the greatest number, is what animates his opinion.
Democracy in America is of course principally about its great subject,
but there are in it many reminders of a larger view that its author has.
One constant theme of the book is that the Old World must learn from the
New; in fact, the book functions not so much as an independent study of
a unique phenomenon as a study of comparative political science.
Tocqueville suggests that democratic institutions need to be introduced
in France; there will be independence for none, he adds, unless, as in
the American republic, independence is granted for all. With uncommon
clarity he predicts the totalitarian potentialities of the twentieth
century, where unlimited power restricts itself not to a class, but
first to a party, and then to a single man. The famous ending of the
first volume carries this insight to a more elaborate and specific
culmination. There are two nations, Tocqueville says, which will
probably dominate the next century, the United States and Russia. One,
he says, is driven by the desire for power and war, the other by the
desire to increase domestic prosperity. He predicts that there will be
no peace until the aggressiveness of Russia is checked by the
peacefulness of the United States; in his own words, he looks to a
future in which the principle of "servitude" will encounter that of
"freedom."
The second volume of Democracy in America was published after a lapse of
five years. The first volume had established its author as one of the
best political thinkers in Europe. It won for him not only the esteem of
the best minds of the Continent but financial and even political
rewards, so that from the time of its publication Tocqueville was to
take an active part as a member of the French government. The second
volume is concerned not with the basic economic and social
characteristics of America, but with subsidiary questions about the
nature of American culture. He asks, for example, how Americans
cultivate the arts and whether or not eloquence is to be encountered in
the rhetoric of Congress. He covers the progress of science as well as
that of poetry, the position of religious minorities, even the meaning
of public monuments in a democracy. His general conclusion concerning
the arts in America is that they do not flourish as they do in other
political climates, for the arts require an atmosphere of privilege and
an amount of money that a tax-conscious public is quite unlikely to
spend. The useful, he says, is much preferred in a democracy to the
beautiful. The artist becomes an artisan and, the author remarks with
some delicacy, he tends to produce "imperfect commodities" rather than
lasting works of art.
Nevertheless, Tocqueville suggests that a lowering of some standards is
amply compensated by a heightening of others. Particularly in the matter
of foreign policy does he admire the republican sense as well as form of
government. Toward the end of Democracy in America he spends much
thought on the inclinations toward war and peace of different forms of
government. The democratic form, he judges, is predisposed to peace
because of various influences: the rapid growth of personal wealth; the
stake in property; the less material but equally important "gentleness
of heart" which allows the citizens of a democracy a more humane view of
life. Yet, when the democratic government is involved in war, the same
application of ambition and energy that is so marked in commercial life
results often in military success as well. Tocqueville's last thoughts
about the democracy and its army deal with the danger to any society
from its own standing army, and he covers substantially the same ground
on this matter as do the authors of the Federalist papers. Democracy in
America ends with the restatement that despotism may be encountered even
in republics. While democracies can, the author admits, on occasion be
violent and unjust, he believes these occasions are exceptional. They
will be more and more frequent, however, in the proportion that equality
is allowed to lapse. Among the last of Tocqueville's animated
descriptions is that of the "flock of timid and industrious animals" who
have given up their individuality to a strong central government. He
urges a balance between central and decentralized power, the constant
consciousness of equality for all members of the polity.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|