Hippolyte Taine

born
April 21, 1828, Vouziers, Ardennes,
France
died March 5, 1893, Paris
French
thinker, critic, and historian, one of
the most esteemed exponents of
19th-century French Positivism. He
attempted to apply the scientific method
to the study of the humanities.
Early life and career
Taine was born into a professional
middle-class family; his father was a
lawyer. He was educated privately at
home until shortly after his father’s
death; thereafter, he went with his
mother to live in Paris and became an
outstanding pupil at the Collège Bourbon
and then at the highly prestigious École
Normale. He gained his licenceès-lettres
(preliminary degree) in 1848 and began
to study for his agrégation (advanced
degree) in philosophy, one of his
dominant interests. He already held
unorthodox intellectual views. He had
apparently lost his Christian faith by
the age of 15, and his youthful
rationalist attitude led him to admire
the ideas of the Idéologue philosophers
who held that all knowledge must be
based on sense experience, on
observation, and on controlled
experiment; this overriding conviction
guided his later career. He was also
already attracted by the metaphysical
ideas of Hegel and Spinoza, which
inspired in him a desire to find a total
explanation of the causal forces of life
and the universe.
In
contrast to these views, his new
teachers of philosophy in Paris held the
prevailing philosophical doctrine of
eclecticism; consequently—and not
without creating some scandal in
academic circles—Taine’s agrégation jury
failed him in 1851. He then taught for
brief periods at Nevers and Poitiers but
in 1852 applied for leave of absence.
Returning to Paris, he devoted himself
to preparing his two dissertations for
the doctorate in literature: De Personis
Platonicis (“Concerning Plato’s
Characters”) and his first well-known
work, a study of La Fontaine (1853;
revised and published in 1861 as La
Fontaine et ses fables [“La Fontaine and
His Fables”]).
He
gained his doctoral degree in May 1853
and began an essay on Livy, Essai sur
Tite-Live (1856), which, despite further
criticism of his philosophical outlook,
won a prize from the Académie Française.
During this period he was also attending
lectures in science and gathering the
knowledge of physiology that he utilized
later in his work on psychology.
Reluctant to return to full-time
teaching, he lived by private tutoring
and as a man of letters. Even a holiday
in 1854, necessitated by ill health, was
turned to advantage: in 1855 he
published a literary guidebook based on
his travels, Voyage aux eaux des
Pyrénées (“Voyage to the Waters of the
Pyrenees”).
Attack on eclecticism
More important for his own development,
he contributed frequent literary and
historical articles to such leading
journals as the Revue des Deux Mondes,
the Revue de l’Instruction Publique, and
the Journal des Débats, articles that
provided the basis for three books
further enhancing the reputation he had
gained by his works on La Fontaine and
Livy. These were Les Philosophes
français du XIXe siècle (1857; “The
French Philosophers of the 19th
Century”), a critical polemic against
the prevailing eclectic philosophy of
Victor Cousin and his group, which also
provides in its later chapters a lucid
exposition of his own Positivist theory
of knowledge; a first collection of
Essais de critique et d’histoire (1858;
“Essays of Criticism and History”); and
his notable Histoire de la littérature
anglaise, 4 vols. (1863–64; History of
English Literature, 1871).
The
celebrated “Introduction” to the
Histoire gives a succinct statement of
Taine’s approach to literary and
cultural history and a basic text for
the understanding of his scientific
attitude to literary criticism. The same
great causal factors underlie any
cultural artifact of a given age and
society, he claims. By studying the
literary documents one may understand
the psychology of their author, and
this, complemented by scrutiny of the
facts of his life and personality,
illuminates the “faculté maîtresse,” the
predominant characteristic that
determines his work; this, in turn, can
then be “explained” by reference to
three great conditioning facts, “la
race,” “le milieu,” and “le moment”;
i.e., the writer’s inherited
personality, his social, political, and
geographical background, and the
historical situation in which he writes.
It is evident that Taine’s interest here
is less in literature itself than in
historical causation and psychology, and
his method may well be thought to have
encouraged in his admirers an excessive
preoccupation with biography and
literary history at the expense of
critical judgment, though Taine’s own
abilities as a critic were considerable.
Throughout the 1860s Taine continued
indefatigably his researches and his
writing. Even his travels (to England,
Italy, Germany, and The Netherlands)
were utilized to gather notes for future
work—for example, his closely observed
if simplifying Notes sur l’Angleterre
(1872; Notes on England, 1872); and even
his life in Paris led to his Notes sur
Paris: Vie et opinions de M.
Frédéric-Thomas Graindorge (1867; Notes
and Opinions of Mr.
Frédérick-Graindorge, 1875), perhaps the
most personal and entertaining of his
books.
In
1864, by a happy decision of Napoleon
III, he was appointed to succeed
Viollet-le-Duc, the architect, as
professor of aesthetics and of the
history of art at the École des
Beaux-Arts in Paris, where he lectured
for 20 years. The lecture courses, which
he eventually published, include
Philosophie de l’art (1865; The
Philosophy of Art, 1865), De l’idéal
dans l’art (1867; “On the Ideal in
Art”), and those on the philosophy of
art in Italy (1866), The Netherlands
(1868), and Greece (1869).
This
post also gave him a security that
favoured his more protracted scientific
studies and helped make the later 1860s
a happy and fertile period in his life.
He published, in addition to the works
named, his second volume of essays,
Nouveaux essais de critique et
d’histoire (1865; “New Essays of
Criticism and History”), including his
perceptive articles on Racine, Balzac,
and Stendhal (whose psychological acuity
he was one of the first to admire). In
1868 he married Mlle Denuelle, the
daughter of a well-known architect and
artist, by whom he had a son and a
daughter.
Publication of De l’intelligence
In 1870 he published the two volumes of
De l’intelligence (On Intelligence,
1871), a major work in the discipline of
psychology, which had interested him
since his youth. His devotion to science
is most fully illustrated here; he
opposes the speculative and
introspective approach of the eclectics
and outlines a scientific methodology
for the study of human personality that
established him, alongside thinkers such
as Théodule Ribot and Pierre Janet, as a
founder of empirical psychology. Though
much of the work is now outdated, in its
day it helped to modify methods of
research by its emphasis on experiment,
the search for causes, the study of
pathological cases, and the
physiological basis of personality. It
also intensified opposition to his
ideas, and he was angrily accused of
holding a strictly determinist and
materialist view of man—not altogether
unfairly, even though he claimed to
reject materialism and argued that moral
responsibility was compatible with
determinism as he conceived it.
The
work also develops his long-standing
attempt to fuse Positivism and Hegelian
Idealism and to provide a method for a
scientific metaphysics. Through such a
metaphysics, he maintained, the final
causes of life itself might be
discovered; its insights inspired him to
an exalted pantheistic trust in nature
that is movingly expressed in essays on
Marcus Aurelius (in Nouveaux essais) and
Iphigeneia (in Derniers essais).
Germany’s invasion and defeat of France
in 1870–71 had a profound impact upon
Taine (already prepared in his mind by a
visit in 1869 that had disabused him of
his earlier enthusiasm for German
civilization). The French defeat, in his
view, sprang from a deep national
sickness, and he determined to devote
his final years to examining its causes.
A shift of interest toward politics is
illustrated by a brochure of 1872 on the
problems and effects of universal
suffrage, but, above all, his approach
was historical: to seek the sources of
the political instability that he held
responsible for his country’s plight.
Historical theories
This major reorientation of concern led
to his great historical work, Les
Origines de la France contemporaine
(“The Origins of Contemporary France”),
a monumental analysis, claiming
scientific objectivity (although its
factual and interpretative reliability
have been challenged). It seeks to show
that France’s primary fault lay in
excessive centralization, originating
during the ancien régime, and
intensified by the French Revolution,
about which he shares and develops
Edmund Burke’s hostile view. Taine
asserted that far from promoting
liberty, as most of the French believe,
the Revolution merely transferred
absolute power to even more illiberal
hands. A first volume, on L’Ancien
Régime (“The Old Regime”), appeared in
1876, followed by three volumes on the
Revolution (1878–85). In 1878 he was
also elected to the Académie Française.
To have
more time for his self-appointed task he
withdrew increasingly from Paris and
after 1883 even resigned his
professorship. Only one volume of Le
Régime moderne (“The Modern Regime”),
however, was published in his lifetime
(1891), the second volume coming out in
November 1893. The entire work was
reissued in 1899. There also appeared
after his death his Derniers essais de
critique et d’histoire (1894; “Last
Essays of Criticism and History”) and an
unfinished autobiographical and
psychological novel, written about 1861,
Étienne Mayran (1910). He died in Paris
in 1893 and was buried at
Menthon-Saint-Bernard.
Taine
achieved fame over a wide range of
disciplines—as a leading French thinker,
as a literary and art critic, and as a
historian. His greatest influence upon
his contemporaries, however, was as an
intellectual leader, one of the most
esteemed exponents of 19th-century
French positivism, the cult of science
in its most devoted, high-minded, and
rational form. His work represents a
reaction against excessive emotionalism
and spiritualist philosophy and was
unified by his attempt to apply the
scientific method to the study of
literature and art, psychology, cultural
history, and to ethics and metaphysics.
Taine’s ideas helped provide a
theoretical basis for the literary
movement of naturalism; the novel, he
argued, should contribute to the
scientific understanding of human
nature, revealing, like the new
scientific psychology he advocated, the
physiological and psychological
determinants of human behaviour.
Donald Geoffrey Charlton